Skip to main content

ORIGINAL RESEARCH article

Front. Artif. Intell., 18 October 2022
Sec. Machine Learning and Artificial Intelligence
Volume 5 - 2022 | https://doi.org/10.3389/frai.2022.900943

Judgment aggregation, discursive dilemma and reflective equilibrium: Neural language models as self-improving doxastic agents

  • 1Karlsruhe Institute of Technology, Department of Philosophy, Karlsruhe, Germany
  • 2Allen Institute for Artificial Intelligence, Aristo, Seattle, WA, United States

Neural language models (NLMs) are susceptible to producing inconsistent output. This paper proposes a new diagnosis as well as a novel remedy for NLMs' incoherence. We train NLMs on synthetic text corpora that are created by simulating text production in a society. For diagnostic purposes, we explicitly model the individual belief systems of artificial agents (authors) who produce corpus texts. NLMs, trained on those texts, can be shown to aggregate the judgments of individual authors during pre-training according to sentence-wise vote ratios (roughly, reporting frequencies), which inevitably leads to so-called discursive dilemmas: aggregate judgments are inconsistent even though all individual belief states are consistent. As a remedy for such inconsistencies, we develop a self-training procedure—inspired by the concept of reflective equilibrium—that effectively reduces the extent of logical incoherence in a model's belief system, corrects global mis-confidence, and eventually allows the model to settle on a new, epistemically superior belief state. Thus, social choice theory helps to understand why NLMs are prone to produce inconsistencies; epistemology suggests how to get rid of them.

1. Introduction

Statistical language models describe the probability distribution of tokens (e.g., words) in a language (Manning and Schütze, 1999). Technological advances in the design of neural networks have recently led to the development of powerful machine learning models, so-called Transformers (Vaswani et al., 2017), which predict language tokens with previously unseen accuracy and have since sparked a scientific revolution in the field of AI and NLP: These neural language models (NLMs)—such as GPT-2 (Radford et al., 2019) and GPT-3 (Brown et al., 2020), BERT (Devlin et al., 2019) and RoBERTa (Liu et al., 2019), or T5 (Raffel et al., 2020)—are not only regularly achieving ever better SOTA results in traditional NLP tasks like machine translation, reading comprehension, or natural language inference (as documented, e.g., on paperswithcode.com); they are also successfully applied to solve further cognitive tasks involving advanced reasoning, specifically multi-hop inference (Clark et al., 2020; Saha et al., 2021), explanation (Yang et al., 2018; Zaheer et al., 2020; Dalvi et al., 2021), creative writing (Holtzman et al., 2019), commonsense reasoning (Bosselut et al., 2019b), critical thinking (Betz et al., 2021a), or mathematical theorem proving (Polu and Sutskever, 2020; Noorbakhsh et al., 2021). These broad and robust predictive successes naturally trigger the questions (i) whether it makes sense— conceptually and normatively—to say that NLMs exhibit human rationality (cf. Zimmermann, 2020), and (ii) whether NLMs represent empirically adequate models of human cognition (cf. Goldstein et al., 2020; Schrimpf et al., 2021).

However, and despite their revolutionary impact, NLMs still face important limitations. Arguably one of their major, widely acknowledged failures consists in the fact that the output of NLMs suffers from spectacular inconsistencies (Ribeiro et al., 2019; Ettinger, 2020; Kassner and Schütze, 2020). For example, XLM-Roberta (Conneau et al., 2019) judges that Warsaw lies north of Berlin, Berlin north of Paris, and Paris north of Warsaw1. Likewise, Delphi (Jiang et al., 2021b) ponders that it's wrong to hurt the cat (or the dog) so that the dog (respectively, the cat) can survive, yet that it's equally wrong to let both cat and dog die2. In this paper, we argue that the emergence of such inconsistencies might be partially explained in terms of judgment aggregation during the model's pre-training, and we introduce, moreover, a novel self-contained, self-improving fine-tuning procedure which effectively reduces global inconsistencies.

Let us for a moment conceive of judgment, or belief, as a binary classification task: a sentence is classified as either true or false. Given that NLMs—qua learning objective—seek to match the token distribution of the training data, it seems highly plausible that a NLM's confidence in its classification of sentence s as true correlates closely with the relative frequency of s being presented as true (rather than false) in the training data. In this perspective, we may expect NLMs to aggregate judgments (from the training data) sentence-wise and in accordance with vote ratios (assuming, for now, each training text has one vote).

The hypothesis of sentence-wise vote ratio aggregation, albeit plausible and predictable, has surprising consequences. It is a well-known result from social choice theory that aggregating a profile of individually consistent sets of judgments by means of sentence-wise majority vote may result in an inconsistent set of collective judgments—if, and only if, some judgments range over a minimally inconsistent set of sentences of length equal to or greater than three (see List, 2013). This phenomenon, which mirrors Arrow's impossibility theorem for preference aggregation (Arrow, 1951), is also referred to as discursive dilemma (Pettit, 2001). Now, provided that neural language models form judgments in accordance with sentence-wise vote ratio aggregation, we shouldn't be surprised to find that these judgments are logically inconsistent, even if all the training texts are individually consistent. Discursive dilemma hence provides a potential explanation for why a language model makes inconsistent judgments. We will quantify the extent of such judgment-aggregation-induced incoherence.

