Skip to main content

PERSPECTIVE article

Front. Med., 03 June 2024
Sec. Family Medicine and Primary Care
Volume 11 - 2024 | https://doi.org/10.3389/fmed.2024.1377356

The need for a change in medical research thinking. Eco-systemic research frames are better suited to explore patterned disease behaviors

Joachim P. Sturmberg1,2* Jennifer H. Martin1 Francesco Tramonti3 Thomas Kühlein4
  • 1School of Medicine and Public Health, Faculty of Health and Medicine, University of Newcastle, Callaghan, NSW, Australia
  • 2International Society for Systems and Complexity Sciences for Health, Waitsfield, VT, United States
  • 3Department of Mental Health, Azienda USL Toscana Nordovest & Istituto di Psicoterapia Relazionale, Pisa, Italy
  • 4Allgemeinmedizinisches Institut, Universitätsklinikum Erlangen, Erlangen, Germany

Many practicing physicians struggle to properly evaluate clinical research studies – they either simply do not know them, regard the reported findings as ‘truth’ since they were reported in a ‘reputable’ journal and blindly implement these interventions, or they disregard them as having little pragmatic impact or relevance to their daily clinical work. Three aspects for the latter are highlighted: study populations rarely reflect their practice population, the absolute average benefits on specific outcomes in most controlled studies, while statistically significant, are so small that they are pragmatically irrelevant, and overall mortality between the intervention and control groups are unaffected. These observations underscore the need to rethink our research approaches in the clinical context – moving from the predominant reductionist to an eco-systemic research approach will lead to knowledge better suited to clinical decision-making for an individual patient as it takes into account the complex interplay of multi-level variables that impact health outcomes in the real-world setting.

Scientific research traditions

The roots of modern research trace back to the late 17th century with the exploration of the innate (physical) world.

Newton’s research establishing the laws of the innate physical world based on experiments and repeated measurement in the controlled setting of the laboratory. This approach is based on a number of assumptions with limitations in real world applications – firstly, to experiment in the laboratory setting removes all external context that otherwise would impact the experiment (the law of the free fall of an object holds true only in a vacuum); secondly, that one can exactly measure observations (though Gauss showed that repeated measurements always have an error that symmetrically distributes around the mean); and lastly, that repeating the same experiment at a later time in a different setting will result in exactly the same outcome.

About a century later, Goethe and Humboldt demonstrated that Newton’s laws of the innate world of physics did not apply to the animate world of living beings. To understand and predict their behavior required the simultaneous understanding of their environmental context (1). Furthermore, Pareto observed another important phaenomenon of the animate world, namely that it has a consistent distribution pattern that follows an 80/20 split – now known as the Pareto or inverse power law distribution (2). These observations marked the recognition of the interconnectedness and interdependence inherent in biological systems.

Humboldt is regarded as the founder of systems sciences – the sciences of interconnectedness and interdependence within mechanical and biological systems. In general terms, such systems consist of at least two parts where

• the whole cannot be divided into independent parts,

• each part affects the behavior of the other, and

• the way each part affects the behavior of the system depends on what at least one other part is doing (3).

Biological systems have the added characteristic of being adaptive, i.e., the behavior of one part can change the behavior of all other parts. Over time such changes lead to emergent – marginally stable – system states [homeokinetics (4)] which, in the medical context, we associate with particular diseases and disease severities (Figure 1 – top).

Figure 1
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 1. Comparison of the reductionist and eco-systemic research frames. Note, that the reductionist approach aims to establish clear and repeatable cause-and-effect relationships, whereas the eco-systemic approach aims to gain insight into the dynamics that result in patterned outcomes. Understanding what “caused” an observed pattern (looking backwards) will allow clinicians to use the “pattern specific” interventions best suited to this patient (looking forward). The table provides research questions that can be best answered within each research frame (the selected references only relate to the nature of research questions rather than the differences in research methodology).

Mechanistic vs. eco-systemic research questions

There is a basic difference between physical and biological/social research questions. Physics is concerned with explaining cause-and-effect relationships in the innate world whereas biological/social sciences focus on understanding the emergent structural and behavioral phenomena in nature. While physics rightly focuses on researching mechanisms through a reductionist research paradigm, biological/social sciences should adopt an eco-systemic approach to understand the ways living beings ‘behave’ and constantly adapt at all scales of organization within their changing environments. Biological/social sciences should not only concern themselves with the structure and dynamics of ‘biological/social systems’, but more importantly with finding meaning or making sense of those eco-systemic interactions (5, 6).

Medicine is not a science, it is a praxis (7). Clinicians use those scientific results that as good as possible apply to the individual. Given the endless biological/social variability between individuals and their highly variable living environments, they can never deliver perfectly predictable outcomes. Despite these variabilities, our interventions almost always result in one of a number of limited (i.e., not infinite) familiar patterns of outcomes.

The early successes of medicine arose mainly from the insights of reductionist research that explained the ‘simple’ cause-and-effect mechanisms of then common and life-shortening infectious diseases. However, 21st century medicine mostly struggles with chronic and complex diseases whose successful management demands a systemic understanding of the ‘complex’ interactions amongst the multiple variables from across the different scales of organization.

