Skip to main content

OPINION article

Front. Psychol., 03 November 2014
Sec. Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology

The bright side of boredom

  • Department of Philosophy, University of Louisville, Louisville, KY, USA

Boredom proneness is commonly assessed and measured using self-report scales and questionnaires. The only full-scale measure of boredom that has been extensively used to assess boredom proneness is the Boredom Proneness Scale (BPS) (Farmer and Sundberg, 1986). BPS takes boredom proneness to be the tendency to experience boredom in a wide range of situations (Farmer and Sundberg, 1986). Although there is a close semantic relationship between the terms “tendency” and “disposition,” boredom proneness should not be understood as a dispositional state or property. A subject can possess the disposition to Φ even if the subject never actually Φ s. For that reason, I wish to suggest that one is prone to boredom not only if one possesses characteristics that make one susceptible to being bored, but also if one frequently experiences boredom1. Unlike a disposition that can remain hidden or non-actualized, boredom proneness, I hold, has visible and significant for the subject manifestations. Indeed, the frequent experience of boredom forms something akin to a pervasive lens through which the world is filtered. The boredom prone individual often and easily finds herself to be bored, even in situations that others, typically, find interesting and stimulating. Furthermore, she regularly becomes incapable of maintaining sustained attention, and interest in one's activities (Damrad-Frye and Laird, 1989; Eastwood et al., 2012; Malkovsky et al., 2012), she lacks excitement for, or can find no purpose in, what she is doing (Barbalet, 1999; Fahlman et al., 2009; van Tilburg and Igou, 2012), and she easily becomes frustrated, restless, or weary by either stimuli-poor or challenging situations (Farmer and Sundberg, 1986). Boredom proneness is associated with a plethora of significant bodily, psychological, and social harms (Vodanovich, 2003). Boredom proneness is positively correlated with depression and anxiety (Ahmed, 1990; Blaszczynski et al., 1990; Sommers and Vodanovich, 2000; Goldberg et al., 2011; LePera, 2011), anger and aggression (Gordon et al., 1997; Rupp and Vodanovich, 1997; Dahlen et al., 2004), a lower tendency to engage in and enjoy thinking (Watt and Blanchard, 1994; Seib and Vodanovich, 1998), a propensity to make mistakes in completing common tasks (Wallace et al., 2002), poor interpersonal and social relationships (Leong and Schneller, 1993; Watt and Vodanovich, 1999), lower job and life satisfaction (Farmer and Sundberg, 1986; Kass et al., 2001), problem gambling (Blaszczynski et al., 1990; Mercer and Eastwood, 2010), and drug and alcohol abuse (Lee et al., 2007; LePera, 2011).

Boredom proneness ought to be distinguished from the state of boredom, i.e., the actual experience of boredom (cf. Fenichel, 1953; O'Hanlon, 1981; Neu, 1998; Fahlman et al., 2013). Even though boredom proneness is predicated on the antecedent experience of boredom—viz., one cannot be said to be prone to boredom if one never experienced boredom—the very experience of boredom does not entail boredom proneness. One can be in a state of boredom without one necessarily being prone to boredom. Understood as a psychological state that is not necessarily the manifestation of boredom proneness, boredom is an aversive, transient state that can be often easily alleviated. It can also be a rather common and mundane experience. For instance, most of us experience boredom while waiting in line to pay for our shopping, when our bus or train is delayed, or when we have to endure the same conversation, lecture, or TV show over and over again. Often, boredom is situational: it is brought about by the unchallenging, monotonous, or repetitive situations in which we find ourselves (O'Hanlon, 1981). As a result, boredom can be allayed by a mere change in setting. Boredom, however, need not always be situational. Depending on our moods, desires, and attitudes, situations that are ostensively meaningful and challenging could also bring about the state of boredom (Geiwitz, 1966; Mikulas and Vodanovich, 1993); conversely, situations that are repetitive, monotonous, and utterly humdrum do not have to lead to the experience of boredom (Perkins and Hill, 1985; DeChenne and Moody, 1988).

