Skip to main content

OPINION article

Front. Psychiatry, 25 July 2013
Sec. Forensic Psychiatry

Which Future for Neuroscience in Forensic Psychiatry: Theoretical Hurdles and Empirical Chances

  • 1IEB, Geneva University Medical School, University of Geneva, Geneva, Switzerland
  • 2Child Psychopathology Unit, Scientific Institute, IRCCS Eugenio Medea, Lecco, Italy
  • 3NeuroPsiLab, Department of Public Health and Community Medicine, University of Verona, Verona, Italy

Neuroscience Data and Forensic Psychiatric Examination: Opportunities, Threats, and Limitations of the Current Debate

Almost all of the world’s legal systems assume that criminal responsibility cannot be established if the defendant was not capable to appreciate the wrongfulness of his/her actions (1). Furthermore, most Western Penal Codes assume that the defendant cannot be convicted if he/she is considered unable to evaluate the circumstances surrounding the anti-juridical fact, and/or if he/she is unable to control his/her urges, impulses, or responses. If a subject lacked these abilities, then courts may use statements such as “not guilty by reason of insanity,” “incapacitated person,” or “(partial) mental insanity” (2). Recent developments of neuroscience in clinical practice have lead to consider the potential role of neuroscience data for assessing criminal responsibility in forensic psychiatric examination (FPE) (3). In the literature, opportunities, threats, and limitations of the introduction of neuroscience in FPE have been widely debated (4, 5). It has been proposed that the use of neuroscience data in FPE may, at least in some circumstances, support the detection of such disabilities. Conversely, it has been also stressed the potential misleading role of neuroscience data in courts.

Traditionally, the debate focused on four major issues:

(a) renowned judgments involving the reference to neuroscience data in FPE (68)

(b) the relationship between brain abnormalities and violent behaviors leading to criminal acts:

* in conduct disorders (e.g., antisocial personality disorder, psychopathy, deficit of self-control) (911)

* following traumatic brain injury (1214)

* in sleep/awareness disorders (1517)

(c) opportunities and limitations of neuroimaging techniques (e.g., Magnetic Resonance Imaging, MRI; functional MRI, fMRI; Positron Emission Tomography, PET) (18, 19), behavioral genetics (20), and lie-detection techniques (21)

(d) Heterogeneity in admissibility criteria of neuroscience data through different legal systems (22, 23). Let’s consider US legal system: the rules governing expert testimony usually refer to “Frye” or “Daubert” approach (24). Furthermore, the crucial but controversial role of Federal Rules of Evidence (notably FRE 401, FRE 403, and FRE 702) in US legal system is a vexing issue in the literature [for a detailed description, (18)]. In many legal system, e.g., in Italy, there is not something like Federal Rules of Evidence and the judge has to evaluate – case by case – evidences presented by experts (e.g., psychiatrist, psychologist, or neurologist). If the interpretation of FRE may sometimes be hard and misleading, no specific criteria for admissibility (except for judge’s decision) may be also extremely dangerous.

Our aim is to highlight the critical issues about the conditions that support – in specific circumstances – the introduction of neuroscience data in FPE. In other words, before advocating or refusing the use of neuroscience data in FPE, we have to clarify the role that these data can have in FPE (i.e., a probative value for forensic assessment).

Firstly, we shortly hint at classical cognitive paradigms and their limitations. Secondly, we show that most of the Western Penal Codes are shaped assuming a sort of dualist model of human cognition. Finally, we describe potential misleading implications of neuroscience data endorsed in a dualist legal framework. Even if no neuroscience data can definitively discriminate neither between crime nor a mental defect, and neither between culpability nor innocence, we suggest that the introduction of neuroscience in FPE may be – in specific circumstances – useful and compelling.

Theoretical Hurdles and Empirical Chances: Which Implications for Forensic Settings?

Classically, a dualist model of human cognition assumes a clear distinction between two different substances: the mind and the body (25, 26). In such model, the mind has a direct control on bodily parts. In other words, the mind (roughly speaking, “mental states”) would control and manage the body (roughly speaking, “bodily acts”) through a sort of direct causal relationship. Recent advances in brain researches have arisen new theoretical dilemma. There is a widespread agreement, both in philosophy (27, 28) and cognitive neuroscience (29, 30), that underlines the incompatibility between neurobiological data and dualist conceptual framework. It is assumed that if neuroscience data are introduced in a dualist model, then misleading consequences could be taken for granted. Recent studies seem demand a break with traditional approaches to cognition.

