Skip to main content

OPINION article

Front. Hum. Neurosci., 12 April 2019
Sec. Cognitive Neuroscience
Volume 13 - 2019 | https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2019.00115

Neuroergonomics: Where the Cortex Hits the Concrete

  • Department of Psychology, Institute for Simulation and Training, University of Central, Orlando, FL, United States

Introduction

This present article considers the nature and impact of the vital contributions of Raja Parasuraman and the way in which his brain-child–neuroergonomics–has begun to flourish and blossom in our contemporary world. By unlocking the secrets of brain activity and then finding mechanisms and technologies to elaborate such processes more directly into the world, he has provided us with a clear vision for the future of human-machine interaction. However, it always useful to start by consider antitheses. Thus, I begin my present exploration with the view from radical behaviorism, in some ways the opposite side of the coin from neuroergonomics. To behaviorist researchers, particularly if they are motivated by a utilitarian approach to the world, what happens in the brain may be considered of only passing, rather than vital, interest. This is not to say even the most ardent behaviorist denies the reality of cortical events; for that would be to misrepresent their position (see Watson, 1913; Chiesa, 1994). No, the simple fact is that for some such researchers, if you are able to predict, within a reasonable degree of tolerance, what behavioral sequelae derive from a particular set of environmental cues, then the knowledge of the intervening cortical activity can appear to be somewhat superfluous. For behaviorists, externality is all and associated brain states are of only diminished and diminishing concern.

And. in a somewhat analogous manner, this perspective on the (in)utility of an understanding of intervening (neurological) influences is of the same order of the proposal made by the philosopher Berkeley (1710) to support his idea of the non-existence of matter. Berkeley argued that the step of introducing matter as a mediating entity between the mind of God and the mind of man, was superfluous. This “additional,” and presumably unnecessary, step was even potentially insulting to a “perfect” God who would, presumably eschew inelegant and non-optimal strategies. Only a few now really take Berkeley's denial of matter seriously, and similarly few in our modern world would champion a pristine version of radical behaviorism. Certainly not Raja Parasuraman who saw great value in the potential for real-world applications from modern, emerging neuroscientific insights (Parasuraman, 2003). For most of us in the modern neurosciences then, however well the behaviorist's input-output specifications of the purported “black-box” work, like Pandora we still feel impelled to look inside. Berkeley's argument may however, come full circle. For surely a fully functional neuroergonomics will allow that the mind of one person be readily embedded in the perceived reality of all others. Thus, thesis and antithesis can always render some degree of synthesis.

In this brief article, I look at the genesis of Parasuraman's “neuroergonomic” vision, its growth to the present time, and some of the directions it might take in the near and more distant future. While the work evidently represents an homage to Parasuraman himself, it still raises critical points and debatable objections to neuroergonomics, most especially concerning the facile and untrammeled access (interaction) between the personal, private dimensions of thought and their unfiltered externalizations via modern-day, computer-mediated technology. While I do not find myself on the side of the ardent behaviorist with respect to any such philosophical “fence,” it is still reasonable to call for some limits and constraints upon the intimacy of the linkage between the cortex and the computer (and see Hancock, 2017).

The Genesis of Neuroergonomics

While the term neuroergonomics was first coined by Parasuraman, the general idea of linking mind and machine is clearly not original to him (see e.g., Licklider, 1960). The growing degree of communication between humans and technology was inspired by some at the heart of the cognitive revolution.1 These included luminaries such as Craik (1947, 1948) and Broadbent (1958, 1971), in whose direct academic lineage Parasuraman can be found. In one important sense, Parasuraman's course was set when he entered doctoral work under the tutelage of Professor Roy Davies (Parasuraman and Davies, 1976). Between them, and perhaps with more emphasis here on Raja's contribution, they essentially resolved the confusion inherent in the then extant vigilance literature (see e.g., Buckner and McGrath, 1963). This resolution was accomplished through the implementation of the now rightly famous vigilance taxonomy (see Parasuraman, 1979; Davies and Parasuraman, 1982; Hancock, 2017). Yet, Parasuraman's grounding for developing neuroergonomics precedes even this doctoral phase of his career. For, his undergraduate work had been in electrical engineering (EE) and one can, if pushed, argue that neuroscience is one very specialized form of EE. Certainly, the formalizations and models of EE promote an affinity with the neurosciences in many of its forms.