Can a neural language model get rid of the inconsistencies in its belief system which have arisen from discursive dilemmas? We propose a method for doing so. The key idea is to let the neural language model go through a process of gradual belief revision, inspired by the concept of reflective equilibrium. Reflective equilibrium has been originally introduced by the eminent philosophers Nelson Goodman and John Rawls as a method for how normative beliefs are formed, rationally revised, and justified (Goodman, 1955; Rawls, 1971). It has since been extensively discussed and refined (e.g., Daniels, 1996; Brun, 2014; Baumberger and Brun, 2016; Elgin, 2017), and is today arguably one of the major views about rational belief formation in ethics, logic, philosophy, and epistemology. For all its prominence and despite several formal explication attempts (Tersman, 1993; Thagard, 2000; Yilmaz et al., 2016; Beisbart et al., 2021), there is no agreement about what exactly this method amounts to. We conceive of reflective equilibrium, for the purposes of this paper, as a process of step-wise and local belief revision, where

[RE-process 1] each modification is triggered by a critical logical assessment of a finite (typically small) sub-part of the entire current belief system;

[RE-process 2] step-wise adjustments seek to locally improve the mutual justification (logical fit) between individual beliefs;

with the overarching aims:

[RE-aim 1] in the long run, the continuous revisions logically improve (e.g., increase global coherence of) the belief system as a whole;

[RE-aim 2] the evolving belief system converges toward a new belief state.

Such a thin conception of reflective equilibrium resembles connectionist accounts of coherence, proposed in philosophy (Thagard, 1992, 2000) and psychology (Simon et al., 2004, 2015). We may note, however, that it differs fundamentally from Bayesian updating (Jeffrey, 1965), AGM belief revision (Alchourron et al., 1985), or formal learning theory (Kelly, 1996) inasmuch as beliefs are not required to be logically consistent from the outset, and may be revised without external triggers such as the acquisition of novel facts or evidence.

This paper's attempt to emulate advanced normative theories of rational agency (namely, the theory of reflective equilibrium) with and through NLMs is in line with recent empirical findings in cognitive science which establish that NLMs, and in particular Transformers, can explain both the behavioral and the neural response of the human brain in high-level language processing tasks (Goldstein et al., 2020; Schrimpf et al., 2021).

Figure 1 presents the overall design of our specific computational experiments, which fall in two parts. In part one (pre-training), we train randomly initialized Transformer language models on carefully constructed text corpora (cf. Section 3.2). Each text corpus is built by simulating a society of authors who hold (internally consistent) beliefs about how to sort items in a domain, and express their views in argumentative texts (cf. Section 3.1). To further increase experimental control and to eliminate confounding factors (e.g., tokenization), texts are composed in a simple and transparent artificial language, rather than a natural one. (Consequently, the Transformer learns but the artificial language.) The artificial language has a straight-forward semantic interpretation: One may use it to articulate a strict order in a domain. Now, by eliciting the degrees of belief of the pre-trained language models and comparing those with the beliefs of the simulated authors who have produced the training texts in the first place (cf. Section 3.4), we examine the language models' belief formation mechanism and the extent of judgment-aggregation-induced inconsistencies (i.e., the output inconsistency that can be explained with reference to the model's specific way of aggregating judgments).

FIGURE 1
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 1. Overall design. A randomly initialized language model (LM) is trained on a synthetic text corpus produced by artificial, simulated authors. The accordingly pre-trained model (PTLM) subsequently trains on self-generated texts, which finally yields a fine-tuned model (FTLM).

In part two of the experiments (self-training), we submit the pre-trained language models to continuous self-training. More specifically, a model generates, at each step of the self-training loop, a series of texts which are supposed to spell out the logical implications of a small subset of the model's current beliefs (we prompt the model with sentences it tends to consider true). The generated texts—which may be conceived as a model's simple “self-reflections” and attempts to locally “think through” its current beliefs—are processed and transformed into suitable training data on which the model is eventually trained (cf. Section 3.3). Accordingly defined self-training, with sub-steps (i) text-generation and (ii) training on self-generated texts, corresponds closely to properties [RE-process 1] and [RE-process 2], which characterize reflective equilibrium. Tracking the evolution of the models' belief systems during self-training, we assess whether inconsistencies are resolved and the model converges toward an improved belief state (cf. Section 3.5). In other words, we verify whether the process is conducive to [RE-aim 1] and [RE-aim 2]. As a simple baseline, we consider an analogous fine-tuning loop where texts are picked from the original corpus rather than generated by the model, but which is, otherwise, identical to the self-training loop.

The main findings of these experiments can be summarized as follows:

(R1) Neural language models trained on an unbiased text corpus compiled by a group of authors form beliefs, grosso modo, in accordance with sentence-wise vote ratios (one author, one vote); especially so if the number of authors who withhold their judgment is small (Cf. Section 4.1).

(R2) Pre-trained language models may exhibit judgment-aggregation-induced inconsistencies. Both the frequency and the gradual severity of logical inconsistencies in the models' belief systems correspond closely to those observed in the underlying societies' collective beliefs (i.e., vote ratios) (Cf. Section 4.1).

(R3) Training on self-generated texts substantially reduces the extent of logical inconsistencies and hence improves the coherence of the models' belief systems (Cf. Section 4.2). The fact that self-generated texts (i) are inferentially structured and (ii) occasionally contain sentences the model actually disbelieves (at the time when generating the text) suggests that the observed coherence improvements are brought about by a rational belief revision mechanism.

