Skip to main content

OPINION article

Front. Psychol., 28 April 2015
Sec. Cognition
This article is part of the Research Topic Music Cognition View all 8 articles

Origin of music and embodied cognition

  • Department of Psychology, Northeastern University, Boston, MA, USA

Mystery of Music

Music is a poorly understood ability. Its strong power over humans, its origin and cognitive function, have been a mystery for a long time. Aristotle (1995) listed the power of music among the great unsolved problems. Darwin wrote (1871) that musical ability “must be ranked amongst the most mysterious with which (man) is endowed.” Nature published a series of essays on music (Editorial, 2008). The authors of these essays agreed that “none… has yet been able to answer the fundamental question: why does music have such power over us?” (Ball, 2008).

In this article I advocate a hypothesis that music has a specific cognitive function to embody abstract thoughts. This embodiment proceeds through musical emotions, special types of emotions that we may experience when listening to music and that connect abstract thoughts and mental representations to instinctual drives. The embodiment of abstract thoughts through music is a unique contribution of this article.

Aesthetic Emotions and the Knowledge Instinct

According to a theory of drives and emotions developed by Grossberg and Levine (1987), instinctual drives are neural mechanisms similar to internal sensors in the mind-body. They measure vital bodily parameters and indicate to the organism their deviations from safe ranges. Emotional neural signals connect these instinctual indications to decision-making brain-mind regions (Grossberg and Levine, 1987; Grossberg, 1988). The emotions felt are associated with these neural signals. For example, a bodily sensor-like mechanism measures sugar level in the blood and indicates when it is below a safe range. This generates emotional neural signals, which are felt as hunger and drive decision-making mechanisms to look for food. Instincts and emotions are the mechanisms of embodiment.

This theory of drives and emotions has been extended to the knowledge instinct (KI) and aesthetic emotions (Perlovsky, 2001, 2006, 2007, 2014a,b; Perlovsky and Kozma, 2007; Mayorga and Perlovsky, 2008; Perlovsky et al., 2011). KI measures similarities between representations and top-down signals, or more generally between bottom-up and top-down signals. KI drives the development of mental representations in correspondence with experience throughout the hierarchy. Neural circuits involved in KI are discussed in Levine and Perlovsky (2008). Satisfaction or dissatisfaction of KI is indicated by aesthetic emotions. The existence of these special emotions related to knowledge were first discussed by Kant (1790), and have been experimentally demonstrated in Perlovsky et al. (2010). Aesthetic emotions embody knowledge.

Mental Hierarchy

Knowledge is stored in the brain's mental representations, which are organized in an approximate hierarchy from raw sensory percepts at the “bottom” to objects, to situations, to abstract thoughts, and to representations unifying life experience near the “top” of the mental hierarchy (Perlovsky, 2001, 2006; Perlovsky et al., 2011). Near the bottom of the hierarchy the knowledge is embodied in direct experience. “Higher up” representations of abstract knowledge cannot be embodied in direct experience, because abstract knowledge does not exist in the world “ready-made.” These representations are learned from personal experience under the guidance of language (Perlovsky, 2013b). Abstract knowledge exists in language, where it has been created during millennia of cultural evolution. Children learn knowledge at an early age through language; this is possible because real life experience is not needed. This difference between language and cognitive representations makes it possible for children to speak without “real” understanding.

Whereas language representations refer only to facts in language, cognitive representations refer to facts in the real world. Language representations become crisp and conscious in a child's mind by the age of 5 or 7. Cognitive representations, conversely, remain vague and less conscious (Perlovsky, 2013c). To appreciate this, one could imagine a familiar object with eyes closed; the imagination would be much more vague than the perception of the same object with opened eyes. Imaginations are neural projections from cognitive representations to the visual cortex (Grossberg, 1988); so vagueness of imaginations demonstrates vagueness of cognitive representations (Bar et al., 2006; Perlovsky, 2006, 2009). At higher levels in the mental hierarchy, abstract cognitive representations are even more vague and less conscious than language ability to clearly discuss these concepts. This is confirmed in brain imaging experiments (Binder et al., 2005): words for concrete objects stimulate cognitive brain areas in both hemispheres, whereas abstract words stimulate only language brain areas in the left hemisphere.