However, beyond speculations on these associations, Raja's choice of research topic and subsequent exploration of vigilance served assuredly as his first formal stride toward the neuroergonomic conception. Clearly challenged by his advisor to clarify the vigilance concept (see e.g., Davies and Tune, 1969), this area of sustained attention has proven to epitomize the marriage of pure science and application in the real-world (see Mackworth, 1948, 1950; Hancock and Warm, 1989; Hancock, 2013). In point of fact, vigilance research emerged from a pure, real-world challenge and the attachment of the term “vigilance” was itself derived from Mackworth's search through then applicable neuroscientific conceptualizations of the time (see Head, 1923; Swash, 2008; see also the work of one of Head's colleagues and advisors, Rivers-Rivers, 1896). Slowly, and some might observe inevitably, Parasuraman's search for a theoretical explanation of the descriptive taxonomy he had distilled, embraced contemporary neuroscientific progress (Parasuraman, 1979). This development was facilitated by Raja's post-doctoral collaboration with Jackson “Jack” Beatty (see Parasuraman and Beatty, 1980). From a present-day perspective, the specific techniques they used, such as Electroencephalography (EEG) and eye movement assessment, might appear to be rather rudimentary, but in the middle to late 1970s they were at the very forefront of cortical exploration (and see e.g., Gath et al., 1983; Berka et al., 2007).

Parasuraman's investigations of advanced human-machine systems, which for him often meant complex aviation technologies (see e.g., Parasuraman et al., 1996; Parasuraman and Manzey, 2010), was accompanied by some very basic and fundamental contributions to the foundations of modern neuroscience (e.g., Parasuraman et al., 1992). Although his efforts in the practical and the theoretical domains can be linked to opportunistic and relevant funding successes, the desire for some form of hybrid sub-discipline was, for Parasuraman, more conceptually driven. Most especially, he became progressively more and more involved in human interaction with automation in which the essential “readiness of the operator to respond” is mediated not merely the success of collaborative interaction but dictated the very form which such interaction would be advised to take (and see Parasuraman and Mouloua, 1996). In part, this perspective perhaps under-estimates the purpose-directed work that he and his neuroscience colleagues conducted, on what might be termed pure “neuroscience inquiries.” Yet, these basic inquiries were at the heart of, and served to temper, the genesis of neuro-ergonomics (Parasuraman and Wilson, 2008).

Having been a longstanding colleague of Parasuraman (e.g., Hancock and Parasuraman, 1992, 2003) and having similar interests in general, and on several topics in particular (Hancock et al., 2000), it was quite natural that we discussed and wrote about his neuroergonomic conceptualization (Parasuraman and Hancock, 2004). It was a proposition that Raja discussed with and published on with several luminaries of our science (e.g., Kramer and Parasuraman, 2007). In contrast to the behavioristic proposition presented earlier, we both believed that a greater level of insight into the symphonic productions of the neural orchestra could provide exceptional opportunities to advance human-technology interaction (and see Hancock and Szalma, 2003). This whole enterprise m was then being facilitated by new and exciting brain assessment techniques (e.g., functional Near-Infrared Spectroscopy [fNIRS], and functional Magnetic Resonance Imaging [fMRI]) that opened up new empirical strategies to explain behaviors such as vigilance (Parasuraman, 1986) as well as providing neuroergonomic signals as input to advanced automation. For example, Parasuraman encouraged the fruitful explorations by Scerbo et al. in the creation of an EEG-based index of engagement for adaptive automation control (see e.g., Prinzel et al., 2000; Mikulka et al., 2002). It was in this way that my own original conceptualization of physiologically-mediated, adaptive systems (Hancock et al., 1985; Hancock and Chignell, 1987) could be enacted in the real world. Energized by the DARPA resources involved in the AugCog program, these human-machine forms of neuroergonomic adaptation are now becoming ever more ubiquitous. Such advances evidently involved many leaders in the area of human-machine interaction including critical contributions by those such as Sheridan and Wickens (see e.g., Parasuraman et al., 2000b) as well as those involved in the very first forms of adaptive human-machine systems such as Reising et al. (see Rouse, 1988; and Wilson and Russell, 2003a,b, 2007). But neuroergonomics remained Parasuraman's own.

