Skip to main content

HYPOTHESIS AND THEORY article

Front. Psychol., 02 December 2010
Sec. Quantitative Psychology and Measurement

Matrices Satisfying Regular Minimality

  • 1 Faculty of Statistics, Dortmund Technical University, Dortmund, Germany
  • 2 Department of Psychological Sciences, Purdue University, West Lafayette, IN, USA

A matrix of discrimination measures (discrimination probabilities, numerical estimates of dissimilarity, etc.) satisfies Regular Minimality (RM) if every row and every column of the matrix contains a single minimal entry, and an entry minimal in its row is minimal in its column. We derive a formula for the proportion of RM-compliant matrices among all square matrices of a given size and with no tied entries. Under a certain “meta-probabilistic” model this proportion can be interpreted as the probability with which a randomly chosen matrix turns out to be RM-compliant.

1. Preliminaries

Given a real-valued measure of discriminability m(x, y) between stimuli y Y and stimuli x X, Regular Minimality (RM) means that

[A] for every x X one can uniquely find a matching stimulus in Y, defined as the y Y which is least discriminable from x among all stimuli in Y;

[B] for every y Y one can uniquely find a matching stimulus in X, defined as the x X which is least discriminable from y among all stimuli in X;

[C] if y matches (is the match for) x in the sense [A], then x matches (is the match for) y in the sense [B].

The properties [A] and [B] should be qualified as follows. Two stimuli x1, x2X are considered equivalent if m(x1, y) = m(x2, y) for every y Y; analogously, y1, y2Y are equivalent if m(x, y1) = m(x, y2) for every x X. The uniqueness requirement in [A] and [B] should be taken up to this equivalence relation: the set of matching stimuli for any given x X is nonempty and consists of pairwise equivalent Y-stimuli, and the same holds for the set of X-stimuli matching a given y Y. Another way of stating this is to say that [A] and [B] should hold after any two equivalent stimuli, in both X and Y, have been identically labeled.

The RM principle was proposed in Dzhafarov (2002b) together with the related notion of an observation area. Note that x and y stimuli being compared belong to different sets, X and Y. This reflects the difference between two observation areas: even if x and y have the same value (say, they are line segments of the same length), they must occupy different spatial and/or temporal positions to be perceived as two distinct stimuli (see, e.g., Dzhafarov and Colonius, 2006). So x and y should be designated as, say, x = (5 cm, left) and y = (5 cm, right), and with this rigorous designation X and Y cannot even overlap. Moreover, even the values of the elements of X and Y (ignoring the difference in the observation areas) need not be the same. Thus, in the probability matrix below RM is satisfied in the simplest form (the minima on the main diagonal) even though the values of the stimuli in the first observation area (rows) and in the second one (columns) are not the same:

yes

The distinction between two observation areas should be kept in mind for a correct application of the symmetry requirement, [C]. If in the statement “y matches x” the stimuli x and y exchange places, their values do so together with their respective observation areas. Thus, if the two observation areas are designated as “presented first” and “presented second” (chronologically within a trial), then the requirement [C] should be read as

[C, special case] if y, presented second, matches x, presented first, then x, presented first, matches y, presented second,

and not as

[C-look-alike, garbled] if y, presented second, matches x, presented first, then x, presented second, matches y, presented first.

In the latter statement, the pair (x, y) in the antecedent is different from the pair (x, y) in the consequent, creating thereby a confusion. A corrected version of [C-look-alike, garbled] could be

[C-look-alike, corrected] if a stimulus with value v2 when presented second matches a stimulus with value v1 presented first, then the stimulus with value v1 when presented second matches the stimulus with value v2 presented first.

Unlike [C-look-alike, garbled] this statement makes sense, but it is generally empirically false due to what is known as time-order error (more generally, constant error, see Dzhafarov and Colonius, 2006). By contrast, there seems to be no empirical evidence against [C, special case] or any other form of [C], which makes it possible to propose RM as a fundamental principle of pairwise comparisons (Dzhafarov, 2002b).

