Skip to main content

OPINION article

Front. Psychol., 03 May 2013
Sec. Psychology of Language
This article is part of the Research Topic Does Language Production Shape Language Form and Comprehension? View all 14 articles

Production is at the left edge of the PDC but still central: response to commentaries

  • Department of Psychology, University of Wisconsin-Madison, Madison, WI, USA

In one of the commentaries to my target article (MacDonald, 2013) advocating the Production Distribution Comprehension (PDC) account, Ramscar and Baayen (2013) generously suggest that it's an “intellectual pleasure” to contemplate the PDC claims, even if they don't entirely agree with them. This characterization—both the genuine pleasure and the not entirely agreeing—equally applies to me in reading these 11 stimulating commentaries, and I address some major themes below.

Novelty of the Claim

Laka (2013) correctly observes that many linguists and psycholinguists agree that sensori-motor processes shape language form. She wonders what the PDC contributes beyond this. Similarly, Levy and Gibson (2013) ask what the PDC has to say beyond the fact that producers produce language distributions. These were not my claims; I argued that specifically the difficulty-reduction choices of utterance form have substantial cascading effects through typology and comprehension. The PDC is a distinct perspective, even as it clearly builds on other established work.

Production

The largest theme in the commentaries (Arnold, 2013; Frazier, 2013; Hagoort and Meyer, 2013; Jaeger, 2013; Laka, 2013; Ramscar and Baayen, 2013; Tanenhaus, 2013; Wasow, 2013) is that “not … all aspects of language form and comprehension can be traced to the computational demands of language production.” Since this quote comes from my own article, I certainly don't disagree. I argue that production pressures are too big to ignore in theories of typology and comprehension, not that they're the only game in town. My own objection to my claim is that although it directs attention to understudied issues, it doesn't fully quantify “too important.” I welcome the push to more specificity.

Tanenhaus (2013) (also Jaeger, 2013) suggests that production difficulty could turn out to be overstated, much as ideas about comprehension difficulty have undergone seismic shifts in recent decades. It's exciting to think about what preconceptions will be overturned with new work in conversation and joint action (Hagoort and Meyer, 2013; Pickering and Garrod, 2013; Tanenhaus, 2013), but evidence for ease of production doesn't necessarily weaken the PDC. A central PDC claim is that producers reduce their production difficulty, and so if production turns out to be not so hard, this may owe in part to the success of those efforts. Relatedly, Hagoort and Meyer (2013) and Pickering and Garrod (2013) suggest that in conversational interaction, production, and comprehension have shared processes and representations, and are thus hard to distinguish. That is certainly true, but the tasks of production and comprehension are unquestionably different, and the PDC claim begins with mitigating the particular demands of planning serially ordered elements in production. The role of learning for success at this task is essential to the PDC. For example, Wasow (2013) notes that producers avoid some kinds of ambiguity but not others; a PDC account of this result will necessarily involve learning over time, likely from a combination of the producer's internal states, perceiving one's own productions, and feedback from perceivers. Jaeger's (2013) discussion of production and motor learning is welcome as we pursue a more mechanistic account of learning in production.

Viewing communicative goals more broadly (Arnold, 2013; Jaeger, 2013; Ramscar and Baayen, 2013) is important but not inconsistent with the PDC. If production is relatively more difficult than comprehension, then adjusting utterance form more toward the producer's needs (more fully accommodating the more difficult task) actually serves the overarching goal of efficient communication. The comparatively greater difficulty of production can be seen in the fact that production lags comprehension in acquisition, is more impaired by brain injury or disease, has higher motoric demands, requires memory recall more than recognition, and is less practiced than comprehension, in that we perceive substantially more than we produce. The examples in these commentaries are excellent vehicles for considering production tasks within the broader context of a producer aiming for communicative success.