Within Pasteur's Quadrant: The Value of Use-Inspired Basic Research

Most certainly neuroergonomics is modulated by use-inspired research (Price and Behrens, 2003; Stokes, 2011). It does not stand apart from either pure neuroscience or applied ergonomics but brings the conceptual advances of neuroscience to the world. In this, it challenges the researchers in neuroscience with the practical demands of an ever more, technologically dominated world. Some would argue the use-inspired basic research program is a highly effective and workable model for virtually all of science (Sawyer and Hancock, 2018). Clearly, Parasuraman's conception resonated with many and, after his untimely death, motivated an International Conference first held in Paris in 2016 (and see publications derived therefrom; e.g., Ayaz and Dehais, 2019). A second meeting occurring in Philadelphia now presages the planning stages of its third, biennial meeting for 2020. Many have continued to explore ways in which insights from neuroscience can be enacted in the real-world including my own colleagues who explored how error-related negativity can be used as a pre-emptive signal for error prevention (Sawyer et al., 2017). Of course, we must set such investigations into the wider context of brain-machine interfaces that have been pursued in medicine and other realms, now joining with neuroergonomic developments. It is evident from the present volume concerning the enhancing of the linkage between brain and work, that the fecundity of the neuroergonomic conception lives on and promises to do so, at least for the foreseeable future. From the foregoing, it must be clear that I remain a strong advocate for neuroergonomics and thankful for Raja's fundamental and seminal identification; especially in the naming of the field. However, despite such an optimistic perspective and a vista of fruitful prognostications, neuroergonomics is not without its flaws and potential drawbacks. It is to these concerns that I turn next.

The Dangers of Turning the Mind Inside-Out

The human narrative is essentially a highly and unwarrantedly, optimistic one. In both science and technology, the general zeitgeist is characterized and colored by a positive and enlightened, progressive attitude. Yet, as we are all aware, the developments of science, and their materialization in technology, can be used to pursue very different moral aims and practical goals (Hancock, 2009). Neuroergonomic developments are not exempt from this inherent ambivalence of utility. As I noted earlier, when speed is the primary imperative which is emphasized in a cybernetic, neuroergonomic assembly, then the propensity to speed up any intrinsic error can itself be even fatally facilitated. If neuroergonomics can be used to “short-circuit” some of the components of cognition, then unanticipated and most probably unwanted outcomes might well be facilitated also. For example, the perfection of neuroergonomic techniques might materialize thought into action, all in a moment. Here, a stray idea or passing fancy is then enacted, even if the individual regrets such thoughts almost he moment they have them (Yerdon et al., 2018; Matthews et al., 2019). Connections here to advanced weaponry will render the outcome of some such actions as irreversible. Here then, we need to countenance some limits upon neuroergonomic processing in the form of safety or reality checks. Such discussions certainly need to be had. Although we can assure and comfort ourselves that appropriate safeguards will be in place, such indemnifications are themselves not liable to work flawlessly.

Deception, or lie detection is one relevant example here of insufficiently specified and rather problematic neuroergonomic application. While there is current talk of enforcing mandatory lie detection to members of the current White House staff, the signal detection capacity of this technique is certainly not perfect. As Parasuraman realized Signal Detection Theory (SDT) techniques themselves are not perfectly enacted or reliable when applied to real-world circumstances (Parasuraman et al., 1997, 2000a). As a consequence, one would not wish to link many contemporary, operationally critical systems to the forms of elicited feedback in the classical types of lie detection investigations. Yet, as the range of methods and their diagnosticity and validity, both alone and in combination improve, so the capacity to enact accurate and neuro-cybernetic control itself matures. The issue of veridical detection is important beyond the specialized concerns of deception alone (and see Hancock, 2015). Like much of conscious thought, deception is a higher level function which is much more related to the content of ratiocination, as opposed to the processes that support it. The more general concern of the wider public may well be that neuroergonomics can “read your mind.” Thus, it is important to express the granularity of the interpretation of neuroergonomic signals. This will help affirm (pro tem), that the stimuli of concern for such input are much more allied to the actions of relatively small groups of neurons. It is, of course, true that neuroergonomics seeks to harness EEG signals as well as those from more recent measures (e.g., fNIRS). However, the principle goal, at the present time, is not to read the private contents of individuals' thought. This being said, science rolls on and the possibilities of misuse must be considered, as it must with all forms of automation and technology (Parasuraman and Riley, 1997). Perhaps, at this nascent stage, we might entertain a charter of those activities that neuroergonomics should and should not be used for. Yet I feel, that rather like Asimov's Three Laws of Robotics, these chartered actions might act more as pabulum then prohibition. I know such issues concerned Raja and should be respected and examined by the interdisciplinary area of science that he pioneered.