Theoretical discussions of the state of boredom have been predominantly one-sided. Notwithstanding a few notable exceptions (Nietzsche, 1974, p. 108; Brodsky, 1995; and Russell, 1996, pp. 48, 52), the literary and philosophical history of boredom consists of a series of attempts to articulate boredom's distinctively negative nature. Boredom is thought to be disruptive and harmful (Dostoevsky, 1962, p. 418; Stendhal, 1975, p. 211; Burton, 1621/2001, p. 390; Pessoa, 2002, p. 76; Novalis in Donehower, 2012, p. 48), a great source of unhappiness and suffering (Schopenhauer, 1966, pp. 204, 312–313, 321; Beckett, 1978; Nisbet, 1982, p. 26; Kierkegaard, 1987, pp. 37, 285–286; Fromm, 1990; Schachtel, 2001, p. 183) and, ultimately, a state that hinders the development of one's intellectual, social, and even moral capacities (Dante's Purgatorio, XVII-XIX; Cassian, 2000; Sinkewicz, 2003; Pascal, 2004, pp. 40, 163). Boredom, as “the root of all evil,” is a problematic state (Kierkegaard, 1987, p. 286); it has very few, if any, redeeming characteristics2.

Despite its impressive historical backing, the view that boredom is entirely negative should be rejected. Recent empirical work on boredom, taken in tandem with theoretical considerations about its nature and character, suggest a rather different picture of the state of boredom (Barbalet, 1999; van Tilburg and Igou, 2012; Bench and Lench, 2013; Gasper and Middlewood, 2014). In broad strokes, the picture is as follows: on account of its affective, volitional, and cognitive aspects, boredom motivates the pursuit of a new goal when the current goal ceases to be satisfactory, attractive, or meaningful to the agent. Boredom helps to restore the perception that one's activities are meaningful or significant. It acts as a regulatory state that keeps one in line with one's projects. In the absence of boredom, one would remain trapped in unfulfilling situations, and miss out on many emotionally, cognitively, and socially rewarding experiences. Boredom is both a warning that we are not doing what we want to be doing and a “push” that motivates us to switch goals and projects. Neither apathy, nor dislike, nor frustration can fulfill boredom's function (Goldberg et al., 2011). In what follows, I elaborate on this picture of boredom and make a case for its value and significance.

But first, more needs to be said about the very nature of the state of boredom. In terms of its affective (or qualitative) character, boredom is an aversive state that is characterized by feelings of dissatisfaction, restlessness, and weariness. Although additional feelings might be present during the state of boredom (e.g., mild frustration), the aforesaid feelings are essential to boredom. Not only subjects who experience boredom report on having these feelings, but also, and most importantly, the lack of any one of these feelings would result in a psychological state that is different than boredom (van Tilburg and Igou, 2012; Fahlman et al., 2013; cf. Thackray et al., 1975; Hill and Perkins, 1985; Perkins and Hill, 1985; O'Brien, 2014). Boredom without dissatisfaction cannot be boredom: to be satisfied with one's situation is to cease to be bored with the situation. Restlessness and weariness are equally essential. When one is bored one is not content with one's situation. The state of boredom is one from which we seek to escape. While bored, one is thus restless, for one is not content with one's current situation and one wishes to be doing something else (van Tilburg and Igou, 2012). Lastly, the experience of boredom involves weariness. To experience boredom is to experience a certain kind of weariness or mental fatigue. The boring, in other words, tires us.

The experiential character of boredom includes more than its affective aspects. That is to say, boredom is not merely a sensual or a qualitatively state. While bored one has certain thoughts about one's situation or object of attention. Often, for example, one thinks that the situation in which one finds oneself is bereft of significance or meaning (van Tilburg and Igou, 2012), or that what one is currently doing is incongruous with one's plans. Furthermore, while bored one has a desire, often quite strong, to engage in a different and more satisfying activity. One also has a difficulty maintaining and focusing one's attention (Bernstein, 1975; Fisher, 1993; Martin et al., 2006; Eastwood et al., 2012). One even experiences a slow passage of time (Fenichel, 1953; O'Connor, 1967; Hartocollis, 1972; Conrad, 1997; Martin et al., 2006).