Classical cognitivism and many paradigms in philosophy of mind consider mental operations clearly detached from the body, supporting the analogy between higher cognitive functions and specific computations. Following such perspectives, the content of mental representations should be explained in terms of pure mental states (i.e., intentions, beliefs, and desires). From a different point of view, an embodied perspective claims that many features of cognition deal with (causally or even constitutively) physical body (31, 32). It is still controversial the role of mental representation in embodied approaches. Some scholars have proposed the concept of “body representation” (such as a distinctive class of mental representation), claiming that they are the most promising notion to promote an embodied approach to social cognition (33). Others have proposed the notion of “embodied simulation,” arguing that one can understand others by reusing one’s own mental states or processes such as representations formatted in terms of bodily format (34). Both topics are hotly debated in the literature (35, 36).

Experimental studies seem support the idea that a new theoretical framework of human cognition has to be drawn. Let’s consider an interesting case. Mirror neurons are a distinct class of visuomotor neurons discovered in the ventral premotor cortex of macaque monkeys (37). More recently, evidences of the existence of a mirror neurons system in humans come from non-invasive neurophysiological techniques and neuroimaging studies (38, 39). Anatomically, two main cortical networks with mirror properties have been described in humans: the first one is the parieto-frontal mirror system (formed by the parietal lobe and the premotor cortex plus the caudal part of the inferior frontal gyrus); the second one is the limbic mirror system (formed by the insula and anterior mesial frontal cortex) that provides a direct understanding of emotions of others without higher order cognitive mediation (40). The role of parieto-frontal mirror circuit is hotly debated in the literature. The major interest concerns its functional role in action/intention understanding, in imitation, and more generally in social cognition. Even if many mechanisms may mediate the understanding of other’s behavior, a compelling view supports the hypothesis that parieto-frontal mirror circuit is the only mechanism that allows to understand the action of others “from the inside” (41). The case of mirror mechanism is emblematic; it seems support the hypothesis that recent advances in neuroscience demand a new theory of action execution, of action perception, and more generally a new model for human cognition. Such theoretical considerations are not without practical consequences: the value of neuroscience data can be misunderstood if we endorse them into a misleading perspective. In the next part, we show how and why these considerations may concern also FPE.

Dualist Model in the Forensic Field: Which Problems, if Any, with Neuroscience Data

To assess criminal responsibility, Western Penal Codes usually consider two specific elements. The individual’s body that has materially performed a crime (res extensa, latin for matter of facts) and individual’s mind has taken the decision to commit the crime (res cogitans, latin for mental capabilities). As above reported, it is also scheduled the possibility that a “mental defect” assessed in FPE restrains the possibility to attribute criminal responsibility. This model not only seems remind the dualist framework but it also reflects the way in which forensic psychiatrists usually are called to make assessments about mental capability. Let’s consider the Italian case. Italian Penal Code assumes a clear distinction between mind and body, internal mental states, and external bodily acts. At trial, an Italian judge asked a psychiatrist or psychologist an assessment about “mental capability” of the charged (Codice Penale, art. 88–89) (42), that is to distinguish between crime (i.e., naively “badness”) and mental defects (i.e., naively “madness”). However, there are some problems if we want to improve the assessment in FPE introducing also neuroscience data. “Mental defect” is an extremely ambiguous definition: does “mental defect” include also neurobiological data or, more classically, does it exclusively refer to a behavioral model? Moreover, the Italian judge asked the expert to clarify the “influence” (i.e., they intend causal link or deterministic relationship) between such as “mental defect” and mental abilities during the criminal act. In a dualist perspective, where mind (i.e., “mental states”) directly control the body (i.e., “bodily acts”), it is possible to suppose a causal link between “mental defect” and specific behavior (e.g., aggression). From the perspective of clinical neuroscience, this is a misleading supposition. In fact, experimental data cannot retrospectively assess such as deterministic relationship, given that it can indicates just a statistic-laden correlation. Neuroscience cannot definitively discriminate neither between crime and a mental defect, neither between culpability and innocence.