The notion of RM has been elaborated in Dzhafarov (2003), Dzhafarov and Colonius (2006), and Kujala and Dzhafarov (2008, 2009). It turns out to have nontrivial consequences for a variety of issues of traditional importance, ranging from Thurstonian-type modeling (see, e.g., Dzhafarov, 2006, in response to Ennis, 2006) to the “probability-distance” hypothesis (Dzhafarov, 2002a) to Fechnerian Scaling (see, e.g., Dzhafarov and Colonius, 2007) to matching-by-adjustment procedures (Dzhafarov and Perry, 2010) to the comparative version of the ancient “sorites” paradox (Dzhafarov and Dzhafarov, 2010a,b). In the latter two references the notion of RM (under the more general designation of “regular well-matched stimulus space”) was extended to an arbitrary set of observations areas. In the present work, however, we do not need to go beyond two fixed observation areas.

2. Regular Minimality for Rank Order Matrices Without Ties

In this paper we deal with the case when the stimulus sets are finite,

X = {x1,…,xn}, Y = {y1,…,yn},

and the discrimination function m(x, y) can be viewed as a matrix M = {mij}, i, j ∈ {1,…,n}. Clearly, a matrix which is not square cannot comply with RM (because each x has a unique y-match for which x is a unique match, and vice versa).

Convention 2.1. Henceforth we will assume that every matrix, unless otherwise specified, has pairwise distinct entries (contains no tied entries).

With this convention, the properties [A] and [B] are satisfied trivially (every row and every column has a unique minimal entry), and RM is reduced to the property [C] which now acquires the form

[RM = C] an entry is minimal in its column if it is minimal in its row.

The “column” and “row” in this statement can be exchanged and the statement above strengthened.

Lemma 2.2. In an RM-compliant matrix, an entry is minimal in its column if and only if it is minimal in its row.

Proof. To prove the “only if” part, let h be the mapping {1,…,n} → {1,…,n} defined by mi,h(i) being the minimum entry in row i ∈ {1,…,n}. This mapping is injective, because if there were some rows i i′ with h(i) = h(i′), then mij would be the minimum entry in row i, mij the minimum entry in row i′, whence the column h(i) would have to have two minimum entries. Since an injection {1,…,n} → {1,…,n} is also surjective, it follows that for every column j, yes is the minimum entry in both the row h−1(j) and the column j, and the statement of the lemma follows from the uniqueness of this minimum value. ☐

In this paper we derive the formula for the proportion of RM-compliant matrices among all matrices with a given set of (pairwise distinct) entries. In other words, given any set V of n2 distinct values of a discriminability measure (real numbers), we consider all n2! ways of placing these values in n2 cells of an n × n matrix and count the number of matrices which are RM-compliant. The result is, obviously, invariant with respect to the set V. With no loss of generality, therefore we can assume that the matrices are filled with integers {1,…,n2} representing the ordinal positions of the elements of any possible set V. We will refer to these integer-valued matrices as rank order matrices (without ties), and their elements will be referred to as ranks.

Definition 2.3. A rank order matrix M is said to represent a matrix M′ (of the same size) if mij < mij in yes M implies in M′, for any two cells (i, j) and (i, j′).

Remark 2.4. Due to the bijective correspondence between the entries of M and M′, the “if” in this definition can be replaced or complemented with “and only if.”

Intuitively, the proportion of RM-compliant matrices among all rank order matrices of a given size seems to be the answer to the question: how likely is it to obtain a matrix M (not necessarily a rank order one) satisfying RM “by chance”? To explicate this intuition, we can adopt the following “meta-probabilistic” view. Consider the entries of M not as data but as theoretical (population-level) values of a discriminability measure. Assuming that the possible values for mij (i, j ∈{1,…,n}) form a set of reals 𝕊 of a positive Lebesgue measure (e.g., the interval [0, 1], as in the case when the mij’s are probabilities) we can impose on 𝕊 in each cell of the matrix some probability measure. Then we can pose the question of what the product measure is of the volume occupied by the RM-compliant matrices in yes. If one and the same measure μ is imposed on all entries, then all permutations of any given set of entries are equiprobable. The absence of ties among the entries in this approach is ensured by additionally assuming that the probability measure imposed is absolutely continuous with respect to the Lebesgue measure.1 It is intuitively clear (and shown formally in the lemma below) that the product measure in question equals the proportion of the RM-compliant matrices among all possible rank order matrices. We will denote the product measure μ × … × μ (n2 times) by yes.