In a state of boredom, the world is revealed to oneself in a particular and indeed striking fashion (Elpidorou, forthcoming). The world appears not only to be uninteresting, but also distant, foreign, and often unyielding. Boredom contributes to a loss of value, significance, or meaning. The world of boredom is, in a sense, not our world: it is not the world that is in line with our projects and desires. Our current situation does not attract us; we do not feel compelled to engage with it. The weariness that we experience while bored, compounded with the perception of a slower passage of time, makes the character of boredom all the more aversive (Sackett et al., 2010). Being in a state of boredom feels like being emotionally trapped: the unsatisfying situation with which we are engaging seems to last longer; it appears to be removed from our concerns; and we feel weary. Crucially, however, boredom is not a state of equilibrium. We are not content in it. We feel restless and wish to be doing something else. We desire escape from boredom. In turn, while bored it is difficult for us to focus our attention on features of the present situation. Our mind wanders and alternative goals and situations suddenly become salient to us. If boredom is likened to an emotional trap, it is a trap that due to its own character fortunately “pushes” us to escape from it.

The significance and value of boredom should now be apparent. First, boredom is informative: it tells us something both about the world and about ourselves. While bored, our situation is disclosed to us as unfulfilling, uninteresting, unchallenging, or non-stimulating. On account of this disclosure, boredom also informs us of our own goals, interests, and even self-perceived wellbeing. Being bored means that we are currently engaged not only in an uninteresting or unchallenging situation, but also in a situation that fails to meet our expectations and desires. Boredom is a state that is about ourselves as much as it is about the world.

Second, and most importantly, the negative and aversive experience of boredom acts as a force that motivates us to pursue a goal that appears to us to be more stimulating, interesting, challenging, or fulfilling than the goal that we currently pursue (Barbalet, 1999; van Tilburg and Igou, 2012; Bench and Lench, 2013). In an episode of boredom, our current goal or situation is perceived as unpleasant and unappealing, often as devoid of meaning or significance; on the contrary, alternative goals and situations are made salient and appear to us to be attractive. Boredom thus facilitates the pursuit of alternative goals: it “pushes” us out of this non-stimulating, uninteresting, or unchallenging situation and into another. In motivating us to pursue a situation that is different from our current one, boredom ultimately promotes the restoration of the perception that one's activities are meaningful and congruent with one's overall projects (Locke and Latham, 1990; Sansone et al., 1992; Heine et al., 2006). What alleviates boredom is not simply a change of activity. Rather, what alleviates boredom is a change from an uninteresting, unfulfilling, or non-stimulating situation to one that is perceived by the agent to be satisfactory and in line with her plans and wishes.

Given its twofold function, boredom is best understood as a state that monitors and regulates our behavior. It informs us when we are out of tune with our interests, and, on account of its aversive character, motivates us to engage in situations that are perceived by us as fulfilling or meaningful. Boredom is important. It promotes our interests by trying to keep us in touch with what we care about. It safeguards us from emotional traps and long-term dullness.

Conflict of Interest Statement

The author declares that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Acknowledgment

I am grateful to a reviewer for extensive and very helpful comments on previous versions of this article.

Footnotes

1. ^In Fahlman et al. (2013), a disjunctive account of boredom proneness is offered. “When a person declares herself to be prone to boredom, she is claiming (i) that she frequently experiences boredom, or (ii) that she possesses the qualities that predispose her to experience boredom given the right circumstances” (81; Roman numerals added). My description of boredom proneness is conjunctive: both (i) and (ii) are taken to be necessary in order for an individual to be prone to boredom. If (ii) was a sufficient condition for boredom proneness, then one could be said to be prone to boredom even if one never experienced boredom (e.g., one possesses the relevant characteristics but one never finds herself in circumstances that permit those characteristics to bring about the experience of boredom). If (i) was sufficient, then accidental environmental (or exogenous) conditions could render an individual prone to boredom, even if the individual possesses none of the characteristics that predispose her to experience boredom.

2. ^More recent theoretical discussions of boredom do not diverge greatly from the practice of treating boredom as a problem or malaise. See e.g., Healy (1984, pp. 11, 75) and Svendsen (2004, pp. 16, 154) Even Brodsky, who sets out to defend boredom, describes boredom as an “incurable malaise” (1997, p. 104).