Conclusive Considerations

If it is widely assumed that neuroscience data cannot be profitably endorsed in a dualistic perspective, and if it is possible to show that the most of Western Penal Codes are shaped on a dualistic model, then there are compelling reasons to encourage a new perspective also in the forensic field. As above reported, it is not a theoretical proposition without practical consequences. We have stressed the idea that empirical data cannot directly assess criminal responsibility. Neuroscience data may be useful – in specific and limited circumstances – to give aid to traditional forensic assessment for mental capabilities. Clearly, not all neuroscience data may assume the same explanatory value, and not all data may be useful in FPE. The renowned debate on fMRI data is illustrative. On one side, researches both in biological psychiatry and neuropsychology have been considerably improved by fMRI studies (43, 44); on the other side, the effective implications of such studies are still controversial in clinical practice (45) and also in different research fields (e.g., economic behaviors, forensic settings, moral development, etc.) (18, 46, 47). Nevertheless, the debate on the probative value of specific neuroscientific techniques overcomes the aim of this work.

In conclusion, we suggest that the preliminary condition to introduce neuroscience data in FPE is the assumption of a new perspective overcoming classical dualist models. Such new perspective permits to rule out misleading assumptions (i.e., the deterministic link between “mental defect” and specific behavior). Noteworthy, it is a necessary but not sufficient condition to introduce neuroscience data in FPE, given that such data has to be evaluated case by case.

Acknowledgments

LC was supported by Fondation Ernst et Lucie Schmidheiny (Genève) and by Fondation pour des Bourses d’Etudes Italo-Suisses (Lausanne). Some of the arguments of this paper were presented (Poster Sessions) by LC at the Third National Conference on Neuroethics, Padua, Italy (4–6 May 2011) and at the Annual INS Meeting, Washington, DC, USA (10–11 November 2011) (co-authors A. Gini and B. Baertschi). We really thank B. Baertschi, A. Gini, W. Glannon and C. Sinigaglia, for their helpful comments.

References

1. Heller KJ, Dubber MD, editors. The Handbook of Comparative Criminal Law. Stanford: Stanford University Press (2011).

2. Penney S. Impulse control and criminal responsibility: lessons from neuroscience. Int J Law Psychiatry (2012) 35:99–103. doi:10.1016/j.ijlp.2011.12.004

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

3. Anckarsäter H, Radovic S, Svennerlind C, Höglund P, Radovic F. Mental disorder is a cause of crime: the cornerstone of forensic psychiatry. Int J Law Psychiatry (2009) 32:342–7. doi:10.1016/j.ijlp.2009.09.002

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

4. Dressing H, Sartorius A, Meyer-Lindenberg A. Implications of fMRI and genetics for the law and the routine practice of forensic psychiatry. Neurocase (2008) 14:7–14. doi:10.1080/13554790801992800

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

5. Sinnott-Armstrong WP. Neurolaw and consciousness detection. Cortex (2011) 47:1246–7. doi:10.1016/j.cortex.2011.04.021

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

6. Mobbs D, Lau HC, Jones OD, Frith CD. Law, responsibility, and the brain. PLoS Biol (2007) 5(4):e103. doi:10.1371/journal.pbio.0050103

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

7. Batts S. Brain lesions and their implications in criminal responsibility. Behav Sci Law (2009) 27:261–72. doi:10.1002/bsl.857

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

8. Sartori G, Pellegrini S, Mechelli A. Forensic neurosciences: from basic research to applications and pitfalls. Curr Opin Neurol (2011) 24:371–7. doi:10.1097/WCO.0b013e3283489754

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

9. Blair RJ. Neuroimaging of psychopathy and antisocial behaviour: a targeted review. Curr Psychiatry Rep (2010) 12:76–82. doi:10.1007/s11920-009-0086-x

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

10. Coccaro EF, Sripada CS, Yanowitch RN, Phan KL. Corticolimbic function in impulsive aggressive behavior. Biol Psychiatry (2011) 69:1153–9. doi:10.1016/j.biopsych.2011.02.032