Frazier (2013) and Laka (2013) offer a number of syntactic alternations that might not be amenable to a production-based explanation. These are important, but we should resist the tendency to consider only one production factor (Easy First, say) at a time. In this regard, it's informative to read Wasow's (2013) discussion of interactions among various production biases. His Contiguity strategy echoes Solomon and Pearlmutter's (2004) semantic integration claim: conceptual elements that are tightly bound in a producer's pre-linguistic message tend to enter into utterance planning at the same time, and as a result, tend to end up nearby in the utterance plan. Additional production biases beyond the three I reviewed will complicate the PDC, but so will consideration of other aspects of production, such as Ferreira's (2013) interesting extension of the PDC into prosody. Her examples, and other aspects of acoustic variation (Arnold, 2013), could be helpful in integrating the PDC's emphasis on production demands with the broader communicative goals discussed above. One possibility is that different aspects of utterance planning may vary in their sensitivity to producer and perceiver needs. Thus, the memory retrieval and linearization demands for lexico-syntactic utterance planning may yield a good deal of producer accommodation, in that one alternative utterance form may be substantially easier than others. In contrast, alternative prosodic forms may vary less in production difficulty, and thus acoustic variation may carry relatively more perceiver accommodation than does variation in word order, for example. These speculations reflect the daunting complexity of the multiple facets of utterance planning, but also the opportunities for viewing the system both at the computational level of robust communication and with respect to specific examples for which more mechanistic accounts of utterance planning and its memory, attention, and motor components can be achieved.

Distribution

Laka (2013) asks a key question for many linguists about the PDC's impact in typology: can it tell us about why some sentences are judged grammatical and others not? Accounts of the relationship between language processing and grammaticality certainly do exist; for example Hawkins' (1994) discussion has had substantial impact in some areas of linguistics and little in others. If grammaticality judgments are taken both as what needs to be explained and as inherently independent of production and comprehension, then I don't predict much headway for the PDC here. However, among more gradient accounts of grammar with clear relationships to language use (e.g., Bresnan and Hay, 2008), I suspect that the PDC will have more impact (see also Wasow, 2013).

Ramscar and Baayen (2013) present exactly the sort of typological evidence that I hope psycholinguists will address, in this case the diachronic shift to obligatory pronouns from Latin to French. Wasow (2013) makes related points about noun classes and agreement. They are likely correct that comprehenders benefit from these language features (e.g., Van Berkum et al., 2005), but a benefit does not entail that the form arose for the perceiver's needs. At least some complex overt agreement systems benefit producers (as measured by error rates, Lorimor et al. (2008).1 My own conjecture is that some elements (including agreeing forms, resumptive pronouns, and complementizers) may aid internal monitoring of the producer's progress through the utterance plan by providing an overt signal of the state of plan execution. Thus while there are many examples cross-linguistically of reducing production difficulty by omitting elements, there may also be cases where producing short frequent elements provides benefits that outweigh the effort to produce them (epenthesis may provide other examples). This possibility, plus the idea that a given language feature may serve several functions, doesn't bode well for parsimony or building comprehensive theories, but it does reflect the fact that production and comprehension have multiple sub-tasks, each with computational demands.

Comprehension

Arnold (2013) and Frazier (2013) want to know more about how people learn distributional regularities. I certainly gave short shrift to this topic in my article, but there are abundant examples in the literature (e.g., Ramscar and Baayen, 2013). My own work favors the error-correcting learning algorithms of connectionist networks, with their emphasis on the generalizations over instances that I see as essential to addressing the “what exactly is learned?” questions (e.g., Wells et al., 2009). There are many alternative learning approaches, however; some may more readily apply to certain questions than others, and several may turn out to be effectively equivalent (e.g., Solway and Botvinick, 2012). It's an exciting time to consider the role of learning in language use, granting that steps to date have not been fully convincing (or fully communicated). For example, Frazier (2013) wonders whether the PDC predicts that comprehenders learn the production-based regularities of optional that use in English to the point that they'd have difficulty when that is produced in an environment in which it's rare. It's a surprising prediction from the perspective of much comprehension research, because that has a disambiguating function, which could be always helpful. The answer is yes, the PDC does predict that in cases where the presence of that violates the production-based distributional regularities, it should be disruptive, and that is what we find (Race and MacDonald, 2003).