Therefore, abstract knowledge may remain as disembodied words, disconnected from the world and any emotions. To understand a concept, its cognitive representation must be developed and emotionally connected to the world, to instincts, and to life. Nonhuman animals have only embodied experience; instincts and emotions permeate their every move. But humans possess language, which makes abstract knowledge possible. The price for this ability is the differentiation of our psychic life. Language knowledge does not become automatically embodied and whole with cognition and emotion. Our psychic life is split. The human psyche is not as harmonious as the psyche of animals. Nietzsche (1876/1997) described our differentiated predicament as follows: “human is a dissonance.” Our psyche is not unified.

Cognitive Dissonance and Emergence of Music

At lower levels KI acts automatically: sensory-motor experiences are directly embodied. But at higher levels abstract knowledge is called abstract exactly because it does not exist pre-formed in the world, it is created through the interaction of the world and the mind. But cognitive dissonance (CD), a mechanism opposite to KI, might interfere at higher levels. CD is a discomfort caused by holding conflicting cognitions (Festinger, 1957; Cooper, 2007; Harmon-Jones et al., 2009). This discomfort is usually resolved by devaluing or discarding the conflicting cognition. This discarding often occurs below the level of consciousness; it is fast and momentary (Jarcho et al., 2011). It is also known that the majority of new knowledge originates through the differentiation of previous knowledge, which is the mechanism for several broad empirical laws: Zipf's law, the power law, Pareto law emerge when new entities (or usage) evolve from pre-existing ones (Simonton, 2000; Newman, 2005; Novak, 2010). Therefore, almost all knowledge contradicts other knowledge to some extent. According to CD theory, any knowledge should be discarded before its usefulness becomes established (Perlovsky, 2013a).

As language began emerging, every word brought new knowledge. However, CD should have interfered with this process. Before the usefulness of new knowledge could be established, it should have been discarded along with language (Perlovsky, 2013a). To overcome CD and enable the evolution of language and knowledge, a word should “grab attention” preconsciously. This is the purpose of prosody, or the melody of language sounds (Perlovsky, 2013b). This same mechanism is alive and well today. Over millions of years many musical and prosodial emotions have evolved and have been culturally inherited by everyone. Yet the diversity of culture is “too much” for some people, leading to new knowledge often being discarded in school and later. Recall that Einstein never received a Nobel Prize for Theory of Relativity. The emotions of language prosody embody the meanings of language and connect sounds to cognitive meanings in everyday conversations as well as in science (experimental evidence is discussed below). While language evolved toward more semantic and less emotional sounds, emotionality of voice, inherited from our animal past, evolved toward stronger emotions, to songs and music. And today song lyrics may affect us stronger than the same text without music.

Experimental Confirmations

Our hypothesis suggests that music evolved to connect abstract thoughts and KI, to embody abstract knowledge. This hypothesis has been confirmed experimentally. In Aronson and Carlsmith (1963) children devalued a toy if they could not play with it. The desire “to have” contradicts the inability “to attain”; this creates CD, which is resolved by discarding the contradiction. This experiment repeated many times (Cooper, 2007) was first described in Aesop's Fable 2500 years ago: the fox unable to attain the grape devalues a contradictory cognition by stating: “the grape is sour.”

Does music help in overcoming CD? Masataka and Perlovsky (2012a,b) have reproduced the above experiment with music in the background and observed that the toy is not devalued. Another experiment demonstrated that academic test performance may improve while listening to music. Perlovsky et al. (2013) demonstrated (1) that students allocate less time to more difficult and stressful tests (as expected from CD theory), and (2) with music in the background students can tolerate stress, allocate more time to stressful tests, and improve grades. These experiments confirmed the hypothesis that music helps in overcoming CD. It is likely that music emerged and evolved for a fundamental cognitive function: music makes the accumulation of knowledge and human evolution possible.

Musical Emotions

For thousands of years philosophers and psychologists wondered about the origin of dissonances and consonances. Masataka and Perlovsky (2013) demonstrated that consonant music helps “everyday” decision-making in the presence of cognitive interfering evidence, whereas dissonant music increases interference effects. Is music limited to a few emotions, or does every musical phrase evoke a different shade of emotion? Researchers take opposite sides of this issue (Scherer, 2004; Cross and Morley, 2008; Juslin and Västfjäll, 2008; Zentner et al., 2008; Koelsch, 2011; Juslin, 2013). As reviewed in Perlovsky (2012a,b), this does not affect the main argument of this paper for embodiment of abstract concepts through music.