References

Ahmed, S. M. S. (1990). Psychometric properties of the boredom proneness scale. Percept. Mot. Skills 71, 963–966. doi: 10.2466/pms.1990.71.3.963

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Barbalet, J. M. (1999). Boredom and social meaning. Br. J. Sociol. 50, 631–646. doi: 10.1080/000713199358572

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Beckett, S. (1978). Proust. New York, NY: Grove Press.

Bench, S. W., and Lench, H. C. (2013). On the function of boredom. Behav. Sci. 3, 459–472. doi: 10.3390/bs3030459

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bernstein, H. E. (1975). Boredom and the ready-made life. Soc. Res. 42, 512–537.

Google Scholar

Blaszczynski, A., McConaghy, N., and Frankova, A. (1990). Boredom proneness in pathological gambling. Psychol. Rep. 67, 35–42. doi: 10.2466/pr0.1990.67.1.35

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Brodsky, J. (1995). On grief and Reason: Essays. New York, NY: Farrar, Straus, and Giroux.

Burton, R. (1621/2001). The Anatomy of Melancholy. New York: New York Review of Books. (Originally published).

Google Scholar

Cassian, J. (2000). John Cassian, the Institutes. Vol. 58. Transl. by B. Ramsey. New York, NY: Newman Press.

Conrad, P. (1997). It's boring: notes on the meanings of boredom in everyday life. Qual. Sociol. 20, 465–475.

Google Scholar

Dahlen, E. R., Martin, R. C., Ragan, K., and Kuhlman, M. M. (2004). Boredom proneness in anger and aggression: effects of impulsiveness and sensation seeking. Pers. Individ. Dif. 37, 1615–1627. doi: 10.1016/j.paid.2004.02.016

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Damrad-Frye, R., and Laird, J. D. (1989). The experience of boredom: the role of the self-perception of attention. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 57, 315–320. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.57.2.315

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

DeChenne, T. K., and Moody, A. J. (1988). Boredom: theory and therapy. Psychother. Patient 3, 17–29. doi: 10.1300/J358v03n03_03

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Donehower, B. (ed.). (2012). The Birth of Novalis: Friedrich von Hardenberg's Journal of 1797, With Selected Letters and Documents. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.

Google Scholar

Dostoevsky, F. (1962). The Possessed. (Trans. A. R. MacAndrew) New York, NY: New American Library.

Google Scholar

Eastwood, J. D., Frischen, A., Fenske, M. J., and Smilek, D. (2012). The Unengaged mind defining boredom in terms of attention. Perspect. Psychol. Sci. 7, 482–495. doi: 10.1177/1745691612456044

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Elpidorou, A. (forthcoming). “The significance of boredom: a sartrean reading,” in Philosophy of Mind and Phenomenology, eds D. Dahlstrom, A. Elpidorou, and W. Hopp (New York, NY: Routledge).

Google Scholar

Fahlman, S. A., Mercer, K. B., Gaskovski, P., Eastwood, A. E., and Eastwood, J. D. (2009). Does a lack of meaning cause boredom? Results from psychometric, longitudinal, and experimental analyses. J. Soc. Clin. Psychol. 28, 307–340. doi: 10.1521/jscp.2009.28.3.307

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Fahlman, S. A., Mercer-Lynn, K. B., Flora, D. B., and Eastwood, J. D. (2013). Development and validation of the multidimensional state boredom scale. Assessment 20, 68–85. doi: 10.1177/1073191111421303

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Farmer, R., and Sundberg, N. D. (1986). Boredom proneness–the development and correlates of a new state. J. Pers. Assess. 50, 4–17.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | Google Scholar

Fenichel, O. (1953). “On the psychology of boredom,” in The Collected Papers of Otto Fenichel, Vol. 1, ed O. Fenichel (New York, NY: W. W. Norton), 292–302.

Google Scholar

Fisher, C. D. (1993). Boredom at work: a neglected concept. Hum. Relat. 46, 395–417. doi: 10.1177/001872679304600305

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Fromm, E. (1990). The Sane Society. New York, NY: H. Holt.