Put pragmatically, studying the effect of a defined antibiotic on a defined bacterium, an antihypertensive on blood pressure changes, or an antidepressant on a change in mood/anxiety scores in the laboratory would rightly be best done using the reductionist cause-and-effect research approach. However, many of these findings produced in the highly controlled laboratory environment are not reproduced in ‘real world’ clinical trial settings.

Clinically relevant questions necessitate systemic research approaches focused on patient relevant outcomes like:

• Does a new antibiotic work safely in people, and if so, what is the right dose for a particular person?

• Does lowering blood pressure prevent heart attacks or strokes, and if so, how much blood pressure reduction for an individual patient reduces his/her absolute risk of an event?

• Which type/combination of therapy/ies is best to recover from trauma or loss, and how does that vary amongst people from different social/ethnic backgrounds?

• Whom does a particular population-based prevention intervention benefit, and what are the issues that make it fail in others?

In the laboratory setting, research typically focuses narrowly on one-to-one relationships in the absence of any other contextual constraints (8). What may work well in the deliberately chosen context-free laboratory setting does not necessarily also work as a clinical intervention in diverse clinical settings. By their very nature clinical events are caused by a multitude of interacting factors. Clinical interventions cause one-to-many interactions simultaneously affecting physiological, environmental as well as sense-making/coping systems. Put succinctly, one-to-many relationships cannot be studied by ‘squeezing’ them into ‘sanitized’ one-to-one methodologies (8).

The bottom section of Figure 1 - bottom provides contrasting examples of research questions that either focus on mechanistic cause-and-effect problems or seek to gain insights and understandings of the complex interconnected and interdependent one-to-many cause-and-effect dynamics impacting people’s health.

Finding the cause vs. understanding heterogenous outcomes

Researching a cause-and-effect problem like determing whether ‘a new antibiotic kills a bacterium in vitro’ falls within the Newtonian research paradigm. It requires repeating the same experiment to determine the reliability of observations.

In contrast research to understand observable differences, i.e., patterns, related to a particular phaenomenon [e.g., blood sugar dynamics in insulin-dependent diabetics (29), or experiencing significant diabetes symptoms despite adequate blood sugar control (30)] requires a different approach. Patterns emerge depending on the interactions and combinations of several contributing variables. Pattern analysis techniques like cluster (31) or network (32) analysis can identify which combinations and interactions lead to each of the observed outcomes of interest, and may guide further research in understanding their ‘causal pathways.’ Figure 1 contrasts the differences between the two frames, and Figure 2 illustrates how cluster analysis techniques can inform the management of coronary artery disease (33).

Figure 2
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 2. Patterns associated with cardiovascular disease outcomes (33). The comparisons should be read across the domains as well as columns. A few notable observations should be highlighted (some are well-known): education and income are associated with better outcomes; a diagnosis of diabetes is associated with greater coronary artery disease burden; CRP levels are high in the oldest multi-morbid and diabetes effected multi-ethnic cluster, while LDL levels are remarkably similar across the 4 clusters; 3-vessel disease is age and co-morbidity burden associated; medication adherence appears to have little impact on disease severity and both, composite and all-cause mortality outcomes. Composite cardiovascular and all-cause mortality outcomes are associated with age and co-morbidities, whereas medication neglect and positive health behaviors have paradoxical associations with composite cardiovascular but no all-cause mortality associations. The difference in coronary revascularization in the latter two clusters may indicate provider bias – non-adherence to medical protocols makes those less deserving, while the health-conscious behavior ones overly deserving of interventions. Redrawn from data of 1329 participants (total of 155 variables) by: Flores et al. (33). BMI, body mass index; CABG, coronary artery bypass graft; CAD, coronary artery disease; CRP, C-reactive protein; LDL, low-density lipoprotein; MI, myocardial infarction; PAD, peripheral artery disease; PCI, percutaneous coronary intervention; MACCE, composite of myocardial infarction, stroke, coronary and/or peripheral revascularization.

How to measure clinically relevant outcomes?

Clinically meaningful eco-systemic outcome measures can only be direct measures of endpoints such as hospitalizations, mortality or quality-of-life, resulting in so called ‘patient-oriented evidence that matters’ (POEM) (34). Clinical research frequently relies on indirect (‘surrogate’) outcome measures in the form of ‘biomarkers’ like laboratory measures and radiological quantifications that are assumed to indicate ‘clinically meaningful’ outcomes (34) or a combination of very different clinical (‘composite’) outcomes that tend to overstate benefits (35) (in this context one should consider Goodhart’s law1). However, even though biomarkers may align with pathophysiology of disease, they often fail to reliably predict effects on a clinically meaningful endpoint. For example, clinical trials of lowering the biomarker LDL has had at best tenuous impact on overall survival (36). Even more difficult to define are meaningful outcome measures for psychological/psychotherapeutic interventions – symptom reduction/remission, while common outcome measures, are highly subjective (37) with patients taking what they think and feel most relevant for their lives (38). And finally, the magnitude of an outcome is sensitive to the characteristics of the study population – while an intervention may have only a small benefit at a community level it may result in more people benefiting than the same intervention targeting a high risk cohort (39).

