OPINION article

Front. Med., 11 April 2025

Sec. Regulatory Science

Volume 12 - 2025 | https://doi.org/10.3389/fmed.2025.1536044

Ethical interventions: revisiting the assessment tools for health-system pharmacists


Hong Tham PhamHong Tham Pham1Ronald L. Castelino,Ronald L. Castelino2,3Tyree H. Kiser,Tyree H. Kiser4,5Toby C. TrujilloToby C. Trujillo4Megan K. FischerMegan K. Fischer5Kim-Huong Truong-NguyenKim-Huong Truong-Nguyen6Bao-Chau Truong-NguyenBao-Chau Truong-Nguyen7Minh-Hoang Tran,
Minh-Hoang Tran4,8*
  • 1Faculty of Pharmacy, Nguyen Tat Thanh University, Ho Chi Minh City, Vietnam
  • 2School of Pharmacy, Faculty of Medicine and Health, The University of Sydney, Darlington, NSW, Australia
  • 3Pharmacy Department, Blacktown Hospital, Blacktown, NSW, Australia
  • 4Department of Clinical Pharmacy, Skaggs School of Pharmacy and Pharmaceutical Sciences, University of Colorado Anschutz Medical Campus, Aurora, CO, United States
  • 5Department of Pharmacy, University of Colorado Hospital, UCHealth, Aurora, CO, United States
  • 6Department of Pharmacy, Nhan Dan Gia Dinh Hospital, Ho Chi Minh City, Vietnam
  • 7Faculty of Pharmacy, Pham Ngoc Thach University of Medicine, Ho Chi Minh City, Vietnam
  • 8NTT Hi-Tech Institute, Nguyen Tat Thanh University, Ho Chi Minh City, Vietnam

Introduction

Pharmacist interventions (PIs), which are any actions by pharmacists that can directly change the patient management or therapies (1), play a crucial role in improving patient outcomes by mitigating adverse drug events. Multiple tools have been developed to assess the significance of these interventions, with the primary focus on the clinical and economic impacts (2). Typically, PI assessment is an independent process from PI conduct. In specific, after the pharmacists make the PIs, an expert (or group of experts) will review the PIs and assess them multidimensionally using pre-existing tools. These assessments may be used for revising the hospital policies or protocols to balance the hospital operations and patient outcomes. Despite progress in the development of PI-assessing frameworks, the ethical impact of PIs has largely been neglected in the current assessment tools. Ethical considerations are pivotal in healthcare decisions (3), yet remain underrepresented in evaluation frameworks for PIs. One contributing factor is that PIs are not medical orders but are considered consultations for healthcare providers. Hence, many believe PIs do not have direct ethical impacts on patient treatment or healthcare (4, 5).

However, ethical issues in healthcare require an inter-professional approach (6), including the active engagement of pharmacists. This poses an ethical requirement for PIs (7), especially regarding drug-related problems (DRPs). Given the limited inclusion of this aspect in the PI-assessing tools (2), there are concerns about the breadth of these frameworks. The lack of focus on incorporating the ethical dimension in existing tools hinders the recognition of pharmacist contributions, particularly in scenarios where ethical considerations are central to decision-making. In this paper, we aimed to highlight this issue and potential approaches to integrate ethics into assessment tools for PIs. While there are many approaches to exploring ethical considerations in clinical practice, this paper focuses on the core principles of medical ethics, i.e., autonomy, non-maleficence, beneficence, and justice (3). These principles are the minimum acceptable criteria to ensure ethical standards in clinical practice. Given the major role of health-system pharmacists in addressing DRPs (2), we only comment on DRP-targeted PIs. Pharmacist-initiated orders have stringent regulations and, thus, are outside the scope of most assessment tools. To avoid confusion, we also would like to re-emphasize that this paper does not imply any changes to the practice of health-system pharmacists but only focuses on revising the assessment tools for PIs.