How can multiplicity of emotions be explained and justified from a cognitive and evolutionary standpoint, and why has this ability emerged? The proposed hypothesis relating music to CD suggests the following explanation. CD produces a variety of emotional discomforts, different emotions for every combination of knowledge—in other words, a huge number of emotions. Most of these emotions are barely noticed because they lie below the level of consciousness, and in these unconscious states they produce disincentives for knowledge. Music helps to overcome these emotional discomforts by developing a huge number of conscious musical emotions. The mind being conscious of the multiplicity of emotions can bring into consciousness emotions of CD, and thus be prepared to tolerate them. We enjoy even sad and difficult musical emotions for their positive effect of overcoming difficult CD. Possibly this explains the mysterious enjoyment of sad music: it helps us to overcome CD of life's unavoidable disappointments, including the ultimate one, the knowledge of our finiteness in the material world.

Life is full of rhythms: heartbeat, respiration, day and night, and multiple other rhythms. Rhythms in music remind us that we are alive and yet most animals do not react to rhythms. Melody, harmony, and other musical devices produce complex, uniquely human musical emotions—they are related to knowledge and therefore are aesthetic emotions (Perlovsky et al., 2010; Bonniot-Cabanac et al., 2012). They expand KI toward a differentiated instinct sensitive not only to unifying knowledge and the world, but also to unifying multiplicity of contradictions among various aspects of knowledge. While CD split our psyche into differentiated knowledge, KI and music unify our psyche. Musical emotions embody abstract knowledge and unify our mental life, language and body.

These are the reasons why music affects us so strongly. Music connects thinking and intuition to the world. Our spiritual life is embodied through music. Uniquely human refined musical emotions embody our abstract thoughts from the everyday to the most exalted experience. Our highest mental representations near the top of the mental hierarchy attempt to unify our entire life experience. We perceive them as the meaning of life; their cognitive representations are vague but their feelings are strong, we feel them as emotions of the beautiful (Perlovsky, 2010a,b). These representations cannot be matched to anything “objectively existing” in the world outside of our brain-mind. Their deep meanings have been created in cultural evolution. Every individual human being receives this cultural knowledge through language. However, this cultural wisdom is not received in an embodied form. It might remain as meaningless disembodied text in books. It is up to everyone's personal effort to create an embodied meaning of life from one's own life experience. Music helps us to embody the meaning of life. The beautiful and sublime, art and religious experience, emotions that embody the meaning of life, as well as the highest spiritual experiences are all embodied through music.

Conflict of Interest Statement

The author declares that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Acknowledgments

I am thankful to the editor and reviewers.

References

Aristotle. (1995). “Problems,” in The Complete Works. The Revised Oxford Translation ed J. Barnes (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press), XIX, 29.

Aronson, E., and Carlsmith, J. M. (1963). Effect of the severity of threat on the devaluation of forbidden behavior. J. Abnorm. Soc. Psychol. 66, 584–588. doi: 10.1037/h0039901

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ball, P. (2008). Facing the music. Nature 453, 160–162. doi: 10.1038/453160a

PubMed Abstract | Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bar, M., Kassam, K. S., Ghuman, A. S., Boshyan, J., Schmid, A. M., Dale, A. M., et al. (2006). Top-down facilitation of visual recognition. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 103, 449–454. doi: 10.1073/pnas.0507062103

PubMed Abstract | Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Binder, J. R., Westbury, C. F., McKiernan, K. A., Possing, E. T., and Medler, D. A. (2005). Distinct brain systems for processing concrete and abstract concepts. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 17, 1–13. doi: 10.1162/0898929054021102

PubMed Abstract | Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bonniot-Cabanac, M.-C., Cabanac, M., Fontanari, F., and Perlovsky, L. I. (2012). Instrumentali-zing cognitive dissonance emotions. Psychology 3, 1018–1026. doi: 10.4236/psych.2012.312153

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Cooper, J. (2007). Cognitive Dissonance: 50 Years of a Classic Theory. Los Angeles, CA: Sage.