Hence, the question we really need to answer is: which patient in which context will most likely benefit from an intervention in a subjective and objective way?

Implications

Research, regardless of its methodology and rigor, provides additional data rather than information or knowledge (40). Statistics indicate the probability that – at the population level – these data correlate with particular population observations. However, statistical correlation does not equate to causation. Statistical correlation can only infer a potential causal relationship with a certain probability, and only if the relationship is based on a strong pathophysiologic rationale (41, 42). Hence, it is the researcher’s responsibility to provide critical contextual interpretation of new data to justify their integration to existing understandings. As clinicians we must consider the new understandings in relation to their applicability at the individual/population level, but most importantly, in their unique contexts. And finally, research cannot relieve us from the task of making decisions and being responsible for them.

Knowing the ‘study patient

It is critical to appreciate that there is no ‘prototypical’ patient who can guide clinical practice. The randomized controlled trial provides crude information about the outcome differences of the ‘average patient’ in a study cohort receiving an active versus a placebo intervention. Observed differences, even when statistically significant, generally only have a very small pragmatic (or absolute) benefit. An intervention that helps 1 in 2 average patients (NNT = 2) is 50% effective and 50% ineffective, one that helps 1 in 20 (NNT = 20) is 5% effective and 95% ineffective, one that helps 1 in 100 (NNT = 100) is 1% effective and 99% ineffective, one that helps 1 in 200 (NNT = 200) is 0.5% effective and 99.5% ineffective, and so forth (43). Put differently, even so-called ‘good medical interventions’ are – pragmatically speaking – ineffective for most patients, and the one benefiting is not identifiable from the data. The same applies to harms which often are not expressed in clearly understandable and comparable terms. Of note, in many cases the increase in intensity of an intervention does not improve outcomes but results in increasing harms, e.g., the so called ‘J’ curve in treating hypertension (44, 45) or the use of non-steroidal anti-inflammatories in acute and chronic pain (46).

Whose interests matter most?

Research, like other societal activities, is shaped by the philosophical (47, 48), political and industry doctrines and vested interests of its time – consider, e.g., Mbeki’s stance on HIV (49), or the regulation of embryonic stem cell research (5052); or industries’ influence on research agenda setting (53), financing, conducting and interpreting research (54), or influencing which type of evidence should be prioritized for policy-making (55).

The reductionist understanding that the ‘statistically significant’ dichotomous outcome difference in a randomized controlled trial implies a ‘mechanistic’ cause-and-effect relationship remains widely, but incorrectly, regarded as providing sufficient evidence to promulgate particular pharmaceutical or biomedical interventions to an affected patient population. This misunderstanding suits industry interests well (56). The typical large-scale multi-national industry funded studies only demonstrate small though statistically significant effects, often limited to surrogate or composite outcomes, which are promoted as seemingly benefiting (the misuse of relative benefit) a large number of people (euphemistically referred to as ‘customers’). The rising trend of accelerated drug approval based on surrogate outcome improvements is of great concern given that more than half of approved drugs do not report confirmatory trial outcomes within the required timeframe causing patient harm and high costs despite uncertain clinical benefit (57, 58).

These observations highlight the significant conflict of commercial versus patient-benefit interest of pharmaceutical/device-maker companies (59) – they have nothing to gain from identifying the small group of patients who will ultimately benefit from a given medication/device (60, 61). Further, applying data from relatively healthy, homogeneous backgrounds to vulnerable patient groups not studied in the trials is fraught. The prevailing focus on biomedical intervention research distracts us to appreciate that greater health improvements are more often achieved by strengthening services that address the social and inequality issues within societies (62, 63).

Can precision-medicine result in better global health?

The precision-medicine movement has recognized the failings of population-based intervention studies and aims to discover more specific interventions at the genome/transcriptome/proteome levels. These are expected to be highly predictable to deliver the desired outcome at the patient level (64, 65). Precision-medicine has demonstrated marked improvements in the treatment of certain cancers and improved pharmacotherapy (e.g., warfarin), but has failed to improve interventions and outcomes for common and multimorbid conditions (66, 67).

The promises of precision-medicine may be more wishful thinking than reality (65, 68, 69). Even changes at the physiological level have systemic effects beyond the correction of a specific genomic, transcriptomic or proteomic abnormality. Furthermore, the simplistic understanding that any such ‘precision’ therapy will have a specific target in human biology is fraught and ignores known physiology and pharmacology. Any drug must overcome basic absorption, distribution and metabolism problems even before it comes close to effectively targeting the cell machinery. Additionally, drug effectiveness changes with variability in cell biology, genetic makeup, genomic expression, and change in cell presentation over time (70). Latest at the metabolomic level will we see divergent systemic behavior and less predictable outcomes. Despite these fundamental reservations, an approach to collate the outcomes of individually targeted precision-medicine interventions has the potential to identify community-wide response patterns, an approach that aligns with the eco-systemic research frame.