Levy and Gibson (2013) display some pique at my perceived neglect of surprisal, a competence-level account that they claim is a “theoretical advance,” contrasted with the PDC by being computationally implemented and making precise predictions about the loci of comprehension difficulty. They then admit that surprisal doesn't actually predict relative clause difficulty correctly, and they turn to Gibson's experience-independent working memory approach to help out. They can't imagine how the weaker and unimplemented PDC could do any better. The errors in this view are illuminating. First, Levy and Gibson (2013) don't get the distributional facts right about object relative clauses. Gennari and MacDonald (2008) explicitly discuss (and link to performance) the existence of important “late” indeterminacies—NP-(that)-NP sequences, and even NP-(that)-NP-V sequences, that still afford many interpretations and thus can continue to yield late comprehension difficulty. An example above that turns out not to be an object relative is [a competence-level account]NP that [they]NP [claim]V…, where claim takes a sentential complement, and account is not its direct object (as would be the case in an object relative). Several million additional examples (still only a fraction of the relevant experiences) can be found by Googling “said would.” If Levy and Gibson (2013) had not simply assumed a distribution and had actually implemented surprisal in relative clauses based on a realistic corpus, they'd likely find that it does a better job than they imagined. Second, their characterization of the PDC as unimplemented vagueness is incorrect. Relative clause processing is one implemented domain, and unlike Levy and Gibson's (2013) existing surprisal account, MacDonald and Chrisitiansen's (2002) simple recurrent network (SRN) implementation yields the correct loci of processing difficulty, and moreover it does so without the independent working memory that Levy and Gibson (2013) require. Our SRN worked despite experiencing only a fraction of the linguistic experiences that affect human performance. Why? The answer shows how the PDC and this SRN are not surprisal-lite: Implemented surprisal (e.g., Smith and Levy, in press) is Bayesian inference from instances in a corpus; there is no learning and no generalization over lexical or structural similarities. By contrast, the SRN learns and generalizes from common main clauses to rarer relative clauses, which is critical to its success (MacDonald and Christiansen, 2002; Wells et al., 2009). Could surprisal advocates also incorporate learning and generalization? Of course, and it would be extremely interesting. In the meantime, Levy and Gibson's (2013) more-computational-than-thou approach to the PDC seems counterproductive to what I take as a shared interest in the role of experience in comprehension.

Conclusion

Certain central points in the PDC continue to hold in the context of these very stimulating commentaries: The cognitive demands of transforming an a-temporal message into a motor sequence, and the memory and attention needed to develop the plan and execute it, are unique and challenging in human behavior. Producers' adjustments to deal with these challenges have profound downstream consequences, even if these adjustments are being done in the service of another critical task, communication.

Acknowledgments

I am grateful for support from the National Science Foundation (BCS 1123788) and the Wisconsin Alumni Research Fund. Thanks to Mark Seidenberg for helpful comments on an earlier draft of this article.

Footnotes

  1. ^In several studies Jelena Mirković and I investigated the highly complex agreement system in Serbian using [NP[PP]] constructions that generate many errors in English and elsewhere. Serbian speakers produced essentially no agreement errors, and those data remain unpublished.

References

Arnold, J. E. (2013). Information status relates to production, distribution, and comprehension. Front. Psychol. 4:235. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00235

CrossRef Full Text

Bresnan, J., and Hay, J. (2008). Gradient grammar: an effect of animacy on the syntax of give in New Zealand and American English. Lingua 118, 245–259.