Clinical dimension

PIs are performed to address DRPs (2), therefore, the clinical impacts of PIs should correlate with the severity of DRPs (8), not a stand-alone index as in previously proposed assessment tools (2). For instance, in pain management for patients with cancer, overdoses (with a 20% increase in standard dosing) are flagged in a similar manner for both opioids and acetaminophen (also known as paracetamol). However, patient outcomes could differ significantly if these DRPs are not intervened. Addressing acetaminophen overdose is simply keeping the total dose per day below a well-defined threshold, e.g., 4 g for patients without liver impairment. However, it is more complicated to monitor and prevent overdose of medications without ceiling effect like opioids (9). Consequently, if we only use the current assessment tools to evaluate these overdosing DRPs, the 2 PIs should implicate similar clinical impact (resolving overdose). Compared with the PI for acetaminophen overdosing, the PI for opioid DRP is underestimated and implicitly documented as inadequate compliance with the beneficence principle of medical ethics.

More importantly, if the patients and providers are not in agreement on the goals of treatment, all medical orders and PIs should respect the autonomy of the patients (10). Disregarding patient choices or decisions can breed controversy over medical ethics (11). In such cases, PIs should be tailored partially to reflect the autonomy of the patients, given that they have sufficient decision-making capacity (11). Available PI-assessing tools cannot take this into account, as they only focus on the professional opinions of pharmacists but not the patients' perspectives (2). Typical examples are patient refusal of treatment in terminal illness or deprescribing in patients with limited life expectancy. Profession-driven PIs would focus on optimizing the active treatment, whereas patient-preferred PIs may only suggest palliative care due to the unnecessary burden of treatment. These types of dilemmas are normally outside the capacity of a PI-assessing tool. Therefore, assessing the clinical dimension of PIs without considering their clinical contexts and adjusting for patients' preferences can lead to ethical concerns and undermine the applicability of these tools.

Economic dimension

While the economic dimension is primarily based on the hospital perspective, it should not bypass the non-maleficence and beneficence principles of medical ethics (12). In specific, cost savings of PIs are only meaningful if the initial medical orders or practices are professionally and ethically acceptable. For example, in a patient currently taking digoxin who develops hypokalemia (a common trigger of digoxin toxicity (13)), not correcting potassium level is often unacceptable. A PI attempting to supplement potassium for this patient, given no contraindication, is likely to be considered uneconomical by the hospital or payer perspectives. Such assessments should not be conducted based on clinical and ethical standpoints. This also applies to the PI-consulted medical orders or practices, meaning that if the PIs cannot ensure professionalism and ethics, the economic dimension should not be assessed as well.

Organizational dimension

The lack of ethical considerations in the organizational dimension echoes that in the economic dimension. For instance, it is irrational to assign a negative organizational impact to a PI that separates the injections/syringes due to physicochemical incompatibility. In this case, the PI should not be discouraged in any manner despite an increase in workload and time for medication administration. Additionally, drug shortage-related issues create critical dilemmas for pharmacists. These are complex situations that require ethical and clinical justifications on a case-by-case basis (14). The foundational theory of managing drug shortages is balancing the quality of care for an individual patient and for a group of patients or society (15). Given this allocation trade-off, no PI-assessing tools can address the justice principle in these cases. Consequently, assessing the organizational dimension of the PIs can be ethically challenging in non-trivial scenarios.

Ethics management and integration

The simplest solution to address ethical issues that arise during PI assessment is limiting the utilization of these tools for scenarios that can be exempted from significant ethical considerations. Of note, this approach cannot completely solve the problem, as the complex scenarios are still not properly covered. We suggest adding a dimension representing the DRP severity and integrating medical ethics into these tools, either inside other dimensions or as a separate ethical dimension.