(R4) Pre-trained models are mostly over-confident, in the sense that their degrees of belief are globally more informative than the collective beliefs of the authors (vote ratios). Such initial mis-confidence is effectively reduced through self-training, giving rise to a characteristic pattern (sharp initial drop followed by a gradual build-up of informativeness) (Cf. Section 4.3).

(R5) The belief dynamic's volatility decreases sharply during self-training, and overall divergence from the initial belief state doesn't rise any further from a given point onwards. That is, each model's belief system converges to a new equilibrium state. Moreover, the more coherent the pre-trained model's beliefs are in the first place, the less it diverges from its initial belief state during self-training (Cf. Section 4.4).

We consider these to be significant results which altogether justify the conclusion that the language models we study in a synthetic environment rationally self-improve their belief states by undergoing a process of reflective equilibration, as they meet the conditions [RE-process 1], [RE-process 2], [RE-aim 1], and [RE-aim 2].

While our experiments suggest a novel explanation for, and a potential remedy against the tendency of large language models such as GPT-3 or T5 to generate globally inconsistent output, it is still an open question to which extent (a) those inconsistencies in fact stem from judgment aggregation effects and (b) models like GPT-3 or T5 can actually self-improve by reflective equilibration. The very same simplifying assumptions which allow us to study belief formation processes in NLMs by means of computational experiments (in particular the extremely simple artificial language) weaken the analogy to models trained on natural languages. These limitations of the current study call for follow-up investigations and may open up fruitful research perspectives (cf. Section 5).

2. Related work

2.1. Accuracy and consistency of NLMs' factual knowledge claims

Pre-trained language models have been found to be rich and—to a certain extent—accurate knowledge bases (Petroni et al., 2019; Radford et al., 2019). Da et al. (2021) demonstrate that fine-tuning on knowledge graph data (Bosselut et al., 2019a,b) is a particularly effective way for eliciting such commonsense judgments. Knowledge extraction is, however, tricky. Judgments elicited from a model are highly context sensitive (Petroni et al., 2020), prone to (mis-)priming effects (Kassner and Schütze, 2020) and tend to be collectively inconsistent (Ribeiro et al., 2019; Elazar et al., 2021; Jang et al., 2021). Symptomatically, pre-trained language models struggle with negation (Ettinger, 2020; Kassner and Schütze, 2020; Talmor et al., 2020; Jiang et al., 2021a). In an investigation that methodologically parallels this paper's approach, Kassner et al. (2020) study belief formation of NLMs by pre-training a model on a synthetic, logically structured symbolic text corpus. Kassner et al. (2020) observe that belief formation is mainly triggered by memorization effects (rather than reasoning) and is strongly determined by the text frequencies of the corresponding facts. Our findings on belief formation as judgment aggregation are consistent with those results (see also the discussion of mis-calibration below).

As a remedy for incoherence, Kassner et al. (2021a,b) propose to add extra-architecture to a NLM for ensuring that globally consistent beliefs can be elicited from the structurally expanded system. In a similar vein, and drawing from cognitive dual process theories (Kahneman, 2011), Nye et al. (2021) interpret NLMs as fast yet error-prone systems, and demonstrate that these may be complemented by lightweight symbolic processes to increase the global consistency of the output. Recent work on perceptual grounding of NLMs shows that the integration of NLMs into a global neural architecture which interacts with a physical environment increases the ability of NLMs to correctly predict entire, complex physical situations (Zellers et al., 2021), which, in turn, seems to suggest that perceptual grounding fosters global consistency (of complex NLM output) as well.

Finding that the beliefs of our pre-trained language models are logically inconsistent, our study agrees with the literature reported above. However, we go beyond the literature in suggesting (i) a novel (additional, rather than rival) explanation for the NLMs' logical incoherence, namely discursive dilemmas, and in devising (ii) a self-training regime that effectively resolves these sort of inconsistencies. In particular, our self-training process does not rely on external computational resources, but is self-contained: it just makes use of the linguistic abilities available to the NLM itself.

2.2. Mis-calibration and over-confidence of NLMs

Guo et al. (2017) observe that modern, deep networks used for classification tasks are, in general, poorly calibrated, i.e., their probabilistic predictions do not correspond to the empirical likelihood that the prediction is correct. Neural language models, such as, e.g., models for machine translation, risk to be miscalibrated, too (Kumar and Sarawagi, 2019). Various remedies for miscalibration have been proposed and explored in the literature: modification of the loss-function (Moon et al., 2020); coupling and training of a complementary network to predict a prediction's reliability, that is, its empirical likelihood of being correct (Corbière et al., 2019); simultaneous training of an entire ensemble of deep neural networks (Lakshminarayanan et al., 2017); model distillation (Guo H. et al., 2021).

Some pre-trained Transformers have, however, been claimed to be reasonably well calibrated. Thus, Radford et al. (2019) report that GPT-2's conditionally generated answers in a QA task are well calibrated. Similarly, Desai and Durrett (2020) find that fine-tuned BERT (Devlin et al., 2019) and RoBERTa (Liu et al., 2019) generate reliable probabilistic predictions across different NLU tasks—both in- and out-of-domain. Hendrycks et al. (2020), in contrast, evaluating GPT-3 with multi-disciplinary QA tasks, argue that the zero-shot calibration of GPT-3 is extremely poor. Likewise, Guo H. et al. (2021) insist that pre-trained RoBERTa is poorly calibrated out-of-the-box, too. Shwartz and Choi (2020), analyzing mis-calibration in terms of deviation from reporting frequencies, argue that pre-trained language models are well calibrated for prevalent and recurring judgments in the training corpus, but exhibit systematic bias for rare judgments.