Google Scholar

Gasper, K., and Middlewood, B. L. (2014). Approaching novel thoughts: understanding why elation and boredom promote associative thought more than distress and relaxation. J. Exp. Soc. Psychol. 52, 50–57. doi: 10.1016/j.jesp.2013.12.007

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Geiwitz, P. (1966). Structure of boredom. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 3, 592–600. doi: 10.1037/h0023202

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Goldberg, Y. K., Eastwood, J. D., LaGuardia, J., and Danckert, J. (2011). Boredom: an emotional experience distinct from apathy, anhedonia, or depression. J. Soc. Clin. Psychol. 30, 647–666. doi: 10.1521/jscp.2011.30.6.647

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gordon, A., Wilkinson, R., McGrown, A., and Jovanoska, S. (1997). The psychometric properties of the boredom proneness scale: an examination of its validity. Psychol. Stud. 42, 85–97.

Hartocollis, P. (1972). Time as a dimension of affects. J. Am. Psychoanal. Assoc. 20, 92–108. doi: 10.1177/000306517202000104

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Healy, S. D. (1984). Boredom, Self, and Culture. Rutherford, NJ: Fairleigh Dickinson University Press.

Heine, S. J., Proulx, T., and Vohs, K. D. (2006). The meaning maintenance model: on the coherence of social motivations. Pers. Soc. Psychol. Rev. 10, 88–110. doi: 10.1207/s15327957pspr1002_1

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hill, A. B., and Perkins, R. E. (1985). Towards a model of boredom. Br. J. Psychol. 76, 235–240. doi: 10.1111/j.2044-8295.1985.tb01947.x

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kass, S. J., Vodanovich, S. J., and Callander, A. (2001). State-trait boredom: the relationship to absenteeism, tenure and job satisfaction. J. Bus. Psychol. 16, 317–327. doi: 10.1023/A:1011121503118

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kierkegaard, S. (1987). Either/Or, Part I. (Edited and Translated by Howard V. Hong and Edna H. Hong) Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Lee, C. M., Neighbors, C., and Woods, B. A. (2007). Marijuana motives: young adults' reasons for using marijuana. Addict. Behav. 32, 1384–1394. doi: 10.1016/j.addbeh.2006.09.010

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Leong, F. T., and Schneller, G. R. (1993). Boredom proneness: temperamental and cognitive components. Pers. Individ. Dif. 14, 233–239. doi: 10.1016/0191-8869(93)90193-7

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

LePera, N. (2011). Relationships between boredom proneness, mindfulness, anxiety, depression, and substance use. New School Psychol. Bull. 8, 15–25.

Google Scholar

Locke, E. A., and Latham, G. J. (1990). A Theory of Goal Setting and Task Performance. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice.

Google Scholar

Malkovsky, E., Merrifield, C., Goldberg, Y., and Danckert, J. (2012). Exploring the relationship between boredom and sustained attention. Exp. Brain Res. 221, 59–67. doi: 10.1007/s00221-012-3147-z

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Martin, M., Sadlo, G., and Stew, G. (2006). The phenomenon of boredom. Qual. Res. Psychol. 3, 193–211. doi: 10.1191/1478088706qrp066oa

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Mercer, K. B., and Eastwood, J. D. (2010). Is boredom associated with problem gambling behaviour? It depends on what you mean by “boredom.” Int. Gambl. Stud. 10, 91–104. doi: 10.1080/14459791003754414

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Mikulas, W., and Vodanovich, S. (1993). The essence of boredom. Psychol. Rec. 43, 3–12.

Google Scholar

Neu, J. (1998). “Boring from within: endogenous versus reactive boredom,” in Emotions in Psychopathology: Theory and Research, eds W. F. Flack and J. D. Laird (London: Oxford University Press), 158–170.

Nietzsche, F. (1974). The Gay Science. (Translated by Walter Kaufmann) New York, NY: Vintage.

Google Scholar

Nisbet, R. (1982). “Boredom,” in Prejudices: a Philosophical Dictionary. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Google Scholar

O'Connor, D. (1967). The phenomena of boredom. J. Existent. 7, 381–399.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | Google Scholar

O'Hanlon, J. F. (1981). Boredom: practical consequences and a theory. Acta Psychol. 49, 53–82.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | Google Scholar

O'Brien, W. (2014). Boredom. Analysis 74, 236–244. doi: 10.1093/analys/anu041

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pascal, B. (2004). Pensées. (Ed. and Trans. R. Ariew) Indianapolis: Hackett.