The way forward

In conclusion, achieving more predictable medical interventions requires a more comprehensive understanding of which systemic variables, and which contexts, lead to the variety of our observable outcome patterns. Recent systems-focused research has demonstrated improvements in diabetes management (71), the drug treatment of hypertension (72), understanding the treatment of depression (73) and the treatment of brain tumors (74) but is, at this stage, a notable exception in clinical research. More systems-focused studies would significantly contribute to the knowledge required to define which outcome pattern a patient – and especially those with multiple morbidities – most likely will belong to. Understanding the underlying bio-medical, social, emotional and interpersonal features (75) underpinning outcome patterns would then enable us to offer the most likely treatment to remedy the issue of concern.

Learning to cope with uncertainty

One of the challenges to achieving this goal is our psychological need for certainty in clinical decision-making under always uncertain circumstances. The mental frame of evidence-based medicine as outlined by Sackett et al. remains widely seen as the best possible solution – “integrating clinical expertise with the best available external evidence from systematic [meaning clinically relevant] research” (76) in clinical decision-making for this particular patient. However, the best available evidence remains insufficient, which is something that patients and doctors alike should be painfully aware of, but neither are comfortable to acknowledge in a fully open and transparent way. Unwittingly, they collude, in Richard Smith’s words, in a “bogus contract” (77).

Medical education, industry and the media all reinforce the socialization of medicine’s unquestionable grandeur. Collectively we rid ourselves of the discomforts of uncertainty by using the mental trick of “‘causal inference’ as a tool … to determine a cause by observing an effect” (78). We fail to see the circularity in the argument – an ‘observed effect’ suddenly is the new cause for ‘another observed effect’ and so forth (79). Having, what seems to be, a rational argument allows us to confidently justify the widespread use of therapeutic approaches of limited to minimal effectiveness.

Embracing the inherent complexities

While this discourse outlines the philosophical and methodological underpinnings of medical research thinking, it calls for pragmatically considering the inherent complexities facing medical research and practice. From a science perspective, studying biological/social systems with their nonlinear distribution patterns requires different methodological research approaches. From a professional perspective, medical interventions are system-wide interventions, and their impacts always need to be considered across the molecular to environmental scales. From a practitioner perspective, even the most appropriate and most diligent research trial will always only give an approximate answer, and it ultimately at best reduces some degree of a clinician’s uncertainty when having to make decisions in the context of the patient in front of them (80). And from a societal perspective, it challenges the usefulness of medical guidelines as much as the listing and/or public reimbursing of many drugs and medical interventions, like the suppression of ventricular ectopic beats with fleconide (81), the mortality benefits of colorectal cancer screening (82, 83), the effectiveness of molnupiravir on hospitalization or death (84), or knee arthrospcopy for degenerative osteoarthritis (85).

Concluding thoughts

In summary, the reductionist medical research of the late 19th/early 20th century undoubtedly has lead to great benefits in understanding and treating the predominant infectious diseases of the time. However, it failed to achieve the same benefits in relation to the now predominant chronic and multimorbidid conditions affecting our patients. These problems are systemic in nature, i.e., they are the result of interconnected and interdependent activities spanning from the gene to the societal level. From a pragmatic perspective, we need to firstly shift our way of thinking toward an eco-systemic frame, and secondly, need to further develop the as yet embryonic eco-systemic research tools to find those solutions that allow us to offer the most likely beneficious approaches to each of our patients. And lastly, there is an urgent need to re-orientate our undergraduate medical courses to develop critical analytic thinking, and to teach our post graduate specialty trainees a wide range of research methodologies beyond the RCT.

Data availability statement

The original contributions presented in the study are included in the article/supplementary material, further inquiries can be directed to the corresponding author/s.

Author contributions

JS: Writing – review & editing, Writing – original draft, Visualization, Resources, Conceptualization. JM: Writing – review & editing, Writing – original draft, Conceptualization. FT: Writing – review & editing, Writing – original draft, Conceptualization. TK: Writing – review & editing, Writing – original draft, Conceptualization.

Funding

The author(s) declare that no financial support was received for the research, authorship, and/or publication of this article.

Conflict of interest

The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Publisher’s note

All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article, or claim that may be made by its manufacturer, is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.

Footnotes

1. ^When a measure becomes a target, it ceases to be a good measure.

References

1. Wulf, A. The invention of nature. Alexander von Humboldt's New World. New York: Alfred A. Knopf (2015).

Google Scholar

2. Pareto, V. Cours D'économie Politique. Lausanne, Paris: F. Rouge (1897).

Google Scholar

3. Ackoff, RL, and Gharajedaghi, J. Reflections on systems and their models. Syst Res. (1996) 13:13–23. doi: 10.1002/(SICI)1099-1735(199603)13:1<13::AID-SRES66>3.0.CO;2-O

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

4. Yates, FE. Homeokinetics/Homeodynamics: a physical heuristic for life and complexity. Ecol Psychol. (2008) 20:148–79. doi: 10.1080/10407410801977546

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

5. Bronfenbrenner, U. Toward an experimental ecology of human development. Am Psychol. (1977) 32:513–31. doi: 10.1037/0003-066X.32.7.513

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

6. Preiser, R, Biggs, R, De Vos, A, and Folke, C. Social-ecological systems as complex adaptive systems: organizing principles for advancing research methods and approaches. Ecol Soc. (2018) 23:46. doi: 10.5751/ES-10558-230446

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

7. Pellegrino, E, and Thomasma, D. A philosophical basis of medical practice. Towards a philosophy and ethic of the healing professions. New York, Oxford: Oxford University Press (1981).