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

11. Steiner H, Silverman M, Karnik NS, Huemer J, Plattner B, Clark CE, et al. Psychopathology, trauma and delinquency: subtypes of aggression and their relevance for understanding young offenders. Child Adolesc Psychiatry Ment Health (2011) 29:5–21. doi:10.1186/1753-2000-5-21

CrossRef Full Text

12. Colantonio A, Stamenova V, Abramowitz C, Clarke D, Christensen B. Brain injury in a forensic psychiatry population. Brain Inj (2007) 21:1353–60. doi:10.1080/02699050701785054

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

13. Camille N, Griffiths C, Fellows L, Vo K, Kable JW. Ventromedial frontal lobe damage disrupts value maximization in humans. J Neurosci (2011) 31:7527–32. doi:10.1523/JNEUROSCI.6527-10.2011

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

14. Sundram F, Deeley Q, Sarkar S, Daly E, Latham R, Craig M, et al. White matter microstructural abnormalities in the frontal lobe of adults with antisocial personality disorder. Cortex (2012) 48:216–29. doi:10.1016/j.cortex.2011.06.005

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

15. Cartwright R. Sleepwalking violence: a sleep disorder, a legal dilemma, and a psychological challenge. Am J Psychiatry (2004) 161:1149–58. doi:10.1176/appi.ajp.161.7.1149

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

16. Ohayon MM, Schenck CH. Violent behavior during sleep: prevalence, comorbidity and consequences. Sleep Med (2010) 11:941–6. doi:10.1016/j.sleep.2010.02.016

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

17. Kamphuis J, Meerlo P, Koolhaas JM, Lancel M. Poor sleep as a potential causal factor in aggression and violence. Sleep Med (2012) 13:327–34. doi:10.1016/j.sleep.2011.12.006

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

18. Brown T, Murphy E. Through a scanner darkly: functional neuroimaging as evidence of a criminal defendant’s past mental states. Stanford Law Rev (2010) 62:119–208.

19. Kessler K, Muckli L. Reading others’ minds by measuring their brains: fascinating and challenging for science, but ready for use in court? Cortex (2011) 47:1240–2. doi:10.1016/j.cortex.2011.04.019

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

20. Markowitsch HJ, Staniloiu A. Neuroscience, neuroimaging and the law. Cortex (2011) 47:1248–51. doi:10.1016/j.cortex.2011.06.013

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

21. Rissman J, Greely HT, Wegner AD. Detecting individual memories through the neural decoding of memory states and past experience. Proc Natl Acad Sci U S A (2010) 107:9849–54. doi:10.1073/pnas.1001028107

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

22. Garland B, Glimcher PW. Cognitive neuroscience and the law. Curr Opin Neurobiol (2006) 6:130–4. doi:10.1016/j.conb.2006.03.011

CrossRef Full Text

23. McCabe DP, Castel AD, Rhodes MG. The influence of fMRI lie detection evidence on juror decision-making. Behav Sci Law (2011) 29:566–77. doi:10.1002/bsl.993

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

24. Casartelli L, Chiamulera C. Opportunities, threats and limitations of neuroscience data in forensic psychiatric evaluation. Curr Opin Psychiatry (2013). doi:10.1097/YCO.0b013e32836342e1. [Epub ahead of print].

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

25. Descartes R. III. Discours de la méthode et essais. In: de Buzon F, editor. Œuvres Complètes. Paris: Gallimard (2009).

26. Damasio A. Descartes’s Error: Emotion, Reason, and the Human Brain. New York: Grosset/Putnam (1994).

27. Gallagher S, Zahavi D. The Phenomenological Mind: An Introduction to Philosophy of Mind and Cognitive Science. London: Routledge (2008).

28. Gallagher S, Cole J. Dissociation in self-narrative. Conscious Cogn (2011) 20:149–55. doi:10.1016/j.concog.2010.10.003

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

29. Ferrari PF, Gallese V. Mirror neurons and intersubjectivity. In: Braten S, editor. On Being Moved. from Mirror Neurons to Empathy. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Company (2007). p. 73–8.

