Skip to main content

EDITORIAL article

Front. Psychol., 22 August 2014
Sec. Consciousness Research
This article is part of the Research Topic Olfactory Consciousness across Disciplines View all 14 articles

Olfactory consciousness across disciplines

  • 1Philosophy Program, Graduate Center, City University of New York, New York, NY, USA
  • 2The Department of Cognitive and Brain Science, Ben-Gurion University of the Negev, Beer-Sheva, Israel

Although vision is the de facto model system of consciousness research, studying olfactory consciousness has its own advantages, as this collection of articles emphatically demonstrates. One advantage of olfaction is its computational and phenomenological simplicity, which facilitates the identification of basic principles. Other researchers study olfactory consciousness not because of its simplicity, but because of its unique features. Together, olfaction's simplicity and its distinctiveness make it an ideal system for testing theories of consciousness. In this research topic, the results of recent research into olfactory consciousness are presented.

Simplicity of Olfaction

The relative simplicity of olfaction makes it a natural starting point for investigating perception. Olfaction has been used as a theoretical launchpad at least since 1764, when Reid wrote that “beginning with the simplest, and proceeding by very cautious steps to the most complex” (Reid, 1764) is the best strategy to understand the human mind. Following his own advice, Reid begins his Inquiry into the Human Mind with a chapter on olfaction. Quilty-Dunn's article explores Reid's account of odors as secondary qualities and argues for the relevance of Reid's theory for contemporary debates (Quilty-Dunn, 2013). The simplicity of the olfactory system is also what prompts Merrick and her colleagues to suggest in their review article that olfaction can be used as “the gateway to the neural correlates of consciousness” (Merrick et al., 2014).

Keller, in his contribution, takes advantage of the relative simplicity of the olfactory system in his attempt to identify the function of conscious information processing. Visual perception performs a myriad of functions. This versatility of vision makes the identification of the subset of vision's functions that require consciousness challenging. This problem, Keller argues, is much more tractable in olfaction, which is a specialized sense with circumscribed functions (Keller, 2014).

Unique Features of Olfaction

The many unique features that distinguish olfactory consciousness from other forms of perceptual consciousness are reviewed here with a focus on cognition by Stevenson and Attuquayefio (2013), and with a focus on neuroanatomy and neurodynamics by Merrick et al. (2014).

One striking feature of olfaction is the difficulty associated with olfactory imagery. It is easier to imagine seeing something than it is to imagine smelling it. Whether it is at all possible to voluntarily experiencing smells in the absence of the physical stimulus is the topic of ongoing research. Stevenson and Attuquayefio review the relevant literature and conclude that olfactory imagery is not possible (Stevenson and Attuquayefio, 2013). In contrast, Arshamian and Larsson argue that some individuals are capable of imagining smells (Arshamian and Larsson, 2014). Young (2014) sides with Arshamian and Larsson. According to Young, the fact that experiences during olfactory imagery have a qualitative character shows that olfactory awareness is always qualitatively conscious. In addition, he surveys evidence that olfactory sensory states can have a qualitative character in the absence of awareness.

Another peculiarity of olfaction is that it is unclear what, if anything, smells represent. Lycan, in his article, argues that olfaction does represent (Lycan, 2014). Lycan elaborates his previous proposal that a smell represents a miasma in the air (Lycan, 1996, 2000). In contrast, Batty, in her contribution, defends her proposal that there are no represented objects in olfaction (Batty, 2014). Instead, according to Batty, smells represent olfactory properties as occurring abstractly in our vicinity. Batty argues that, because there are no objects in olfaction, there can also be no object-failure, and therefore no olfactory illusions. A third view on the topic of olfactory objects is presented by Castro and Seeley (2014), who argue that the objects of olfactory perception are not objective physical entities, but affective categories.

The unique temporal structure of olfactory perception serves as the focus of Olofsson's review (Olofsson, 2014). Olfaction has a much lower temporal resolution than vision and audition. Olofsson reviews the literature on measurements of the time it takes subjects to respond to olfactory stimuli and proposes a cascade model of olfactory perception according to which we first detect an odor, then identify it, and finally determine odor valence and edibility.

Theory Testing in Olfaction

Some contributions to this research topic show that the simplicity of olfaction and its distinctiveness make it a useful system for testing theories of consciousness. Quality-space theory explains the nature of the mental qualities distinctive of perceptual states by appeal to their role in perceiving rather than by appeal to conscious subjective reports (Rosenthal, 2010). Here, Young and his coauthors show that quality-space theory, which is typically described in terms of color qualities, also applies to odor qualities (Young et al., 2014).