Google Scholar

8. Sturmberg, JP, and Marcum, JA. From cause and effect to causes and effects. J Eval Clin Pract. (2024) 30:296–308. doi: 10.1111/jep.13814

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

9. Braunwald, E. The treatment of acute myocardial infarction: the past, the present, and the future. Eur Heart J Acute Cardiovasc Care. (2012) 1:9–12. doi: 10.1177/2048872612438026

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

10. Maggioni, AP, Franzosi, MG, Fresco, C, Turazza, F, and Tognoni, G. GISSI trials in acute myocardial infarction: rationale, design, and results. Chest. (1990) 97:146S–50S. doi: 10.1378/chest.97.4_Supplement.146S

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

11. Hochman, JS, Anthopolos, R, Reynolds, HR, Bangalore, S, Xu, Y, O’Brien, SM, et al. Survival after invasive or conservative Management of Stable Coronary Disease. Circulation. (2023) 147:8–19. doi: 10.1161/CIRCULATIONAHA.122.062714

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

12. Damluji, AA, Forman, DE, Wang, TY, Chikwe, J, Kunadian, V, Rich, MW, et al. Management of Acute Coronary Syndrome in the older adult population: a scientific statement from the American Heart Association. Circulation. (2023) 147:e32–62. doi: 10.1161/CIR.0000000000001112

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

13. Hristov, M, and Weber, C. Myocardial infarction and inflammation: lost in the biomarker labyrinth. Circ Res. (2015) 116:781–3. doi: 10.1161/circresaha.115.305919

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

14. Huang, S, and Frangogiannis, NG. Anti-inflammatory therapies in myocardial infarction: failures, hopes and challenges. Br J Pharmacol. (2018) 175:1377–400. doi: 10.1111/bph.14155

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

15. Chambless, DL. Training in and dissemination of empirically-validated psychological treatments: report and recommendations. Clin. Psychol. (1995) 48, 3–23.

Google Scholar

16. Sakaluk, JK, Williams, AJ, Kilshaw, RE, and Rhyner, KT. Evaluating the evidential value of empirically supported psychological treatments (ESTs): a meta-scientific review. J Abnorm Psychol. (2019) 128:500–9. doi: 10.1037/abn0000421

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

17. Borsboom, D. A network theory of mental disorders. World Psychiatry. (2017) 16:5–13. doi: 10.1002/wps.20375

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

18. van Os, J, Guloksuz, S, Vijn, TW, Hafkenscheid, A, and Delespaul, P. The evidence-based group-level symptom-reduction model as the organizing principle for mental health care: time for change? World Psychiatry. (2019) 18:88–96. doi: 10.1002/wps.20609

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

19. Binder, PE. Suffering a healthy life-on the existential dimension of health. Front Psychol. (2022) 13:803792. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2022.803792

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

20. Lundh, LG, and Falkenström, F. Towards a person-oriented approach to psychotherapy research. J Pers Oriented Res. (2019) 5:65–79. doi: 10.17505/jpor.2019.07

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

21. Keyes, CL. Promoting and protecting mental health as flourishing: a complementary strategy for improving national mental health. Am Psychol. (2007) 62:95–108. doi: 10.1037/0003-066x.62.2.95

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

22. Sakuma, M, Iimuro, S, Shinozaki, T, Kimura, T, Nakagawa, Y, Ozaki, Y, et al. Optimal target of LDL cholesterol level for statin treatment: challenges to monotonic relationship with cardiovascular events. BMC Med. (2022) 20:441. doi: 10.1186/s12916-022-02633-5

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

23. Stillemans, G, Paquot, A, Muccioli, GG, Hoste, E, Panin, N, Åsberg, A, et al. Atorvastatin population pharmacokinetics in a real-life setting: influence of genetic polymorphisms and association with clinical response. Clin Transl Sci. (2022) 15:667–79. doi: 10.1111/cts.13185

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

24. Gnant, M, Dueck, AC, Frantal, S, Martin, M, Burstein, HJ, Greil, R, et al. Adjuvant Palbociclib for early breast Cancer: the PALLAS trial results (ABCSG-42/AFT-05/BIG-14-03). J Clin Oncol. (2021) 40:282–93. doi: 10.1200/JCO.21.02554

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

25. Thorlund, JB, Juhl, CB, Roos, EM, and Lohmander, LS. Arthroscopic surgery for degenerative knee: systematic review and meta-analysis of benefits and harms. BMJ. (2015) 350:h2747. doi: 10.1136/bmj.h2747