Regarding the former option, criteria to assess ethical aspects should be given within each dimension of the original tools. If the initial medical orders/practices and PIs ensure the 4 minimal ethics principles (autonomy, non-maleficence, beneficence, and justice) (3), it is rational to assess all dimensions of the PIs. Otherwise, the dimension(s) requiring ethical considerations should not be assessed but instead, noted as not applicable. For the latter option, ethical considerations should be assessed after the DRP severity and clinical dimensions. If this ethical dimension does not flag any change, all other dimensions can be assessed accordingly. In contrast, when there is a positive or negative change, all other dimensions should not be considered for assessment.

To clarify the ethical dimension when assessing PIs, let us take a look at a scenario of an unconscious patient with terminal illness (microsatellite instability-high metastatic colorectal cancer) and no insurance/family members. The standard medical order initiates pembrolizumab. Given the poor prognosis for this patient, a PI suggests stopping the anticancer regimen. Appraising the PI as a cost-saving action can be unethical, if the PI is meant to avoid the costs on the hospital. In another hypothetically similar situation, the medical order attempts to avoid the standard anticancer regimen to reduce the treatment costs and workload, whereas the PI suggests initiating pembrolizumab. Considering the PI uneconomical can also be unethical, as the intention of the medical order, in this case, is not clinically and ethically justified. Therefore, to proceed with the assessment of economic and organizational dimensions of the PI without triggering these ethical issues, both the original medical order and PI need to be ethically appropriate. This shows why and how ethical dimension should be added to the PI assessment tools.

Author contributions

HP: Conceptualization, Formal analysis, Investigation, Writing – original draft, Writing – review & editing. RC: Conceptualization, Formal analysis, Investigation, Writing – original draft, Writing – review & editing. TK: Conceptualization, Investigation, Writing – original draft, Writing – review & editing. TT: Formal analysis, Investigation, Writing – original draft, Writing – review & editing. MF: Formal analysis, Investigation, Writing – original draft, Writing – review & editing. K-HT-N: Investigation, Writing – original draft, Writing – review & editing. B-CT-N: Investigation, Writing – original draft, Writing – review & editing. M-HT: Conceptualization, Formal analysis, Investigation, Project administration, Supervision, Validation, Writing – original draft, Writing – review & editing.

Funding

The author(s) declare that financial support was received for the research and/or publication of this article. This research was supported by NIH/NCATS Colorado CTSA Grant Number UM1 TR004399. Contents are the authors' sole responsibility and do not necessarily represent official NIH views.

Conflict of interest

HP reported receiving speaking fees and travel reimbursement from Servier Vietnam Ltd and Pfizer Vietnam Ltd, grants from Servier Vietnam Ltd, and speaking fees from Aguettant Asia Pacific Pte Ltd outside the submitted work. K-HT-N reported receiving travel reimbursement from Pierre Fabre Vietnam Ltd outside the submitted work. M-HT reported receiving travel reimbursement from Pfizer Vietnam Ltd and Viatris Vietnam Ltd, speaking fees and grants from Servier Vietnam Ltd, and speaking fees from Aguettant Asia Pacific Pte Ltd outside the submitted work.

The remaining authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Generative AI statement

The author(s) declare that no Gen AI was used in the creation of this manuscript.

Publisher's note

All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article, or claim that may be made by its manufacturer, is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.

References

1. SHPA Committee of Specialty Practice in Clinical Pharmacy. SHPA standards of practice for clinical pharmacy. J Pharm Pract Res. (2005) 35:122–48. doi: 10.1002/j.2055-2335.2005.tb00322.x

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

2. Vo TH, Charpiat B, Catoire C, Juste M, Roubille R, Rose FX, et al. Tools for assessing potential significance of pharmacist interventions: a systematic review. Drug Saf. (2016) 39:131–46. doi: 10.1007/s40264-015-0370-0

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

3. Varkey B. Principles of clinical ethics and their application to practice. Med Princ Pract. (2021) 30:17–28. doi: 10.1159/000509119

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

4. Vuković Rodríguez J, Juričić Ž. Perceptions and attitudes of community pharmacists toward professional ethics and ethical dilemmas in the workplace. Res Social Adm Pharm. (2018) 14:441–50. doi: 10.1016/j.sapharm.2017.05.010