A Brief Glimpse of the Future for Neuroergonomics

So what then of the future for neuroergonomics? We have to consider this in terms of both temporal horizon and contextual area. The temporal horizon can be conceived of as near-term events, likely within the next decade, and more extended projections, perhaps across the coming century. As for area context, we must look for developments in the neurosciences, the nature of work and general human activity and their fusion in the neuroergonomic enterprise. Across all of these time-scales and focus areas, the central leitmotif will, I think, be human-machine intimacy. At present, the connections between humans and their technology are slow, limited, and in reality rather absurdly constrained. We currently witness individuals in possession of hand-held super-computer linked to extensive networks and databases, hunting and pecking with fingers on ill-designed keyboard displays to enter language-mediated and language-limited instructions to achieve their purported goals. It has turned our contemporary world into unending lines of “heads-down,” oblivious persons, constantly and myopically attached to these limited portals (and see Hancock, 2016). Near-term technical developments will surely have to further expose and dissolve these highly limiting interface constraints. It is rather ludicrous that interactions with the most advanced of human-computational creations can even be countenanced as being limited by the quirky configuration of “QWERTY” keyboards. Although I do not wish to limit this point to any particular interface instantiation, I believe that significant progress can and will be made here at the interface. I see the line of evolution being characterized as “the disappearance of the interface.” Here, the physical contact between the user and their computational support system will not merely became small, faster, and more portable, but will begin to “evaporate,” as it were. In principle, any surface in a person's ambient environment can act as a “display” space (and see Hancock et al., 2015). Thus, personally “carrying” a display will, presumably and even shortly, be obviated altogether. I see this however, as closer to a century rather than a decade step of progress, although technologies like automated vehicles may well-serve to accelerate these, “not-on-body” option (Hancock et al., 2019a). Similarly, controls also will eventually be remotely enacted. The degree to which the physicality of such future human-computer interaction will be embedded in the uses, as opposed to being embedded in the world is simply a question of preferred (and currently most profitable) design options. Proximal and remote “intent inferencing,” and interfaces to support such intent inferencing will be crucial areas of technical and neuroergonomic development.

I have briefly mentioned the potential downsides of an untrammeled link between intention and action. In reality, we rather need now to be writing, if not laws, at least socially-agreed conventions on such limits, right at the present time. That we are not means that the future will continue to see ad hoc emergent patterns from an unplanned, and relatively “mindless” maw of realized technical innovations. Such unconstrained emergence portends potential disaster. For the neuroergonomic technologies, the battle of the coming decade remains “signal to noise” differentiation. We have an evident existence proof that patterns of activation in the brain do sum to produce intended actions in nominally “normal” human beings. But how to identify those patterns, how to model them, and how to predict them remain mountainous and prohibitive challenges. Yet many are climbing this mountain and work on the physical, prosthetic replication and replacement of such capacities for variously “disabled” individuals progresses apace. I am optimistic of punctate “successes” here, along this line of development in the near future. More understanding in this domain will also help us distinguish between simple, quantifiable processing “capacities,” and what the human brain actually achieves. I can well-countenance machine superiority in some closed domains, especially if floating point operations are used as the metric of capacity assessment (Moore, 1965; Kurzweil, 2005). What remains undecided is the relative capacities when we frame the two comparisons from a human perspective. The latter would feature measurements on dimensions such as trust, creativity, interest, etc. of which in artificial computational systems, we know almost nothing (Salmon et al., 2019). Yet, as neuroergonomics features, it is not human vs. computer, but rather a true emergent hybrid of the two which is the unit of interest. Once the interface barriers are down, we may have to re-cast the whole of psychology by asking questions like, what now is memory? and what is “selective attention” when all elements of any display can be recorded and processed? These emergent, conscious properties of the now fully integrated human-machine dyad are hard to specify. What is not hard to envisage is that they will almost certainly be very different from the nature of consciousness we presently experience.