Frazier, L. (2013). Say what you please? Really? Front. Psychol. 4:237. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00237

CrossRef Full Text

Ferreira, F. (2013). The PDC framework applied to prosody and disfluency. Front. Psychol. 4:232. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00232

CrossRef Full Text

Gennari, S. P., and MacDonald, M. C. (2008). Semantic indeterminacy in object relative clauses. J. Mem. Lang. 58, 161–187.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Hagoort, P., and Meyer, A. (2013). What belongs together goes together: the speaker-hearer perspective. A commentary on MacDonald's PDC account. Front. Psychol. 4:228. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00228

CrossRef Full Text

Hawkins, J. A. (1994). A Performance Theory of Order and Constituency. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Jaeger, T. F. (2013). Production preferences cannot be understood without reference to communication. Front. Psychol. 4:230. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00230

CrossRef Full Text

Laka, I. (2013). On language production principles and the form of language: a más cómo, menos por qué. Front. Psychol. 4:231. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00231

CrossRef Full Text

Levy, R., and Gibson, E. (2013). Surprisal, the PDC, and the primary locus of processing difficulty in relative clauses. Front. Psychol. 4:229. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00229

CrossRef Full Text

Lorimor, H., Bock, K., Zalkind, E., Sheyman, A., and Beard, R. (2008). Agreement and attraction in Russian. Lang. Cogn. Process. 23, 769–799.

MacDonald, M. C., and Christiansen, M. H. (2002). Reassessing working memory: comment on Just and Carpenter (1992) and Waters and Caplan (1996). Psychol. Rev. 109, 35–54.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

MacDonald, M. C. (2013). How language production shapes language form and comprehension. Front. Psychol. 4:226. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00226

CrossRef Full Text

Pickering, M. J., and Garrod, S. (2013). How tightly are production and comprehension interwoven? Front. Psychol. 4:238. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00238

CrossRef Full Text

Race, D. S., and MacDonald, M. C. (2003). “The use of “that” in the production and comprehension of object relative clauses,” in Proceedings of the 25th Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society, eds R. Alterman and D. Kirsh (Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum).

Ramscar, M., and Baayen, H. (2013). Production, comprehension and synthesis: a communicative perspective on language. Front. Psychol. 4:233. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00233

CrossRef Full Text

Smith, N. J., and Levy, R. (in press). The effect of word predictability on reading time is logarithmic. Cognition.

Solomon, E. S., and Pearlmutter, N. J. (2004). Semantic integration and syntactic planning in language production. Cogn. Psychol. 49, 1–46.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Solway, A., and Botvinick, M. M. (2012). Goal-directed decision making as probabilistic inference: a computational framework and potential neural correlates. Psychol. Rev. 119, 120–154.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Tanenhaus, M. K. (2013). All P's or mixed vegetables? Front. Psychol. 4:234. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00234

CrossRef Full Text

Van Berkum, J. J. A., Brown, C. M., Zwitserlood, P., Kooijman, V., and Hagoort, P. (2005). Anticipating upcoming words in discourse: evidence from ERPs and reading times. J. Exp. Psychol. Learn. Mem. Cogn. 31, 443–467.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Wasow, T. (2013). The appeal of the PDC program. Front. Psychol. 4:236. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00236

CrossRef Full Text

Wells, J. B., Christiansen, M. H., Race, D. S., Acheson, D. J., and MacDonald, M. C. (2009). Experience and sentence processing: statistical learning and relative clause comprehension. Cogn. Psychol. 58, 250–271.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Citation: MacDonald MC (2013) Production is at the left edge of the PDC but still central: response to commentaries. Front. Psychol. 4:227. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00227

Received: 10 April 2013; Accepted: 11 April 2013;
Published online: 03 May 2013.

Edited by:

Charles Jr. Clifton, University of Massachusetts Amherst, USA

Reviewed by:

Charles Jr. Clifton, University of Massachusetts Amherst, USA

Copyright © 2013 MacDonald. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License, which permits use, distribution and reproduction in other forums, provided the original authors and source are credited and subject to any copyright notices concerning any third-party graphics etc.

*Correspondence: mcmacdonald@wisc.edu

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.