Lemma 2.5. Let μ be a probability measure imposed on the set 𝕊 of a positive Lebesgue measure in each cell of an n × n matrix. Let μ be absolutely continuous with respect to the Lebesgue measure. Then the set of RM-compliant matrices in yes is yes-measurable and its yes-measure equals the proportion of RM-compliant matrices among all n × n rank order matrices (without ties).

Proof. Since 𝕊 is measurable, so is 𝕊 ∩]x, ∞[ for any real x, and so is

www.frontiersin.org

for any permutation π of (1,…,n2). The yes-measure of 𝔸π is invariant with respect to π, which is obvious from symmetry considerations, or from the computation

www.frontiersin.org

where χ𝕊(x) is the indicator function of 𝕊 on reals and ι the identity permutation. The Lebesgue measure of

www.frontiersin.org

is zero as this set lies within a finite union of (n2 − 1) -dimensional hyperplanes. By absolute continuity of μ, yes Since

www.frontiersin.org

we have

www.frontiersin.org

whence yes for any π. Now, let πRM be the set of all permutations represented by RM-compliant rank order n × n matrices, and let the number of these matrices be Sn. Then

www.frontiersin.org

which proves the lemma. ☐

Obviously, the theoretical values of a discriminability measure (such as probabilities of the response “different”) are not random variables. The measure μ imposed on 𝕊 therefore cannot be interpreted in frequency-related terms. Rather it can be thought of as a distribution of “subjective beliefs.” The assignment of one and the same measure μ to all cells then can be interpreted as a lack of subjective expectations with respect to possible associations between rows and columns. One cannot simply replace theoretical entries in this “meta-probabilistic” interpretation with data and treat μ as representing a hypothetical random variable. For one thing, if the possible set of data points is finite, as it is usually the case, this reinterpretation would necessitate finding a way of dealing with ties, as their probability would then no longer be zero. Most importantly, however, the null hypothesis that all cells of a matrix are generated according to one and the same distribution seems neither justified nor interesting. In another paper (Dzhafarov et al., 2010 under review), we propose both a simple way of dealing with tied entries and a data-analytic interpretation of the proportions of matrices with different degrees of RM-compliance, appropriately defined.

3. Proportion of RM-Compliant Matrices

Convention 3.1. Unless otherwise specified, henceforth every matrix mentioned will be assumed to be a rank order matrix (with no ties, in accordance with Convention 2.1).

Lemma 3.2. Let Mαβ be a matrix obtained from a matrix M by permutations α and β of its rows and columns, respectively. Then Mαβ = Mα′β′ implies (α, β) = (α′, β′).

Proof. Denoting Mαβ = Mα′β′ = M′, the entries mij and yes of M and M′, respectively, are related to each other as

www.frontiersin.org

and

www.frontiersin.org

If (α, β) ≠ (α′, β′) then, for some (i, j), yes and yes would have to be two identical entries in different cells, which is excluded by Convention 2.1. ☐

Lemma 3.3. If a matrix M satisfies RM, then so will any matrix M obtained from M by an arbitrary permutation of its rows and columns.

Proof. By arbitrary permutations α and β of the rows and columns, respectively, we transform M into a matrix M′. Its entries yes are related to the entries mij of M as

www.frontiersin.org

If mij in M is the minimum entry in the row i, then yes in M′ is the minimum entry in the row α(i), as the latter is merely the β-permutation of the row i of M; and if mij in M is the minimum entry in the column j, then yes in M’ is the minimum entry in the column β(j), as the latter is merely the α-permutation of the column j of M. Since permutations are bijective, it follows that the minimum entry in every row (column) in M′ is also the minimum entry in its column (respectively, row). ☐

Lemma 3.4. By appropriately chosen permutations of rows and columns one can bring any RM-compliant matrix M to a special form M′, in which the row and column minima are located on the main diagonal in the increasing order, yes This special form is unique for every M.

Proof. Let i1,…,in be the rows of M arranged in the increasing order of their minima. Let these minima be located in the columns j1,…,jn, respectively. Then the permutations

www.frontiersin.org

and

www.frontiersin.org

are easily seen to yield M′ with the desired properties. The uniqueness statement follows from the uniqueness of the sequences i1,…,in and j1,…,jn. ☐

The procedure is illustrated on the 4 × 4 RM-compliant matrix below, using the permutation of rows α = {1 → 3,2 → 2,3 → 1,4 → 4} and the permutation of columns β = {1 → 1,2 → 4,3 → 2,4 → 3}:

yes

Definition 3.5. Let us refer to RM-compliant matrices in this special form (minima on the diagonal in increasing order) as special matrices.