I cannot leave an envisioned future without at least making one final observation; and this is on the future nature of work (Hancock, 1997). The last century or so has seen a change in emphasis on what composes the content of work. It's not that cognition was not important for example, in nineteenth century work; it was. It is not that the physical requirements of work in our society have disappeared; they have not. But rather, it is the predominance of one over the other as well as the capacity to replace either with an artificial surrogate that have framed our immediate past as to the work experience (Hancock, 2014). But now we have to ask a more fundamental question: what exactly is “work” and what form will it take in the near and more distant future? Heavily influenced by culture and history, work has most often been conceived as something testing, difficult, and often aversive. Work has been a burden to be borne, hard labor to be accomplished, and an arduous necessity for existence. Leisure is often framed as work's antithesis; something desired to be done in hours not devoted to “work.” I have argued before, and argue here, that this is a very limited and impoverished way in which to think of these types of human activity (Hancock, 1997). Thus, I see neuroergonomics as a critical catalyst in a forthcoming “sea-change” in our conception of “work.” In fact, I see a brisance in the wall that separates work from leisure for almost all people. The words obligation, vocation, avocation, and vacation may begin to splinter. Thus, I think neuroergonomics itself will change from the “brain at work” to the activities of the “elaborated person.” In this, I see the title of the recent text by Ayaz and Dehais (2019) not simply as appropriate, but rather as prescient and even prophetic. I take it as self-evident that the progress which will be accomplished in the coming 100 years will dwarf all of those of the whole of human existence. If we are able to avoid the incipient onset of “civicide,” which faces us (Hancock, 2019), what is understood to be “human” at the end of the twenty-first century may well-deserve even a different nomenclature than the species “homo sapiens,” that entered it.

Some Brief Concluding Observations

We have understood the explicit values and operations of cybernetic control loops now for well over half a century (Wiener, 1950; Hancock, 2018b). Enacting human-machine control via adaptive systems employing physiological indicators is itself now more than a third of a century old (Hancock et al., 1985). The employment of such signals, and especially those derived from advancing neuroscience techniques, to the wider swath of technological work is itself now even decades-old (see e.g., Donchin et al., 2000; Parasuraman and Rizzo, 2008). Each of these respective steps is one along a path to ever greater human-machine intimacy. They each, sequentially, attack the barriers of communication between an external system and the operator's internal state. Further, they provide models, simulations, and designs which ought to allow us to consciously and mindfully plan this advancing interaction. But in the end, we must ask an age old question. Because we can achieve this ever-increasing degree of intimacy, should we necessarily do so? It is a question that pervades all of technology (Hancock, 2018a; Hancock et al., 2019b) and clearly is not confined to the neuroergonomic realm alone. These were some of the wider concerns that equally tasked Raja Parasuraman during his scientific career. His legacy may lead us to our solutions.

Given the contributions of Raja's scientific oeuvre and his continuing concerns as to how technology was used in society, the final conclusion I derive here is a rather simple appeal. It is directed primarily at bench scientists and implores that even as we labor at the rock-face of progress, some portion of our time, effort, and cognition must be given over to the wider ramifications of each experimental procedure that we undertake. This appeal must also be directed to an informed public, whose concern similarly must be for the advances in these overall areas of science and exactly how they will impact and frame future reality. It is so easy for both of these constituencies (working scientists and informed public) to dismiss these moral and ethical conundra with facile utterances such as “not my job,” “not my responsibility,” “not my concern,” or “not relevant at my pay grade,” but it is this indifference to accountability, and its lack of associated moral obligations that can lead us away from the cybernetic dysfunctionality we are obviously experiencing at the present time (Hancock, 2018b). At least in Raja's name, the appeal has now been made here.

Author Contributions

The author confirms being the sole contributor of this work and has approved it for publication.

Conflict of Interest Statement

The author declares that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Acknowledgments

The author would like to thank Professor Carryl Baldwin for valuable suggestions on an earlier version of the present work. Further, the author is especially grateful for the insightful and encouraging comments by Professor Frederic Dehais and Professor Jochem Rieger in the process of revising and improving the current work.

Footnote

1. ^Clearly, I do not wish to convey that these are the only antecedents of the mind-brain-machine interface conception which has origins in multiple disciplines ranging from computer science and engineering through cybernetics and all of the neurosciences.

References

Ayaz, H., and Dehais, F. (2019). (Eds.). Neuroergonomics: The Brain at Work and in Everyday Life. London: Elsevier; Academic Press.

Google Scholar

Berka, C., Levendowski, D. J., Lumicao, M. N., Yau, A., Davis, G., Zivkovic, V. T., et al. (2007). EEG correlates of task engagement and mental workload in vigilance, learning, and memory tasks. Aviat. Space Environ. Med. 78, B231–B244.

PubMed Abstract | Google Scholar

Berkeley, G. (1710). A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge. Dublin: JB Lippincott and Company.

Google Scholar

Broadbent, D. E. (1958). Perception and Communication. Elmsford, NY: Pergamon Press. doi: 10.1037/10037-000

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Broadbent, D. E. (1971). Decision and Stress. Oxford: Academic Press.

Google Scholar

Buckner, D. N., and McGrath, J. J. (1963). Vigilance: A Symposium. New York, NY: McGraw-Hill.