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

5. Simegn W, Weldegerima B, Endeshaw A, Sisay G, Mohammed A, Wondimsigegn D, et al. Assessment of community pharmacy professionals' attitude and perception towards ethical issues in Amhara Region, Ethiopia: a cross-sectional survey 2020. Risk Manag Healthc Policy. (2021) 14:4127–39. doi: 10.2147/RMHP.S328328

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

6. Clark PG, Cott C, Drinka TJ. Theory and practice in interprofessional ethics: a framework for understanding ethical issues in health care teams. J Interprof Care. (2007) 21:591–603. doi: 10.1080/13561820701653227

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

7. Barreda Hernández D, Mulet Alberola A, González Bermejo D, Soler Company E. The reason for having a code of pharmaceutical ethics: Spanish pharmacists code of ethics. Farm Hosp. (2017) 41:401–9. doi: 10.7399/fh.2017.41.3.10611

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

8. Lekpittaya N, Kocharoen S, Angkanavisul J, Siriudompas T, Montakantikul P, Paiboonvong T. Drug-related problems identified by clinical pharmacists in an academic medical centre in Thailand. J Pharm Policy Pract. (2024) 17:2288603. doi: 10.1080/20523211.2023.2288603

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

9. Trescot AM, Datta S, Lee M, Hansen H. Opioid pharmacology. Pain Physician. (2008) 11:S133–S53. doi: 10.36076/ppj.2008/11/S133

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

10. Rhodes R. “Duties to respect patients' autonomy and assess capacity.” In: The Trusted Doctor: Medical Ethics and Professionalism. Online, , ed. New York, NY: Oxford University Press (2020). doi: 10.1093/med/9780190859909.001.0001

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

11. Navin MC, Brummett AL, Wasserman JA. Three kinds of decision-making capacity for refusing medical interventions. Am J Bioeth. (2022) 22:73–83. doi: 10.1080/15265161.2021.1941423

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

12. Peacock S, Ruta D, Mitton C, Donaldson C, Bate A, Murtagh M. Using economics to set pragmatic and ethical priorities. BMJ. (2006) 332:482–5. doi: 10.1136/bmj.332.7539.482

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

13. Rehman R, Hai O. Digitalis Toxicity. StatPearls Publishing (2023).

Google Scholar

14. Fox ER, McLaughlin MM. ASHP guidelines on managing drug product shortages. Am J Health Syst Pharm. (2018) 75:1742–50. doi: 10.2146/ajhp180441

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

15. Jagsi R, Spence R, Rathmell WK, Bradbury A, Peppercorn J, Grubbs S, et al. Ethical considerations for the clinical oncologist in an era of oncology drug shortages. Oncologist. (2014) 19:186–92. doi: 10.1634/theoncologist.2013-0301

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Keywords: ethics, intervention, pharmacist, pharmacy service, hospital, health-system, assessment tools

Citation: Pham HT, Castelino RL, Kiser TH, Trujillo TC, Fischer MK, Truong-Nguyen K-H, Truong-Nguyen B-C and Tran M-H (2025) Ethical interventions: revisiting the assessment tools for health-system pharmacists. Front. Med. 12:1536044. doi: 10.3389/fmed.2025.1536044

Received: 28 November 2024; Accepted: 28 March 2025;
Published: 11 April 2025.

Edited by:

Wei Luan, Shuguang Hospital Affiliated to Shanghai University of TCM, China

Reviewed by:

Riza Alfian, Sekolah Tinggi Ilmu Kesehatan ISFI Banjarmasin, Indonesia

Copyright © 2025 Pham, Castelino, Kiser, Trujillo, Fischer, Truong-Nguyen, Truong-Nguyen and Tran. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Minh-Hoang Tran, dG1ob2FuZ0BudHQuZWR1LnZu

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.