In line with this mixed picture, we find that a pre-trained language model's confidence in judgment s is closely tied to the relative frequency of s being considered as true according to training sources—if and only if the training corpus is balanced w.r.t. s (cf. Section 4.1). We go beyond the literature in proposing a self-training procedure that effectively reduces global biases (mis-confidence) in a model's belief system (cf. Section 4.3).

2.3. NLMs as reasoners

While the zero-shot reasoning ability of PTLMs is agreed to be limited (e.g. Brown et al., 2020; Zhou et al., 2020), NLMs have been fine-tuned to reliably carry out formal deduction (Weber et al., 2019; Minervini et al., 2020) and natural-language inference (Banerjee et al., 2020; Clark et al., 2020; Betz et al., 2021b; Saeed et al., 2021). Moreover, NLMs have been successfully trained to generate natural language proof chains or multi-hop derivations of a conclusion from a given set of sentences, as demonstrated by ProofWriter (Tafjord et al., 2020), PRover (Saha et al., 2020), multiPRover (Saha et al., 2020), EntailmentWriter (Dalvi et al., 2021), Parapattern-BART (Bostrom et al., 2021), or the Transformer trained on CLUTRR data (Sinha et al., 2019) by Gontier et al. (2020).

This study parallels these proof-generating systems inasmuch as our pre-trained model is used to generate inferentially structured texts as well. However, unlike in the systems mentioned above, text generation during self-training is open-ended rather than goal-oriented (i.e., does not aim to proof a given conclusion); in addition, we effectively employ such generated argumentative texts to further self-train the model.

2.4. Self-training and self-improving NLMs

The learned skills of a NLM can be deployed for self-improvement both during inference and training. On the one hand, dynamic context expansion, i.e., the augmentation and/or modification of a task's input by the NLM at inference time, has been extensively studied in the context of commonsense QA (e.g., Chen et al., 2019; Lewis et al., 2020; Petroni et al., 2020; Shwartz et al., 2020) and reasoning (e.g., Saha et al., 2020; Betz et al., 2021a). On the other hand, semi-supervised learning, i.e., the automatic augmentation of unlabeled training data, is a widely implemented technique for self-training, which typically distinguishes a teacher-model for data augmentation, and a student-model being trained (Du et al., 2021; Mi et al., 2021; Seo et al., 2021). Yang et al. (2020) push the idea of self-training further by labeling synthetic examples that have been generated by a NLM. In a refinement of this approach, He et al. (2021) show that such self-training yields substantial improvements in commonsense reasoning and NLI performance.

In agreement with this literature, we train our models on self-generated texts during self-training. However, we deviate from the prevailing teacher-student paradigm: Teacher (generating training text) and student (being trained) are one and the same model. In consequence, text generation is dynamic and may adapt during the self-training processes (e.g., texts with different properties may be produced at the beginning of self-training as compared to at the end, see also Section 4.2). In these regards, our self-training procedure resembles iterative back-translation, which has been shown to improve the quality of machine translation, especially through correcting errors in the original training data (Guo Y. et al., 2021).

3. Technical design

The introduction has provided an informal overview of our computational experiments and motivated our general approach. In this section, we shall describe the methodological set-up more thoroughly. Section 3.1 explains how we generate synthetic training corpora by simulating groups of authors who hold beliefs about how to rank objects in a domain, and who generate texts by expressing those beliefs. It also introduces the artificial language used throughout the experiments. The two training phases (pre-training and self-training) are described in Sections 3.2, 3.3. Section 3.4 details the mask-prediction task we employ to elicit a model's beliefs. And Section 3.5 introduces the “doxastic metrics” for assessing the models' belief systems (e.g., with respect to consistency). Further technical details may be found in the Appendix (Supplementary material) and will be pointed to where appropriate.

3.1. Artificial corpus construction

We use a simple artificial language L—actually, a small fragment of 1st-order logic—to carry out our study. The language is designed so that it contains minimally inconsistent subsets of size 3, can be easily and unambiguously tokenized, and possesses a simple semantics.

The alphabet of L consists of 200 constants a1a200 and two binary predicate letters R, S. All sentences in L are atomic, and have hence the form xRy or xSy (we use x, y, z as metavariables ranging over L's constants). The logic of L is defined by the following four inference-rules (which are not expressible in L itself): irreflexivity (xRx ⇒ ⊥, for any x); asymmetry (xRy, yRx ⇒ ⊥, for any x, y); transitivity (xRy, yRzxRz, for any x, y, z); duality (xRyySx, for any x, y).

Note that, because of duality, there exists, for every L-sentence, precisely one other logically equivalent L-sentence. For example, sentence a3Sa2 is equivalent to sentence a2Ra3.

And because of asymmetry, there exist, for every L-sentence, exactly two different logically contradictory L-sentences. Sentence a3Sa2, for example, is contradictory to a2Sa3, and to a3Ra2.

We say that xRy is the negation of xSy, and vice versa, and write s̄ for the negation of sentence s.