Google Scholar

Chiesa, M. (1994). Radical Behaviorism: The Philosophy and the Science. Boston, MA.

Google Scholar

Craik, K. J. (1947). Theory of the human operator in control systems: I. The operator as an engineering system. Br. J. Psychol. 38, 56–61.

PubMed Abstract | Google Scholar

Craik, K. J. (1948). Theory of the human operator in control systems: II. Man in the element in a control system. Br. J. Psychol. 38, 142–148.

Google Scholar

Davies, D. R., and Parasuraman, R. (1982). The Psychology of Vigilance. London: Academic Press.

Davies, D. R., and Tune, G. S. (1969). Human Vigilance Performance. Oxford: American Elsevier.

Google Scholar

Donchin, E., Spencer, K. M., and Wijesinghe, R. (2000). The mental prosthesis: Assessing the speed of a P300-based brain-computer interface. IEEE Trans. Rehabil. Eng. 8, 174–179. doi: 10.1109/86.847808

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gath, I., Lehmann, D., and Bar-On, E. (1983). Fuzzy clustering of EEG signal and vigilance performance. Int. J. Neurosci. 20, 303–312. doi: 10.3109/00207458308986584

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hancock, P. A. (1997). On the future of work. Ergon. Des. 5, 25–29. doi: 10.1177/106480469700500407

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hancock, P. A. (2009). Mind, Machine, and Morality. Chichester: Ashgate.

Google Scholar

Hancock, P. A. (2013). In search of vigilance: the problem of iatrogenically created psychological phenomena. Am. Psychol. 68, 97–103. doi: 10.1037/a0030214

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hancock, P. A. (2014). Automation: how much is too much? Ergonomics 57, 449–454. doi: 10.1080/00140139.2013.816375

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hancock, P. A. (2016). The bleeding of conscious intensity J. Neurol. Neuro Rehabil. Res. 1, 13–14. Available online at: http://www.alliedacademies.org/articles/the-bleeding-of-conscious-intensity.html

Hancock, P. A. (2017). On the nature of vigilance. Hum. Factors 59, 35–43. doi: 10.1177/0018720816655240

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hancock, P. A. (2018a). Some Pitfalls in the Promises of Automated and Autonomous Vehicles. Ergonomics.

Hancock, P. A. (2018b). The humane use of human beings. Appl. Ergonom. doi: 10.1016/j.apergo.2018.07.009. [Epub ahead of print].

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hancock, P. A. (2019). In Praise of Civicide.

PubMed Abstract

Hancock, P. A., Caird, J. K., Chignell, M. H., Mizobuchi, S., Burns, P. C., Feng, J., et al. (2019b). Challenges to human drivers in increasingly automated vehicles.

Hancock, P. A., and Chignell, M. H. (1987). “Adaptive control in human-machine systems,” in Human Factors Psychology, ed P.A. Hancock (Amsterdam: North-Holland), 305–345. doi: 10.1016/S0166-4115(08)62312-2

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hancock, P. A., Chignell, M. H., and Lowenthal, A. (1985). An adaptive human-machine system. Proc. IEEE Conf. Syst. Man Cybern. 15, 627–629.

Hancock, P. A., Masalonis, A. J., and Parasuraman, R. (2000). On the theory of fuzzy signal detection: theoretical and practical considerations and extensions. Theor. Issues Ergon. Sci. 1, 207–230. doi: 10.1080/14639220110038640

CrossRef Full Text

Hancock, P. A., Nourbakhsh, I., and Stewart, J. (2019a). The road to autopia: how artificially intelligent automated vehicles will impact patterns of future transportation. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 1–8. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1805770115

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hancock, P. A., and Parasuraman, R. (1992). Human factors and safety in the design of intelligent vehicle-highway systems. J. Safety Res. 23, 181–198. doi: 10.1016/0022-4375(92)90001-P

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hancock, P. A., and Parasuraman, R. (2003). “Human factors and ergonomics,” in Handbook of Cognitive Science, Vol. 2, ed L. Nadel (London, Nature Publishing Group), 410–418.