Lemma 3.6. Denoting by sn the number of n × n special matrices and by Sn the total number of n × n matrices satisfying RM,

www.frontiersin.org

Proof. Any matrix M that can be transformed (in the sense of Lemma 3.4) to a given special matrix M′ can be obtained from this M′ by means of permutations

www.frontiersin.org

and

www.frontiersin.org

The number of permutations α−1 is n! and so is the number of permutations β−1. Since every combination of α−1 and β−1 yields a unique matrix M (by Lemma 3.2), the number of such matrices for a given M′ is (n!)2. The statement of the lemma follows. ☐

As an immediate consequence we obtain

Corollary 3.7. The proportion pn of RM-compliant matrices among all n × n matrices is

www.frontiersin.org

4. Main Theorem

We turn now to computing the number of RM-compliant matrices, Sn (n ≥ 1).

We will make use of the following notion. For k = 1,…,n, we will call the set of cells

www.frontiersin.org

in an n × n matrix M the kth frame (this set is empty for k = 1). Clearly, M is the union of its diagonal entries and its frames. The letters f in the 4 × 4 matrix below indicate its frame cells and the dots fill the corresponding diagonal cells:

yes

Theorem 4.1. The number Sn of n × n RM-compliant matrices is

www.frontiersin.org

where

www.frontiersin.org

Remark 4.2. The combinatorial meaning of cmb(x,y) is the number of permutations of x objects taken y at a time (equivalently, the number of ways y distinct objects can be placed in x placeholders).

Proof. Let the diagonal entries (ranks) in the matrix M have been chosen and arranged as m11 = d1 < … < mnn = dn. We compute the number of ways in which we can fill the off-diagonal entries of M so that RM is satisfied in the special form (mij > di and mij > dj if i j).

The nth frame should be filled by 2(n − 1) ranks chosen from the set of n2dn ranks exceeding dn. The number of such choices is

www.frontiersin.org

None of these choices can violate the special form of RM, because any rank exceeding dn will also exceed any dk for k < n.

For k = 2,…,n − 1, let now all the frames above the kth have been filled without violating the special form of RM. The kth frame then should be filled by 2(k − 1) numbers chosen from the set of n2dk numbers exceeding dk, from which however we should remove all the n2k2 numbers used up to fill in the previous n k frames and diagonal elements. That is, the kth frame can be filled in by (n2dk) − (n2k2) = k2dk numbers taken 2(k − 1) at a time. The number of such choices is

www.frontiersin.org

None of these choices can violate the special form of RM, because any rank exceeding dk will also exceed any dk for k′ < k, and if k′ > k then the choice above is irrelevant. The formula also applies to k = 1, since d1 = 1 (any other placement of 1, the smallest rank in M, would violate RM), and cmb(1 − 1, 2 (1 − 1)) = 1, which is the number of ways to fill the empty first frame.

Since, for any given n-tuple d1 < d2 < … < dn and any k = 1,…,n − 1, the value of cmb(k2dk, 2(k − 1)) does not depend on the fillings of the previous n k frames, the number of ways of filling all n frames of M is

www.frontiersin.org

Then the number of special matrices is

www.frontiersin.org

and the statement of the theorem follows by Lemma 3.6. ☐

5. Computational Algorithm

Here we present the formula of Theorem 4.1 in a form which is less compact but more economic for computational purposes.

For every diagonal element dk we have dkdk−1 + 1 if k > 1 (and d1 ≥ 1); and in order for the multiplicands cmb(k2dk, 2(k− 1)) to be nonzero we should also require that dkk2 − 2(k − 1) for k = 1,…,n. It is easy to see, in particular, that the only values for the ranks d2 and d1 which satisfy these inequalities are 2 and 1, respectively. The formula for the number of special matrices acquires the form

www.frontiersin.org

The number of the arithmetic operations can be further reduced if we rewrite this as

www.frontiersin.org

Algorithm 5.1. The following is a Mathematica™ program for computing precise values of pn:

In[1]:=
cmb[a_, b_] := a!/(a - b)!;
up[c_] := c^2 - 2*c + 2;
F[n_, d_, k_] := F[n, d, k] = If[k < n,
   cmb[k^2 - d, 2*k - 2]* Sum[F[n, d1, k +
    1], {d1, d + 1, up[k + 1]}]];
F[n_, d_, n_] := cmb[n^2 - d, 2*n - 2]
In[2]:=
n = ???; (* ??? to be replaced with the
    desired value of n *)
Print[F[n, 1, 1]*(n!)^2/(n^2)!]