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

26. Weghuber, D, Barrett, T, Barrientos-Pérez, M, Gies, I, Hesse, D, Jeppesen, OK, et al. Once-weekly Semaglutide in adolescents with obesity. N Engl J Med. (2022) 387:2245–57. doi: 10.1056/NEJMoa2208601

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

27. Stanford, FC, Tauqeer, Z, and Kyle, TK. Media and its influence on obesity. Curr Obes Rep. (2018) 7:186–92. doi: 10.1007/s13679-018-0304-0

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

28. Group TCR. Community intervention trial for smoking cessation (COMMIT): II. Changes in adult cigarette smoking prevalence. Am J Public Health. (1995) 85:193–200. doi: 10.2105/AJPH.85.2.193

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

29. Ahlqvist, E, Storm, P, Käräjämäki, A, Martinell, M, Dorkhan, M, Carlsson, A, et al. Novel subgroups of adult-onset diabetes and their association with outcomes: a data-driven cluster analysis of six variables. Lancet Diabetes Endocrinol. (2018) 6:361–9. doi: 10.1016/s2213-8587(18)30051-2

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

30. Nielsen, ABS, Gannik, D, Siersma, V, and de Fine, ON. The relationship between HbA1c level, symptoms and self-rated health in type 2 diabetic patients. Scand J Prim Health Care. (2011) 29:157–64. doi: 10.3109/02813432.2011.585542

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

31. Frades, I, and Matthiesen, R. Overview on techniques in cluster analysis. Methods Mol Biol. (2010) 593:81–107. doi: 10.1007/978-1-60327-194-3_5

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

32. Hevey, D. Network analysis: a brief overview and tutorial. Health Psychol Behav Med. (2018) 6:301–28. doi: 10.1080/21642850.2018.1521283

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

33. Flores, AM, Schuler, A, Eberhard, AV, Olin, JW, Cooke, JP, Leeper, NJ, et al. Unsupervised learning for automated detection of coronary artery disease subgroups. J Am Heart Assoc. (2021) 10:e021976. doi: 10.1161/JAHA.121.021976

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

34. Rosser, W, Slawson, D, and Shaughnessy, A. Information mastery: Evidence based family medicine. New York: Decker Inc (2004).

Google Scholar

35. Ferreira-González, I, Permanyer-Miralda, G, Domingo-Salvany, A, Busse, JW, Heels-Ansdell, D, Montori, VM, et al. Problems with use of composite end points in cardiovascular trials: systematic review of randomised controlled trials. BMJ. (2007) 334:786. doi: 10.1136/bmj.39136.682083.AE

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

36. Byrne, P, Demasi, M, Jones, M, Smith, SM, O'Brien, KK, and DuBroff, R. Evaluating the association between low-density lipoprotein cholesterol reduction and relative and absolute effects of statin treatment: a systematic review and Meta-analysis. JAMA Intern Med. (2022) 182:474–81. doi: 10.1001/jamainternmed.2022.0134

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

37. Adler, JM, Skalina, LM, and McAdams, DP. The narrative reconstruction of psychotherapy and psychological health. Psychother Res. (2008) 18:719–34. doi: 10.1080/10503300802326020

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

38. Sprenkle, DH, Davis, SD, and Lebow, JL. Common factors in couple and family therapy: The overlooked foundation for effective practice. New York and London: Guilford Press (2009).

Google Scholar

39. Rose, G. Sick individuals and sick populations. Int J Epidemiol. (2001) 30:427–32. doi: 10.1093/ije/30.3.427

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

40. Sturmberg, JP. Knowledge translation in healthcare – towards understanding its true complexities; comment on “using complexity and network concepts to inform healthcare knowledge translation”. Int J Health Policy Manag. (2018) 7:455–8. doi: 10.15171/ijhpm.2017.111

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

41. Howick, J, Glasziou, P, and Aronson, JK. Evidence-based mechanistic reasoning. J R Soc Med. (2010) 103:433–41. doi: 10.1258/jrsm.2010.100146

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

42. Howick, J. Exposing the vanities—and a qualified defense—of mechanistic reasoning in health care decision making. Philos Sci. (2011) 78:926–40. doi: 10.1086/662561

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

43. Bogaty, P, and Brophy, J. Numbers needed to treat (needlessly?). Lancet. (2005) 365:1307–8. doi: 10.1016/S0140-6736(05)61025-2

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

44. Messerli, FH, and Panjrath, GS. The J-curve between blood pressure and coronary artery disease or essential hypertension: exactly how essential? J Am Coll Cardiol. (2009) 54:1827–34. doi: 10.1016/j.jacc.2009.05.073

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

45. Cardoso, CRL, and Salles, GF. Associations between achieved ambulatory blood pressures and its changes with adverse outcomes in resistant hypertension: was there a J-curve for ambulatory blood pressures? Hypertension. (2021) 77:1895–905. doi: 10.1161/hypertensionaha.121.17200