Google Scholar

Hancock, P. A., Sawyer, B. D., and Stafford, S. (2015). The effects of display size on performance. Ergonomics 58, 337–354. doi: 10.1080/00140139.2014.973914

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hancock, P. A., and Szalma, J. L. (2003). The future of Neuroergonomics. Theor. Issues Ergon. Sci. 4, 238–249. doi: 10.1080/1463922021000020927

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hancock, P. A., and Warm, J. S. (1989). A dynamic model of stress and sustained attention. Hum. Factors 31, 519–537. doi: 10.1177/001872088903100503

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hancock, P. A. (2015). Hoax Springs Eternal: The Psychology of Cognitive Deception. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press. doi: 10.1017/CBO9781107785311

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Head, H. (1923). The conception of nervous and mental energy (II) “Vigilance” A physiological state of the nervous system. Br. J. Psychol. 14, 126–147.

Google Scholar

Kramer, A. F., and Parasuraman, R. (2007). “Neuroergonomics: applications of neuroscience to human factors,” in Handbook of Psychophysiology, eds J. T. Cacioppo, L. G. Tassinary, and G. G. Berntson (New York, NY: Cambridge University Press), 704–722. doi: 10.1017/CBO9780511546396.030

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kurzweil, R. (2005). The Singularity is Near. New York, NY: Viking.

Google Scholar

Licklider, J. C. R. (1960). Man-computer symbiosis. IRE Trans. Hum. Factors Electron. 1, 4–11. doi: 10.1109/THFE2.1960.4503259

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Mackworth, N. H. (1948). The breakdown of vigilance during prolonged visual search. Q. J. Exp. Psychol. 1, 6–21. doi: 10.1080/17470214808416738

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Mackworth, N. H. (1950). Researches on the Measurement of Human Performance. Medical Research Council, Special Report. Series. No. 268.

Matthews, G., De Winter, J., and Hancock, P. A. (2019). Convergence and divergence in cognitive workload assessments: where next for research and practice. Theor. Issues Ergon. Sci.

Mikulka, P. J., Scerbo, M. W., and Freeman, F. G. (2002). Effects of a bio-cybernetic system on vigilance performance. Hum. Factors 44, 654–664. doi: 10.1518/0018720024496944

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Moore, G. (1965). Cramming more components onto integrated circuits. Electronics Magazine 38.

Google Scholar

Parasuraman, R. (1979). Memory load and event rate control sensitivity decrements in sustained attention. Science 205, 924–927. doi: 10.1126/science.472714

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Parasuraman, R. (1986). “Vigilance, monitoring, and search,” in Handbook of Perception and Human Performance, eds K.R. Boff, L. Kaufman, and J.P. Thomas (Oxford, England: John Wiley and Sons), 1–39.

Google Scholar

Parasuraman, R. (2003). Neuroergonomics: Research and practice. Theor. Issues Ergon. Sci. 4, 5–20. doi: 10.1080/14639220210199753

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Parasuraman, R., and Beatty, J. (1980). Brain events underlying detection and recognition of weak sensory signals. Science 210, 80–83. doi: 10.1126/science.7414324

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Parasuraman, R., and Davies, D. R. (1976). Decision theory analysis of response latencies in vigilance. J. Exp. Psychol. 2:578. doi: 10.1037/0096-1523.2.4.578

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Parasuraman, R., Greenwood, P. M., Haxby, J. V., and Grady, C. L. (1992). Visuospatial attention in dementia of the Alzheimer type. Brain 115, 711–733. doi: 10.1093/brain/115.3.711

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Parasuraman, R., and Hancock, P. A. (2004). Neuroergonomics: harnessing the power of brain science for human factors and ergonomics. Hum. Factors Ergon. Soc. Bull. 47, 4–5. Available online at: http://peterhancock.ucf.edu/wp-content/uploads/sites/175/2013/02/117-bulletin1204.pdf

Parasuraman, R., Hancock, P. A., and Olofinboba, O. (1997). Alarm effectiveness in driver-centered collision-warning systems. Ergonomics 40, 390–399 doi: 10.1080/001401397188224

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Parasuraman, R., and Manzey, D. H. (2010). Complacency and bias in human use of automation: an attentional integration. Hum. Factors 52, 381–410. doi: 10.1177/0018720810376055

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Parasuraman, R., Masalonis, A. J., and Hancock, P. A. (2000a). Fuzzy signal detection theory: Basic postulates and formulas for analyzing human and machine performance. Hum. Factors 42, 636–659. doi: 10.1518/001872000779697980

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Parasuraman, R., Mouloua, M., and Molloy, R. (1996). Effects of adaptive task allocation on monitoring of automated systems. Hum. Factors 38, 665–679. doi: 10.1518/001872096778827279

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Parasuraman, R., and Mouloua, M. (1996). Automation and Human Performance: Theory and Applications. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