The language L has a simple, natural semantics. A theory (set of sentences) in L is consistent (⊥ cannot be derived with the inference-rules) if and only if it can be interpreted as a strict order over a domain D of 200 items. Let us flesh out the semantics of L with a concrete model and consider the top-200 tennis players, 1, 2…200, as our domain D. Every constant in L is a unique name of one of these tennis players, and we may assume that a1 refers to player 1, a2 to player 2 etc. We interpret the binary relation R as expressing that one player is strictly taller than another player. This relation is irreflexive (no player is strictly taller than herself), asymmetric (if i is strictly taller than j, j cannot be strictly taller than i), transitive (if i is strictly taller than j and j is strictly taller than k, i is strictly taller than k), and hence matches the logic of L. Correspondingly, S stands for the relation that one player is strictly smaller than another. Under the assumption that no two players are of exactly the same height, both relations satisfy duality. In this interpretation, the sentence a2Sa3, e.g., means that player 2 is strictly smaller than player 3. We will resort to the tennis model of L to illuminate the further exposition of the technical framework; yet, note that it serves merely illustrative purposes and represents just one possible interpretation of the artificial language used in this study.

To generate text corpora in L, we simulate text production processes. We define authors as formal agents who hold consistent beliefs (in L) and can produce texts which express those beliefs. To simplify the semantic representation of an author's beliefs, we additionally assume that her beliefs can be interpreted as a strict total order over a sub-domain of D. In terms of the tennis model: An author sorts a subset of players by height, such as for example by means of the following descending ranking of the top-10 players except number 3 (sub-domain),

2,4,10,1,7,8,9,6,5.                 (H*)

Now, the corresponding pairwise height comparisons represent all her beliefs, e.g., she believes that a2Ra1 and that a9Sa1 are true, she believes that a2Sa4 is false, and she suspends judgment vis-à-vis a2Ra24 and a103Sa57 (i.e., neither considers these sentences true nor false). Hence, an author's belief system (B) is a consistent and closed set of L-sentences. For example, because the author believes a2Ra1 and a9Sa1, she also believes the logical consequence a2Ra9.

We further distinguish two types of authors by means of a “reach threshold”: those who can express every L-sentence they believe (reach = ∞) when producing a text; vs. those who can only express a sentence of the form xRy or xSy if, loosely speaking, the rank-order difference between x and y according to their belief system lies below a given threshold reach (with reach < 200). For example, in a belief system corresponding to (H*) above, the rank-order difference between players 1 and 7 equals 1, whereas the rank-order difference between players 1 and 6 is 4. With unlimited reach threshold, an author holding that belief system can express both her beliefs that a1Ra7 and that a1Ra6; with reach = 3, however, she can only express the former, not the latter. The introduction of a reach threshold has the effect that an author's set of expressible beliefs is not necessarily deductively closed.

Our simulated authors randomly produce finite, truthful, unbiased, inferentially structured L-texts, i.e., sequences of expressible L-sentences s1, s2, …, sl. Texts are truthful because they only contain sentences the author believes to be true (siB for i = 1…l). Texts are unbiased because all of an author's expressible beliefs are equally likely to figure in a text by the author. Texts are inferentially structured because, rather than expressing an author's beliefs in random order, texts follow the logical implications defined by the inference-rules, in particular, they contain transitivity arguments (e.g., xRy, yRz, xRz) and duality arguments (xRy, ySx) as sub-sequences. Consider, for illustration, the following two texts:

text1:a6Sa8 a2Ra1 a9Sa1 a2Ra9,text2:a11Sa8 a2Ra1 a9Sa1 a2Ra9.

Both are inferentially structured: the final sentence follows from the two preceding ones. An author who holds beliefs corresponding to (H*) may produce text1, provided her reach threshold is greater than 6. She cannot, however, produce text2, as the author does not believe that the first sentence in text2 is true (she is suspending judgement), and text2 is therefore not truthful to her beliefs. Appendix A gives further details of how authors sample texts.

We define a society as a group of n authors with belief systems Bi (i = 1…n) that share a specific set of background beliefs and produce, independently of each other, texts that collectively make up a corpus. A society's shared background beliefs, K, are modeled as a strict total order on subdomain DKD; every author's belief system then extends this shared order, KBi with DKDiD for i = 1…n. Let us assume, returning to the tennis model, that it is common knowledge how to rank players 4, 5 and 6 (DK = {4, 5, 6}) in terms of height, namely as

4,6,5.                     (HK)

The illustrative belief system represented by (H*) above shares and extends the background knowledge (HK).

We may characterize societies in terms of (i) the number of authors, (ii) the extent of shared background beliefs, as measured by the ratio |DK|/|D|, and (iii) the reach threshold which controls which beliefs authors can express in their texts. So as to cover, in our simulation study, a wide spectrum of boundary conditions, we define 3 × 4 × 2 corresponding profiles with

n_authors = 5, 15, 25;

background_ratio = 0, 0.25, 0.5, 0.75;

reach = ∞, 50.

Note that in societies with reach = 50, authors can express less than half of the beliefs they may hold; and, importantly, the text corpus they produce is not inferentially closed. Put differently, such authors communicate efficiently: while they explicitly express less than half of their beliefs, everything they do believe can be inferred from what they (may) express.

For each of the 24 profiles, we create five different societies (by sampling shared background beliefs and the authors' belief systems), each of which collectively produces (with equal contributions by all authors) a corpus of 101,000 texts. This gives us 120 different societies and an equal number of corresponding text corpora.