We present the values of pn for n = 2,…,13, rounded to the sixth decimal place:

yes

Under our “meta-probabilistic” interpretation, the table shows that the compliance with RM even for matrices as small as 4 × 4 or 5 × 5 can be considered “unlikely to occur by chance alone.”

Conflict of Interest Statement

The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Acknowledgments

This research has been supported by NSF grant SES 0620446 and AFOSR grant FA9550-09-1-0252 to Purdue University.

Footnote

  1. ^Recall that a measure μ is absolutely continuous with respect to the Lebesgue measure if it is defined on the same sigma algebra, and if the m-measure of a set is zero whenever its Lebesgue measure is zero.

References

Dzhafarov, E. N. (2002a). Multidimensional Fechnerian scaling: probability-distance hypothesis. J. Math. Psychol. 46, 352–374.

CrossRef Full Text

Dzhafarov, E. N. (2002b). Multidimensional Fechnerian scaling: pairwise comparisons, regular minimality, and nonconstant self-similarity. J. Math. Psychol. 46, 583–608.

CrossRef Full Text

Dzhafarov, E. N. (2003). Thurstonian-type representations for “same-different” discriminations: deterministic decisions and independent images. J. Math. Psychol. 47, 208–228.

Dzhafarov, E. N. (2006). On the law of Regular Minimality: reply to Ennis. J. Math. Psychol. 50, 74–93.

Dzhafarov, E. N., and Colonius, H. (2006). “Regular Minimality: a fundamental law of discrimination,” in Measurement and Representation of Sensations, eds H. Colonius and E. N. Dzhafarov (Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum), 1–46.

CrossRef Full Text

Dzhafarov, E. N., and Colonius, H. (2007). Dissimilarity cumulation theory and subjective metrics. J. Math. Psychol. 51, 290–304.

Dzhafarov, E. N., and Dzhafarov, D. D. (2010a). Sorites without vagueness II: comparative sorites. Theoria. 76, 25–53.

CrossRef Full Text

Dzhafarov, E. N., and Dzhafarov, D. D. (2010b). “The sorites paradox: a behavioral approach,” in Mathematical Models for Research on Cultural Dynamics: Qualitative Mathematics for the Social Sciences, eds J. Valsiner and L. Rudolph (Routledge: London), in press.

Dzhafarov, E. N., and Perry, L. (2010). Matching by adjustment: if X matches Y, does Y match X? Front. Quant. Psychol. Meas. 4: 24, 1–16. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2010.00024.

Ennis, D. M. (2006). Sources and influence of perceptual variance: comment on Dzhafarov’s Regular Minimality principle. J. Math. Psychol. 50, 66–73.

Kujala, J. V., and Dzhafarov, E. N. (2008). On minima of discrimination functions. J. Math. Psychol. 52, 116–127.

Kujala, J. V., and Dzhafarov, E. N. (2009). Regular Minimality and Thurstonian-type modeling. J. Math. Psychol. 53, 486–501.

Keywords: discriminability, permutations, regular minimality

Citation: Trendtel M, ÜnlÜ A and Dzhafarov EN (2010) Matrices satisfying regular minimality. Front. Psychology 1:211. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2010.00211

Received: 05 August 2010; Accepted: 05 November 2010;
Published online: 02 December 2010.

Edited by:

Hans Colonius, University of Oldenburg, Germany

Reviewed by:

Jason W. Osborne, North Carolina State University, USA
Judit Antal, College Board, USA

Copyright: © 2010 Trendtel, ÜnlÜ and Dzhafarov. This is an open-access article subject to an exclusive license agreement between the authors and the Frontiers Research Foundation, which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original authors and source are credited.

*Correspondence: Ehtibar N. Dzhafarov, Department of Psychological Sciences, Purdue University, 703 Third Street, West Lafayette, IN 47907, USA. e-mail: ehtibar@purdue.edu

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.