A second theory that is discussed here is the global workspace theory, according to which widespread broadcasting of information in the brain is necessary for consciousness (Baars, 2005). It has previously been suggested that the global workspace theory fails to explain conscious odor perception (Young, 2012). Here, Baars defends the global workspace theory against this suggestion and argues that the theory is applicable to olfactory consciousness (Baars, 2013). The widespread broadcasting of information that is central for the global workspace theory may be accomplished through synchronous gamma oscillations. Mori and colleagues review what is known about these oscillations in olfactory networks (Mori et al., 2013). They concluded that in olfaction the olfactory bulb plays the role that the thalamus plays for visual consciousness.

Outlook

Olfactory Consciousness across Disciplines demonstrates that the simplicity and distinctiveness of olfactory consciousness make it an ideal system for theory testing. Theories of consciousness that aspire to be applicable to all modalities have to be consistent with these results. This research topic provides the resources for testing theories of consciousness in olfaction and offers some examples. We hope that this will enable and encourage a more systematic investigation of olfactory consciousness.

Conflict of Interest Statement

The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

References

Arshamian, A., and Larsson, M. (2014). Same same but different: the case of olfactory imagery. Front. Psychol. 5:34. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00034

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Baars, B. J. (2005). Global workspace theory of consciousness: toward a cognitive neuroscience of human experience. Prog. Brain Res. 150, 45–53. doi: 10.1016/S0079-6123(05)50004-9

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Baars, B. J. (2013). Multiple sources of conscious odor integration and propagation in olfactory cortex. Front. Psychol. 4:930. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00930

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Batty, C. (2014). The illusion confusion. Front. Psychol. 5:231. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00231

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Castro, J. B., and Seeley, W. P. (2014). Olfaction, valuation, and action: reorienting perception. Front. Psychol. 5:299. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00299

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Keller, A. (2014). The evolutionary function of conscious information processing is revealed by its task-dependency in the olfactory system. Front. Psychol. 5:62. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00062

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Lycan, W. G. (1996). Consciousness and Experience. Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books/MIT Press.

Lycan, W. G. (2000). “The slighting of smell,” in Of Minds and Molecules: New Philosophical Perspectives on Chemistry, eds N. Bhushan and S. Rosenfeld (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 273–289.

Lycan, W. G. (2014). The intentionality of smell. Front. Psychol. 5:436. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00436

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Merrick, C., Godwin, C. A., Geisler, M. W., and Morsella, E. (2014). The olfactory system as the gateway to the neural correlates of consciousness. Front. Psychol. 4:1011. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.01011

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Mori, K., Manabe, H., Narikiyo, K., and Onisawa, N. (2013). Olfactory consciousness and gamma oscillation couplings across the olfactory bulb, olfactory cortex, and orbitofrontal cortex. Front. Psychol. 4:743. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00743

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Olofsson, J. K. (2014). Time to smell: a cascade model of human olfactory perception based on response-time (RT) measurement. Front. Psychol. 5:33. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00033

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Quilty-Dunn, J. (2013). Reid on olfaction and secondary qualities. Front. Psychol. 4:974. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00974

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Reid, T. (1764). Inquiry into the Human Mind on the Principles of Common Sense, ed D. Brookes, 1997. University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press.

Rosenthal, D. M. (2010). How to think about mental qualities. Philos. Issues 20, 368–393. doi: 10.1111/j.1533-6077.2010.00190.x

CrossRef Full Text

Stevenson, R. J., and Attuquayefio, T. (2013). Human olfactory consciousness and cognition: its unusual features may not result from unusual functions but from limited neocortical processing resources. Front. Psychol. 4:819. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00819

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Young, B. D. (2012). Stinking consciousness! J. Conscious. Studies 19, 223–243.

Young, B. D. (2014). Smelling phenomenal. Front. Psychol. 5:713. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00713

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Young, B. D., Keller, A., and Rosenthal, D. M. (2014). Qualtiy space theory in olfaction. Front. Psychol. 5:1. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00001

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Keywords: olfaction, smell, consciousness, theories of consciousness, perceptual consciousness

Citation: Keller A and Young BD (2014) Olfactory consciousness across disciplines. Front. Psychol. 5:931. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00931

Received: 18 July 2014; Accepted: 05 August 2014;
Published online: 22 August 2014.

Edited and reviewed by: Anil K. Seth, University of Sussex, UK

Copyright © 2014 Keller and Young. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) or licensor are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: ben@psychosyntax.com

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.