Google Scholar

Parasuraman, R., and Riley, V. (1997). Humans and automation: use, misuse, disuse, abuse. Hum. Factors 39, 230–253. doi: 10.1518/001872097778543886

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Parasuraman, R., and Rizzo, M. (2008). Neuroergonomics: The Brain at Work. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Parasuraman, R., Sheridan, T. B., and Wickens, C. D. (2000b). A model for types and levels of human interaction with automation. IEEE Trans. Syst. Man Cybern. Part A Syst. Hum. 30, 286–297. doi: 10.1109/3468.844354

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Parasuraman, R., and Wilson, G. F. (2008). Putting the brain to work: Neuroergonomics past, present, and future. Hum. Factors 50, 468–474. doi: 10.1518/001872008X288349

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Price, R. H., and Behrens, T. (2003). Working Pasteur's quadrant: harnessing science and action for community change. Am. J. Community Psychol. 31, 219–223. doi: 10.1023/A:1023950402338

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Prinzel, L. J., Freeman, F. G., Scerbo, M. W., Mikulka, P. J., and Pope, A. T. (2000). A Closed-loop system for examining psychophysiological measures for adaptive task allocation. Int. J. Aviat. Psychol. 10, 393–410. doi: 10.1207/S15327108IJAP1004_6

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Rivers-Rivers, W. H. (1896). On the apparent size of objects. Mind 5, 71–80. doi: 10.1093/mind/V.1.71

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Rouse, W. B. (1988). Adaptive aiding for human/computer control. Hum. Factors 30, 431–443. doi: 10.1177/001872088803000405

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Salmon, P., Hancock, P. A., and Carden, T. (2019). To Protect us From the Risks of Advanced Artificial Intelligence, We Need to Act Now. The Conversation, January 24th.

Sawyer, B. D., and Hancock, P. A. (2018). Hacking the human: the prevalence paradox in cybersecurity. Hum. Factors 60, 597–609. doi: 10.1177/0018720818780472

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Sawyer, B. D., Karwowski, W., Xanthopoulos, P., and Hancock, P. A. (2017). Detection of error-related negativity in complex visual stimuli: a new neuroergonomic arrow in the practitioner's quiver. Ergonomics 60, 234–240. doi: 10.1080/00140139.2015.1124928

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Stokes, D. E. (2011). Pasteur's Quadrant: Basic Science and Technological Innovation. Washington, DC: Brookings Institution Press.

Google Scholar

Swash, M. (2008). Henry Head and the development of clinical neuroscience. Brain 131, 3453–3456. doi: 10.1093/brain/awn258

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Watson, J. B. (1913). Psychology as the behaviorist views it. Psychol. Rev. 20, 158–177. doi: 10.1037/h0074428

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Wiener, N. (1950). The human Use of Human Beings: Cybernetics and Society (No. 320). New York, NY: Perseus Books Group.

Wilson, G. F., and Russell, C. A. (2003a). Operator functional state classification using multiple psychophysiological features in an air traffic control task. Hum. Factors 45, 381–389. doi: 10.1518/hfes.45.3.381.27252

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Wilson, G. F., and Russell, C. A. (2003b). Real-time assessment of mental workload using psychophysiological measures and artificial neural networks. Hum. Factors 45, 635–643. doi: 10.1518/hfes.45.4.635.27088

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Wilson, G. F., and Russell, C. A. (2007). Performance enhancement in an uninhabited air vehicle task using psycho-physiologically determined adaptive aiding. Hum. Factors 49, 1005–1018. doi: 10.1518/001872007X249875

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Yerdon, V. A., Wohleber, R. W., Matthews, G., and Reinerman-Jones, L. E. (2018). “A simulation-based approach to development of a new insider threat detection technique: active indicators,” in International Conference on Applied Human Factors and Ergonomics (Cham: Springer), 3–14.

Google Scholar

Keywords: neuroergonomics, adaptive systems, human-machine systems, automation, autonomy

Citation: Hancock PA (2019) Neuroergonomics: Where the Cortex Hits the Concrete. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 13:115. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2019.00115

Received: 28 December 2018; Accepted: 14 March 2019;
Published: 12 April 2019.

Edited by:

Carryl L. Baldwin, George Mason University, United States

Reviewed by:

Frederic Dehais, National Higher School of Aeronautics and Space, France
Jochem W. Rieger, University of Oldenburg, Germany

Copyright © 2019 Hancock. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: P. A. Hancock, peter.hancock@ucf.edu

Download