As an additional characterization of a society's diversity, we measure the rank correlation between the strict orders which model the authors' belief systems. In particular, we resort to Kendall's tau correlation measure, finding that kendalltau varies between −0.03 and 0.22, with median value at 0.055. We split simulated societies in two equally sized groups, classified as exhibiting high diversity (kendalltau < 0.055) vs. high agreement (kendalltau> 0.055).

3.2. Pre-training regime

We train randomly initialized T5 models (Raffel et al., 2020; Wolf et al., 2020) on each society's text corpus with an equal share of masked language modeling (denoising) and text generation training items, which gives us in total 120 pre-trained models. We construct denoising training items by masking sequences in the raw training texts (in close analogy to the original pre-training regime of T5); moreover, text generation training items consist in an initial sub-sequence of a given text (as input) and the full text (as target). Models are accordingly trained on a given corpus (which is randomly divided into a train split containing 100,000 raw texts and an eval split with 1,000 texts) for 18 epochs or until eval loss doesn't decrease any further. Appendix C provides further technical details.

We have chosen masked token prediction and linear text completion as pre-training tasks because our belief elicitation procedure (cf. Section 3.4) is based on masked token prediction, and the self-training regime (cf. Section 3.3) requires that models are able to generate texts. This dual demand has also guided our choice of transformer architecture (seq-to-seq rather than decoder- or encoder-only models)—whereas the experiments presented here could in principle be carried out with causal LMs, too, by adapting the belief elicitation procedure.

3.3. Self-training regime

Every pre-trained model is submitted to four independent self-training runs, which consist in 600 training steps. At each step in a self-training loop, the model generates texts, which are processed, filtered, masked, and finally used as training data for denoising training (see Appendix D, Algorithm 2). More specifically, we generate, first of all, 200 prompts by sampling strong beliefs from the model (see also Appendix D, Algorithm 3). Being queried with each of these prompts, the model returns, with beam sampling, 5 generated text sequences and corresponding scores. Texts are split into sub-sequences of length 3, discarding all sub-sequences which do not represent a syntactically well-formed sentence. Next, we keep only sentences from texts with at least 6 well-formed sentences and high beam scores (top 15%). These sentences are transformed into training data by masking their predicate letters—similarly to the masking for belief elicitation (cf. Section 3.4). Finally, the model is trained on a denoising task with the thusly generated training items for one epoch.

We define a simple baseline in close correspondence to self-training by drawing texts from the original corpus rather than letting the model generate raw training texts itself.

3.4. Belief elicitation and sentence-wise vote ratios

Let M be a neural language model capable of masked token prediction in our language L. To elicit the model's belief in a L-sentence aiRaj (likewise aiSaj), we mask the predicate letter, ai[mask]aj, query the model, and interpret the model's probability prediction for [mask] = R, the so-called confidence, as its degree of belief in aiRaj, in short:

BELM(aiRaj)=ProbM( [mask]=R|ai [mask] aj).

Since we will compare a model's degrees of belief with the authors' beliefs in a society, we introduce the sentence-wise vote ratio as a simple belief aggregation method. Consider a society containing n authors with belief systems Bi (i = 1…n) and shared reach threshold r. Let Bir denote the corresponding set of expressible beliefs of author i. We define the society's sentence-wise vote ratio in the L-sentence s as

VR(s)=1ni=1nv(i) with v(i)={1if sBir0if s¯Bir0.5otherwise .

The sentence-wise vote ratio generalizes binary sentence-wise majority voting.

3.5. Doxastic metrics

The following metrics can be applied both to degrees of belief elicited from a model and, likewise, to vote ratios aggregated from belief systems of authors. To keep the presentation plain, we shall introduce them, below, as doxastic metrics only.

First of all, transitivity violation is one reason for why degrees of belief may be logically incoherent. Let s1, s2, s3 be three minimally inconsistent L-sentences (such as, e.g., a1Ra2, a2Ra3, a1Sa3), i.e., any two of these statements imply, with transitivity (and, possibly, duality), the negation of the remaining one. Now, let x1, x2, x3 be degrees of belief assigned to these three statements [xi = BEL(si)]. For definiteness, we may assume x1x2x3. Informally speaking, the degrees of belief violate the transitivity rule in case x1, x2, x3 are all too high (at least one statement has to be dis-believed). In particular, as s2 and s3 jointly imply the negation of s1, either the conjunction of s2 and s3, or s1 must not be believed. We may resort to fuzzy logic (see Appendix B) to spell out this constraint as a precise inequality,

x1+x210.            (TC)

We will say that x1, x2, x3 violate the transitivity constraint iff they violate the above inequality (3), in which case x1+x2−1 expresses the degree of transitivity violation. Let us suppose, for example, that x1 = 0.4, x2 = 0.5, and x3 = 0.8. In this case, the transitivity constraint is not violated, as x1 and x2 add up to 0.9 ≤ 1. Consider, in contrast, slightly higher degrees of belief x1 = 0.5, x2 = 0.7, x3 = 0.8: this belief profile violates the transitivity constraint with degree 0.2. Note that it is only by considering the degree of transitivity violation (in addition to observing whether TC is satisfied) that we may evaluate the latter case differently from a situation where all three collectively inconsistent statements are maximally believed (x1 = x2 = x3 = 1).