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

46. Gøtzsche, PC. Non-steroidal anti-inflammatory drugs. BMJ. (2000) 320:1058–61. doi: 10.1136/bmj.320.7241.1058

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

47. Greenhalgh, T, Howick, J, and Maskrey, N. Evidence based medicine: a movement in crisis? BMJ. (2014) 348:g3725. doi: 10.1136/bmj.g3725

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

48. Kaushik, V, and Walsh, CA. Pragmatism as a research paradigm and its implications for social work research. Soc. Sci. (2019) 8. doi: 10.3390/socsci8090255

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

49. Liverani, M, Hawkins, B, and Parkhurst, JO. Political and institutional influences on the use of evidence in public health policy. PLoS One. (2013) 8:e77404. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0077404

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

50. Annas, GJ, Caplan, A, and Elias, S. Stem cell politics, ethics and medical progress. Nat Med. (1999) 5:1339–41. doi: 10.1038/70900

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

51. Karch, A. Vertical diffusion and the policy-making process: the politics of embryonic stem cell research. Polit Res Q. (2010) 65:48–61. doi: 10.1177/1065912910385252

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

52. Stadelmann, D, and Torgler, B. Voting on embryonic stem cell research: citizens more supportive than politicians. PLoS One. (2017) 12:e0170656. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0170656

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

53. Akl, EA, and Khamis, AM. The intersections of industry with the health research enterprise. Health Res Policy Syst. (2019) 17:53. doi: 10.1186/s12961-019-0457-7

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

54. Siena, LM, Papamanolis, L, Siebert, MJ, Bellomo, RK, and Ioannidis, JPA. Industry involvement and transparency in the most cited clinical trials, 2019-2022. JAMA Netw Open. (2023) 6:e2343425. doi: 10.1001/jamanetworkopen.2023.43425

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

55. Fabbri, A, Lai, A, Grundy, Q, and Bero, LA. The influence of industry sponsorship on the research agenda: a scoping review. Am J Public Health. (2018) 108:e9–e16. doi: 10.2105/ajph.2018.304677

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

56. Onakpoya, IJ, Spencer, EA, Thompson, MJ, and Heneghan, CJ. Effectiveness, safety and costs of orphan drugs: an evidence-based review. BMJ Open. (2015) 5:e007199. doi: 10.1136/bmjopen-2014-007199

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

57. Deshmukh, AD, Kesselheim, AS, and Rome, BN. Timing of confirmatory trials for drugs granted accelerated approval based on surrogate measures from 2012 to 2021. JAMA Health Forum. (2023) 4:e230217. doi: 10.1001/jamahealthforum.2023.0217

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

58. Gellad, WF, and Kesselheim, AS. Accelerated approval and expensive drugs - a challenging combination. N Engl J Med. (2017) 376:2001–4. doi: 10.1056/NEJMp1700446

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

59. Cohen, D. Cancer drugs: high price, uncertain value. BMJ. (2017) 359:j4543. doi: 10.1136/bmj.j4543

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

60. Tonelli, MR. Conflict of interest in clinical practice. Chest. (2007) 132:664–70. doi: 10.1378/chest.07-0315

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

61. Chimonas, S, Mamoor, M, Zimbalist, SA, Barrow, B, Bach, PB, and Korenstein, D. Mapping conflict of interests: scoping review. BMJ. (2021) 375:e066576. doi: 10.1136/bmj-2021-066576

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

62. Hamad, R, and Galea, S. The role of health Care Systems in Bolstering the social safety net to address health inequities in the wake of the COVID-19 pandemic. JAMA. (2022) 328:17–8. doi: 10.1001/jama.2022.10160

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

63. Marmot, M. The health gap: doctors and the social determinants of health. Scand J Public Health. (2017) 45:686–93. doi: 10.1177/1403494817717448

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

64. National Research Council (US). Committee on a framework for developing a new taxonomy of disease. Toward precision medicine: building a knowledge network for biomedical research and a new taxonomy of disease. Washington, DC: National Academies Press (2011).

Google Scholar

65. Weil, AR. Precision medicine. Health Aff (Millwood). (2018) 37:687. doi: 10.1377/hlthaff.2018.0520

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

66. Seymour, CW, Gomez, H, Chang, C-CH, Clermont, G, Kellum, JA, Kennedy, J, et al. Precision medicine for all? Challenges and opportunities for a precision medicine approach to critical illness. Crit Care. (2017) 21:257. doi: 10.1186/s13054-017-1836-5

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

67. Goetz, LH, and Schork, NJ. Personalized medicine: motivation, challenges, and progress. Fertil Steril. (2018) 109:952–63. doi: 10.1016/j.fertnstert.2018.05.006

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

68. Greenland, P, and Hassan, S. Precision preventive medicine—Ready for prime time? JAMA Intern Med. (2019) 179:605–6. doi: 10.1001/jamainternmed.2019.0142

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

69. Manrai, AK, Patel, CJ, and Ioannidis, JA. In the era of precision medicine and big data, who is normal? JAMA. (2018) 319:1981–2. doi: 10.1001/jama.2018.2009