30. Sinigaglia C, Rizzolatti G. Through the looking glass: self and others. Conscious Cogn (2011) 20:64–74. doi:10.1016/j.concog.2010.11.012

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

31. Gallagher S. Simulation trouble. Soc Neurosci (2007) 2:353–65. doi:10.1080/17470910601183549

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

32. Gallese V. Before and below ‘theory of mind’: embodied simulation and the neural correlates of social cognition. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci (2007) 362:659–69. doi:10.1098/rstb.2006.2002

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

33. Goldman A, de Vignemont F. Is social cognition embodied? Trends Cogn Sci (Regul Ed) (2009) 13:154–9. doi:10.1016/j.tics.2009.01.007

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

34. Gallese V, Sinigaglia C. What is so special about embodied simulation? Trends Cogn Sci (Regul Ed) (2011) 15:512–9. doi:10.1016/j.tics.2011.09.003

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

35. Niedenthal PM. Embodying emotion. Science (2007) 18:1002–5. doi:10.1126/science.1136930

CrossRef Full Text

36. de Bruin L, Gallagher S. Embodied simulation, an unproductive explanation: comment on Gallese and Sinigaglia. Trends Cogn Sci (Regul Ed) (2012) 16:98–9. doi:10.1016/j.tics.2011.12.003

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

37. di Pellegrino G, Fadiga L, Fogassi L, Gallese V, Rizzolatti G. Understanding motor events: a neurophysiological study. Exp Brain Res (1992) 91:176–80. doi:10.1007/BF00230027

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

38. Rizzolatti G, Craighero L. The mirror-neuron system. Annu Rev Neurosci (2004) 27:169–92. doi:10.1146/annurev.neuro.27.070203.144230

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

39. Iacoboni M, Mazziotta JC. Mirror neuron system: basic findings and clinical applications. Ann Neurol (2007) 62:213–8. doi:10.1002/ana.21198

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

40. Keysers C, Gazzola V. Expanding the mirror: vicarious activity for actions, emotions, and sensations. Curr Opin Neurobiol (2009) 19:666–71. doi:10.1016/j.conb.2009.10.006

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

41. Rizzolatti G, Sinigaglia C. The functional role of the parieto-frontal mirror circuit: interpretations and misinterpretations. Nat Rev Neurosci (2010) 11:264–74. doi:10.1038/nrn2805

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

42. Marinucci G, Dolcini E. Manuale di Diritto Penale. Parte Generale. Milano: Giuffré (2009).

43. Dolan MC, Fullam RS. Psychopathy and functional magnetic resonance imaging blood oxygenation level-dependent responses to emotional faces in violent patients with schizophrenia. Biol Psychiatry (2009) 66:570–7. doi:10.1016/j.biopsych.2009.03.019

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

44. Penadés R, Pujol N, Catalán R, Massana G, Rametti G, García-Rizo C, et al. Brain effects of cognitive remediation therapy in schizophrenia: a structural and functional neuroimaging study. Biol Psychiatry (2013) 73(10):1015–23. doi:10.1016/j.biopsych.2013.01.017

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

45. Pike GB. Quantitative functional MRI: concepts, issues and future challenges. Neuroimage (2012) 15:1234–40. doi:10.1016/j.neuroimage.2011.10.046

CrossRef Full Text

46. Forbes CE, Grafman J. The role of the human prefrontal cortex in social cognition and moral judgment. Annu Rev Neurosci (2010) 33:299–324. doi:10.1146/annurev-neuro-060909-153230

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

47. Baumgartner T, Knoch D, Hotz P, Eisenegger C, Fehr E. Dorsolateral and ventromedial prefrontal cortex orchestrate normative choice. Nat Neurosci (2011) 2:1468–74. doi:10.1038/nn.2933

CrossRef Full Text

Citation: Casartelli L and Chiamulera C (2013) Which future for neuroscience in forensic psychiatry: theoretical hurdles and empirical chances. Front. Psychiatry 4:74. doi: 10.3389/fpsyt.2013.00074

Received: 25 March 2013; Accepted: 11 July 2013;
Published online: 25 July 2013.

Edited by:

William Donald Richie, Meharry Medical College, USA

Copyright: © 2013 Casartelli and Chiamulera. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License, which permits use, distribution and reproduction in other forums, provided the original authors and source are credited and subject to any copyright notices concerning any third-party graphics etc.

*Correspondence: luca.casartelli@unige.ch

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.