For a set of minimally inconsistent triples and corresponding degrees of belief, we may thus calculate (i) the ratio of transitivity violations and (ii) the mean degree of transitivity violation.

The degree of informativeness expresses how extreme—close to either 1 or 0—the beliefs in a system are. We use normalized variance as a simple measure of informativeness (stipulating BELM(s)+BELM(s̄)=1 and hence μ = 0.5). More precisely, let X = 〈x1xk〉 be some degrees of belief, then inf(X)=1ki=1k(1-2xi)2. This measure of informativeness is (for fixed k) negatively correlated with, and hence a proxy for, the joint entropy of the degrees of belief (assuming independence). We will assess global over- and under-confidence of a model's degrees of belief relative to a society's collective judgments in terms of a mismatch of informativeness. In particular, with L-sentences s1, …, sk, X = 〈BELM(s1), …,BELM(sk)〉 and Y = 〈VR(s1), …,VR(sk)〉, we say that model M is globally over-confident if inf(X) > inf(Y), and globally under-confident in the opposite case. Mis-confidence, accordingly defined, is a specific (namely, systematically biased) form of mis-calibration: confidence levels do not only deviate from empirical frequencies (vote ratios), but they do so in a biased way, e.g., systematically over-estimating the empirical frequencies.

Finally, we may want to measure the overall disagreement between two belief systems. Let X = 〈x1xk〉, and Y = 〈y1yk〉 be degrees of belief assigned to L-sentences s1sk. We may now use the relative entropy (Kullback-Leibler divergence) as a measure for how much X diverges from Y, KL(X||Y)=i=1kxilog(xi/yi). We will estimate the volatility of consecutive belief system changes by tracking KL(Xt+1||Xt), and we will measure the global divergence of an evolving belief system at step t from a given initial state by KL(Xt||X0).

Each doxastic metric introduced in this section is calculated for a given set of L-sentences (or, in the case of transitivity violation, a set of inconsistent L-triples). It is, however, impractical to compute these metrics for all L-sentences in the experiments reported below. Therefore, whenever we determine a doxastic metric, we do so for a random sample containing 1,000 L-sentences, which are drawn independently of each other (and irrespectively of the agents' reach thresholds) by randomly choosing (i) two different constants (ai, aj with 1 ≤ ij ≤ 200) and (ii) a binary relation R or S.

4. Results

4.1. Neural belief formation as judgment aggregation

Do pre-trained models aggregate a society's judgments sentence-wise? To answer this question, we elicit a model's degrees of belief for a random sample of sentences S and compare those with the society's corresponding vote ratios. Table 1 reports the thusly calculated mean squared deviation, distinguishing—per column:—between sentences according to the proportion of authors who suspend judgment with respect to the sentence, and aggregating—per row:—over all societies with the same number of authors and reach threshold. Formally, let M1, …, Mk be all models trained on a society with a given number of authors and reach threshold, let S1, …, Sk be random samples of L-sentences, and let R be a given real interval (bin). We write SiRSi for the set of sentences s such that the ratio of authors in the underlying society i who (i) hold a belief about s and (ii) can express s given their reach threshold lies within R. Table 1 displays 1ki=1k1|SiR|sSiR(BELMi(s)-VRi(s))2.

TABLE 1
www.frontiersin.org

Table 1. Mean squared deviation (MSD) between a model's degrees of belief and the underlying society's sentence-wise vote ratios.

The main take-away is that the difference between a society's vote ratio for some sentence s and a model's corresponding degree of belief is small provided that most authors hold an expressible belief about s (right column in Table 1). For higher ratios of judgment suspension, we observe substantially greater differences, especially in societies with few authors or limited reach threshold. In other words, if a training corpus is biased (e.g., a sentence s is underrepresented), a model's degrees of belief may diverge from sentence-wise vote ratios. However, we find the best match between degrees of belief and vote ratios in case of low judgment suspension and limited reach threshold (right-most column, lines 3–6). That is because, in these cases, the authors communicate efficiently (cf. Section 3.1): there is a lower number of different statements they express in texts, but (given same corpus size) each statement they do express will be uttered more frequently, both in absolute and relative terms. Specifically, a statement s about which nearly all authors express their belief (as either s or s̄) will occur twice as frequently in the entire corpus if reach = 50 as compared to reach = ∞. This increased presence in the training corpus may explain the closer match between degrees of belief and vote ratios.

Social choice theory implies, as noted above, that sentence-wise aggregation can result in logical inconsistencies. To which extent does this actually happen in our pre-trained models? Figure 2 displays the relative frequency of transitivity violations (see Section 3.5) for all societies and corresponding pre-trained models according to vote ratios (x-axis) and degrees of belief (y-axis). We observe that, first, the ratio of inconsistencies spreads widely and may be substantial, with some models violating as many as 1 out of 5 transitivity constraints. Second, doxastic transitivity violation (by a model) correlates clearly with vote ratio transitivity violation (Pearson's r = 0.54). This strongly suggests, for lack of an alternative explanation, that the observed incoherence of models' degrees of belief is actually due to their particular sentence-wise judgment aggregation. The models run into discursive dilemmas because they form beliefs, during pre-training, in accordance with sentence-wise vote ratios.

FIGURE 2
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 2. Initial transitivity violation according to degrees of belief (y-axis) and sentence-wise vote ratios (x-axis).