Cross, I., and Morley, I. (2008). “The evolution of music: theories, definitions and the nature of the evidence,” in Communicative Musicality, eds S. Malloch and C. Trevarthen (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 61–82.

Darwin, C. R. (1871). The Descent of Man, and Selection in Relation to Sex. London: John Murray.

Editorial. (2008). Bountiful noise. Nature 453:134. doi: 10.1038/453134a

PubMed Abstract | Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Festinger, L. (1957). A Theory of Cognitive Dissonance. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

Google Scholar

Grossberg, S. (1988). Neural Networks and Natural Intelligence. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Google Scholar

Grossberg, S., and Levine, D. (1987). Neural dynamics of attentionally modulated Pavlovian conditioning: blocking, interstimulus interval, and secondary reinforcement. Appl. Opt. 26, 5015–5030. doi: 10.1364/AO.26.005015

PubMed Abstract | Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Harmon-Jones, E., Amodio, D. M., and Harmon-Jones, C. (2009). “Action-based model of dissonance: a review, integration, and expansion of conceptions of cognitive conflict,” in Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, 41, ed M. P. Zanna (Burlington: Academic Press), 119–166.

Jarcho, J. M., Berkman, E. T., and Lieberman, M. D. (2011). The neural basis of rationalization: cognitive dissonance reduction during decision-making. Soc. Cogn. Affect. Neurosci. 6, 460–467. doi: 10.1093/scan/nsq054

PubMed Abstract | Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Juslin, P. N. (2013). From everyday emotions to aesthetic emotions: towards a unified theory of musical emotions. Phys. Life Rev. 10, 235–266. doi: 10.1016/j.plrev.2013.05.008

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Juslin, P. N., and Västfjäll, D. (2008). Emotional responses to music: the Need to consider underlying mechanisms. Behav. Brain Sci. 31, 559–575. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X08005293

PubMed Abstract | Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kant, I. (1790). The Critique of Judgment. J.H. Bernard Translator. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books.

Koelsch, S. (2011). Towards a neural basis of processing musical semantics. Phys. Life Rev. 8, 89–105. doi: 10.1016/j.plrev.2011.04.004

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Levine, D. S., and Perlovsky, L. I. (2008). Neuroscientific insights on biblical myths: simplifying heuristics versus careful thinking: scientific analysis of millennial spiritual issues. Zygon J. Sci. Relig. 43, 797–821. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9744.2008.00961.x

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Masataka, N., and Perlovsky, L. I. (2012a). Music can reduce cognitive dissonance. Nat. Prec.

Google Scholar

Masataka, N., and Perlovsky, L. I. (2012b). The efficacy of musical emotions provoked by Mozart's music for the reconciliation of cognitive dissonance. Sci. Rep. 2:694. doi: 10.1038/srep00694

PubMed Abstract | Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Masataka, N., and Perlovsky, L. I. (2013). Cognitive interference can be mitigated by consonant music and facilitated by dissonant music. Sci. Rep. 3:2028. doi: 10.1038/srep02028

PubMed Abstract | Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Mayorga, R., and Perlovsky, L. I. (eds.). (2008). Sapient Systems. London: Springer.

Google Scholar

Newman, M. E. J. (2005). Power laws, Pareto distributions and Zipf's law. Contemp. Phys. 46, 323–351. doi: 10.1080/00107510500052444

PubMed Abstract | Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Nietzsche, F. (1876/1997). Untimely Meditations. Tr. R. J. Hollingdale. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Novak, J. D. (2010). Learning, creating, and using knowledge: concept maps as facilitative tools in schools and corporations. J. Learn. Knowl. Soc. 6, 21–30.

Google Scholar

Perlovsky, L. I. (2001). Neural Networks and Intellect: Using Model-Based Concepts. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Perlovsky, L. I. (2006). Toward physics of the mind: concepts, emotions, consciousness, and symbols. Phys. Life Rev. 3, 22–55. doi: 10.1016/j.plrev.2005.11.003

PubMed Abstract | Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Perlovsky, L. I. (2007). “Neural dynamic logic of consciousness: the knowledge instinct,” in Neurodynamics of Higher-Level Cognition and Consciousness, eds L. I. Perlovsky and R. Kozma (Heidelberg: Springer Verlag), 73–108.