Perkins, R. E., and Hill, A. B. (1985). Cognitive and affective aspects of boredom. Br. J. Psychol. 76, 221–234. doi: 10.1111/j.2044-8295.1985.tb01946.x

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pessoa, F. (2002). The Book of Disquiet. (Edited and Translated by Richard Zenith) London: Penguin.

Rupp, D. E., and Vodanovich, S. J. (1997). The role of boredom proneness in self-reported anger and aggression. J. Soc. Behav. Pers. 12, 925–936.

Russell, B. (1996). The Conquest of Happiness. New York, NY: W. W. Norton and Company Inc.

Google Scholar

Sackett, A. M., Meyvis, T., Nelson, L. D., Converse, B. A., and Sackett, A. L. (2010). You're having fun when time flies: the hedonic consequences of subjective time progression. Psychol. Sci. 21, 111–117. doi: 10.1177/0956797609354832

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Sansone, C., Weir, C., Harpster, L., and Morgan, C. (1992). Once a boring task always a boring task? Interest as a self-regulatory strategy. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 63, 379–390. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.63.3.379

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Schachtel, E. (2001). Metamorphosis: on the Conflict of Human Development and the Psychology of Creativity. Hillsdale, NJ: Analytic Press.

Google Scholar

Schopenhauer, A. (1966). The World as will and Representation. New York, NY: Dover Publications.

Google Scholar

Seib, H. M., and Vodanovich, S. J. (1998). Cognitive correlates of boredom proneness: the role of private self-consciousness and absorption. J. Psychol. 132, 642–652. doi: 10.1080/00223989809599295

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Sinkewicz, R. E. (2003). Evagrius of Pontus: the Greek Ascetic Corpus. New York; Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Sommers, J., and Vodanovich, S. J. (2000). Boredom proneness: Its relationship to psychological- and physical-health symptoms. J. Clin. Psychol. 56, 149–155. doi: 10.1002/(SICI)1097-4679(200001)56:13.0.CO;2-Y

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Stendhal (1975). Love. London: Penguin.

Svendsen, L. (2004). A Philosophy of Boredom. London: Reaktion Books.

Google Scholar

Thackray, R. I., Bailey, J. P., and Touchstone, R. M. (1975). “Physiological, subjective, and performance correlates of reported boredom and monotony while performing a simulated radar control task,” in Vigilance: Theory, Operational Performance and Physiological Correlates, ed R. R. Mackie Plenum (Boston, MA: Springer), 203–216.

van Tilburg, W. A., and Igou, E. R. (2012). On boredom: lack of challenge and meaning as distinct boredom experiences. Motiv. Emot. 36, 181–194. doi: 10.1007/s11031-011-9234-9

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Vodanovich, S. J. (2003). Psychometric properties of boredom: a review of the literature. J. Psychol. 137, 569–595. doi: 10.1080/00223980309600636

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Wallace, J. C., Kass, S. J., and Stanny, C. J. (2002). The cognitive failures questionnaire revisited: dimensions and correlates. J. Gen. Psychol. 129, 238–256. doi: 10.1080/00221300209602098

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Watt, J. D., and Blanchard, M. J. (1994). Boredom proneness and the need for cognition. J. Res. Pers. 28, 44–51. doi: 10.1006/jrpe.1994.1005

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Watt, J. D., and Vodanovich, S. J. (1999). Boredom proneness and psychosocial development. J. Psychol. 133, 303–314. doi: 10.1080/00223989909599743

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Keywords: boredom, emotion, frustration, restlessness, weariness

Citation: Elpidorou A (2014) The bright side of boredom. Front. Psychol. 5:1245. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2014.01245

Received: 09 September 2014; Accepted: 13 October 2014;
Published online: 03 November 2014.

Edited by:

Jeffrey K. Yoshimi, University of California, Merced, USA

Reviewed by:

John David Eastwood, York University, Canada

Copyright © 2014 Elpidorou. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) or licensor are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: andreas.elpidorou@louisville.edu

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.