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

70. Wray, NR, Wijmenga, C, Sullivan, PF, Yang, J, and Visscher, PM. Common disease is more complex than implied by the Core gene Omnigenic model. Cell. (2018) 173:1573–80. doi: 10.1016/j.cell.2018.05.051

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

71. Del Prato, S. Heterogeneity of diabetes: heralding the era of precision medicine. Lancet Diabetes Endocrinol. (2019) 7:659–61. doi: 10.1016/S2213-8587(19)30218-9

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

72. Sundström, J, Lind, L, Nowrouzi, S, Hagström, E, Held, C, Lytsy, P, et al. Heterogeneity in blood pressure response to 4 antihypertensive drugs: a randomized clinical trial. JAMA. (2023) 329:1160–9. doi: 10.1001/jama.2023.3322

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

73. Stone, MB, Yaseen, ZS, Miller, BJ, Richardville, K, Kalaria, SN, and Kirsch, I. Response to acute monotherapy for major depressive disorder in randomized, placebo controlled trials submitted to the US Food and Drug Administration: individual participant data analysis. BMJ. (2022) 378:e067606. doi: 10.1136/bmj-2021-067606

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

74. Bergmann, N, Delbridge, C, Gempt, J, Feuchtinger, A, Walch, A, Schirmer, L, et al. The Intratumoral heterogeneity reflects the Intertumoral subtypes of glioblastoma multiforme: a regional immunohistochemistry analysis. Front Oncol. (2020) 10:494. doi: 10.3389/fonc.2020.00494

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

75. Sturmberg, JP. Health: a personal complex-adaptive state In: JP Sturmberg and CM Martin, editors. Handbook of systems and complexity in health. New York: Springer (2014). 231–42.

Google Scholar

76. Sackett, D, Rosenberg, W, Gray, J, Haynes, R, and Richardson, W. Evidence based medicine: what it is and what it isn't. Br Med J. (1996) 312:71–2. doi: 10.1136/bmj.312.7023.71

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

77. Smith, R. Death and the bogus contract between doctors and patients. BMJ. (2022) 377:o1415. doi: 10.1136/bmj.o1415

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

78. Pearl, J, and Mackenzie, D. The book of why: the new science of cause and effect. Boston: Basic Books (2018).

Google Scholar

79. Ackoff, RL. Science in the systems age: Beyond IE, OR, and MS. Oper Res. (1973) 21:661–71.

Google Scholar

80. Cassell, EJ. The sorcerer's broom: medicine's rampant technology. Hast Cent Rep. (1993) 23:32. doi: 10.2307/3562922

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

81. Investigators, TCASTC. Preliminary report: effect of Encainide and flecainide on mortality in a randomized trial of arrhythmia suppression after myocardial infarction. N Engl J Med. (1989) 321:406–12. doi: 10.1056/NEJM198908103210629

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

82. Bretthauer, M, Løberg, M, Wieszczy, P, Kalager, M, Emilsson, L, Garborg, K, et al. Effect of colonoscopy screening on risks of colorectal cancer and related death. N Engl J Med. (2022) 387:1547–56. doi: 10.1056/NEJMoa2208375

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

83. Johansson, M. The questionable value of colorectal cancer screening. BMJ. (2023) 380:200. doi: 10.1136/bmj.p200

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

84. Merck Pharmaceuticals. Merck and ridgeback biotherapeutics provide update on new clinical and non-clinical studies of LAGEVRIO™ (molnupiravir). (2022). Available at: https://www.merck.com/news/merck-and-ridgeback-biotherapeutics-provide-update-on-new-clinical-and-non-clinical-studies-of-lagevrio-molnupiravir/

Google Scholar

85. O'Connor, D, Johnston, RV, Brignardello-Petersen, R, Poolman, RW, Cyril, S, Vandvik, PO, et al. Arthroscopic surgery for degenerative knee disease (osteoarthritis including degenerative meniscal tears). Cochrane Database Syst Rev. (2022) CD014328. doi: 10.1002/14651858.CD014328

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Keywords: systems thinking, research design, philosophy of science, uncertainty, evidence-based medicine, complexity science, philosophy of medicine, complexity thinking

Citation: Sturmberg JP, Martin JH, Tramonti F and Kühlein T (2024) The need for a change in medical research thinking. Eco-systemic research frames are better suited to explore patterned disease behaviors. Front. Med. 11:1377356. doi: 10.3389/fmed.2024.1377356

Received: 27 January 2024; Accepted: 14 May 2024;
Published: 03 June 2024.

Edited by:

Rahul Kashyap, WellSpan Health, United States

Reviewed by:

Ankit Virmani, Google, United States
Archana Reddy Bongurala, Omni Family Health, United States

Copyright © 2024 Sturmberg, Martin, Tramonti and Kühlein. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Joachim P. Sturmberg, jp.sturmberg@gmail.com

ORCID: Joachim P. Sturmberg, orcid.org/0000-0002-2219-6281
Jennifer H. Martin, orcid.org/0000-0002-8614-0199
Francesco Tramonti, orcid.org/0000-0003-4233-4423
Thomas Kühlein, orcid.org/0000-0003-2169-776X

Download