Perlovsky, L. I. (2009). ‘Vague-to-crisp’ neural mechanism of perception. IEEE Trans. Neural Netw. 20, 1363–1367. doi: 10.1109/TNN.2009.2025501

PubMed Abstract | Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Perlovsky, L. I. (2010a). Beauty and Art. Cognitive Function, Evolution, and Mathematical Models of the Mind. WebmedCentral PSYCHOLOGY 2010;1(12):WMC001322. Available online at: http://arxiv.org/abs/1012.3801

Perlovsky, L. I. (2010b). Intersections of mathematical, cognitive, and aesthetic theories of mind. Psychol. Aesthet. Creat. Arts 4, 11–17. doi: 10.1037/a0018147

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Perlovsky, L. I. (2012a). Cognitive function, origin, and evolution of musical emotions. Mus. Sci. 16, 185–199. doi: 10.1177/1029864912448327

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Perlovsky, L. I. (2012b). Cognitive function of music, Part I. Interdiscip. Sci. Rev. 37, 129–142. doi: 10.1179/0308018812Z.00000000010

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Perlovsky, L. I. (2013a). A challenge to human evolution—cognitive dissonance. Front. Psychol. 4:179. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00179

PubMed Abstract | Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Perlovsky, L. I. (2013b). Language and cognition—joint acquisition, dual hierarchy, and emotional prosody. Front. Behav. Neurosci. 7:123. doi: 10.3389/fnbeh.2013.00123

PubMed Abstract | Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Perlovsky, L. I. (2013c). Learning in brain and machine—complexity, gödel, aristotle. Front. Neurorob. 7:23. doi: 10.3389/fnbot.2013.00023

PubMed Abstract | Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Perlovsky, L. I. (2014a). Aesthetic emotions, what are their cognitive functions? Front. Psychol. 5:98. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00098

PubMed Abstract | Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Perlovsky, L. I. (2014b). Mystery in experimental psychology, how to measure aesthetic emotions? Front. Psychol. 5:1006. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2014.01006

PubMed Abstract | Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Perlovsky, L. I., Bonniot-Cabanac, M.-C., and Cabanac, M. (2010). Curiosity and Pleasure. WebmedCentral Psychology 2010;1(12):WMC001275. Available online at: http://www.webmedcentral.com/article_view/1275

Perlovsky, L. I., Cabanac, A., Bonniot-Cabanac, M.-C., and Cabanac, M. (2013). Mozart effect, cognitive dissonance, and the pleasure of music. ArXiv 1209.4017. Behav. Brain Res. 244, 9–14. doi: 10.1016/j.bbr.2013.01.036

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Perlovsky, L. I., Deming, R. W., and Ilin, R. (2011). Emotional Cognitive Neural Algorithms with Engineering Applications. Dynamic Logic: From Vague to Crisp. Heidelberg: Springer.

Google Scholar

Perlovsky, L. I., and Kozma, R. (eds.). (2007). Neurodynamics of Higher-Level Cognition and Consciousness. Heidelberg: Springer-Verlag.

Scherer, K. R. (2004). Which emotions can be induced by music? what are the underlying mechanisms? And how can we measure them? J. New Music Res. 33, 239–251. doi: 10.1080/0929821042000317822

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Simonton, D. K. (2000). Creativity. Cogn. Pers. Devel. Soc. Asp. Am. Psychol. 55, 151–158. doi: 10.1037/0003-066X.55.1.151

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Zentner, M., Grandjean, D., and Scherer, K. R. (2008). Emotions evoked by the sound of music: characterization, classification, and measurement. Emotion 8, 494–521. doi: 10.1037/1528-3542.8.4.494

PubMed Abstract | Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Keywords: music origin, cognitive dissonance, musical emotions, embodied cognition, hierarchy of the mind, abstract thoughts, knowledge instinct

Citation: Perlovsky L (2015) Origin of music and embodied cognition. Front. Psychol. 6:538. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2015.00538

Received: 17 February 2015; Accepted: 14 April 2015;
Published: 28 April 2015.

Edited by:

Mattie Tops, VU University Amsterdam, Netherlands

Reviewed by:

Tianyan Wang, Chinese Academy of Sciences, China

Copyright © 2015 Perlovsky. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) or licensor are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Leonid Perlovsky, lperl@rcn.com

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.