4.2. Coherence increase through self-training

What is the effect of self-training on the level of incoherence of a model's beliefs? Figure 3 plots the models' trajectories during self-training in a logical phase space—i.e., frequency of transitivity violations on the x-axis, mean degree of transitivity violations on the y-axis—, summarizing the time-series shown in Figures E.3, E.4 in the Appendix. It aggregates evolutions of models pre-trained on societies with the same number of authors, same reach threshold, and similar inter-author agreement. We see, first and foremost, that self-training drastically reduces incoherence: models move, along the trajectories, toward the plots' origins. For example, in societies with 15 authors, high diversity and limited reach (left-hand plot, orange trajectory marked with cross), the frequency of transitivity violations (x-axis) is brought down from roughly 15% to less than 4% with a simultaneous reduction in the mean degree of violation (y-axis). Ceteris paribus, these logical improvements of the models' belief systems (which show in the direction and length of the trajectories) are more substantial in societies with high divergence, for corpora that are not inferentially closed (i.e., reach = 50), and for models with high initial levels of incoherence. Consider, for example, societies with 25 authors (trajectories marked with a square) and compare models pre-trained on high-diversity corpora (left-hand plot) vs. those pre-trained on doxastically homogeneous, high-agreement corpora (right-hand plot): Models that have been exposed to highly diverse texts during pre-training (left-hand plot) do not only exhibit greater improvement relative to the initial level of inconsistency, but eventually even attain, in absolute terms, a lower ratio of transitivity violation.

FIGURE 3
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 3. Transitivity violation trajectories during self-training. Markers indicate the final state reached after self-training. Left: models pre-trained on a corpus with high inter-author diversity (kendall_tau < 0.055); right: models pre-trained on a corpus with low inter-author diversity (kendall_tau > 0.055). A trajectory averages over all models pre-trained on a corpus with a given number of agents (indicated by marker style) and a given reach threshold (indicated by color).

In the fine-tuning baseline, where models further train on texts from the corpus rather than on self-generated ones, there is no comparable improvement of beliefs, and the levels of incoherence stay generally far above those observed during self-training (cf. Figures E.3, E.4 in Appendix).

Why does self-training improve the models' beliefs? To better understand how a model modifies its beliefs, and for such diagnostic purposes only, we're parsing and logically evaluating the self-generated texts. This reveals, first, that the texts are, cum grano salis, inferentially structured and coherent. More precisely, while most sentences are logically independent (neutral) of the sentences previously stated in a text, the ratio of sentences that follow from what has been previously asserted is far greater than the ratio of contradictions (cf. Figure E.5 in Appendix). Moreover, belief elicitation reveals that the model occasionally assigns low degrees of belief to sentences in its self-generated texts (cf. Figure E.6 in Appendix). Or, put differently, the model asserts sentences in its texts which it actually disbelieves. All this points toward a mechanism of rational belief revision: In composing an inferentially structured text, starting with its own beliefs and drawing conclusions from what has been written before, the model locally spells out consequences of its beliefs and is brought—by the “unforced force” (Habermas, 1996) of valid inference—to assert sentences it may actually disbelieve. Training on these sentences then triggers a corresponding, coherence-conducive belief revision.

4.3. Mis-confidence correction through self-training

Are pre-trained models initially over- (or under-) confident, and how does self-training affect such mis-confidence? As the scatter-plots in Figure 4 show, pre-trained models tend to be globally over-confident (in the sense of Section 3.5): their degrees of belief are more informative than the collective vote ratios of the corresponding authors. As an exception, models trained on societies with many, strongly disagreeing authors are under-confident. Now, self-training corrects such mis-confidence in characteristic ways, as shown by the line-plots in Figure 4. In cases of initial under-confidence, self-training gradually increases the informativeness of the models' beliefs. In cases of over-confidence, self-training decreases informativeness immediately and sharply. This initial (typically over-shooting) correction tends to result in a state of under-confidence. Further self-training then gradually increases informativeness—in some cases even over and above the informativeness of collective vote ratios (as indicated by a second marker on a curve). We suggest that such a final surplus of informativeness is not necessarily a sign of global mis-confidence (i.e., error), but may simply reflect that the model has rationally consolidated its belief system. After reflective equilibration, the model may well be justified in holding beliefs that are more informative than the original collective vote ratios. All in all, self-training modifies the informativeness of a model's beliefs in—it seems—appropriate and reasonable ways.

FIGURE 4
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 4. Initial over- and under-confidence (scatter-plots), and informativeness evolution during self-training (line-plots). Top: corpora with high inter-author diversity (kendall_tau < 0.055); bottom: corpora with low inter-author diversity (kendall_tau > 0.055). In the scatter-plots, each marker represents a single pre-trained model, which exhibits over-confidence (under-confidence) if and only if its marker lies well above (below) the dotted diagonal. In the line-plots, the shown trajectories average over all models with the same number of agents and same reach threshold; the first marker designates the mean initial doxastic informativeness, the second one marks the step from which on mean doxastic informativeness is greater than average initial vote ratio informativeness.

4.4. Convergence during self-training

Does a model's belief system converge during self-training? In each self-training run, we are tracking the beliefs of the model on a fixed random sample of L-sentence, which allows us to estimate the extent of gradual belief change (volatility) and the global divergence of the belief system from the initial belief state. The most extensive belief change, we observe, takes place at the beginning of self-training, volatility then drops quickly, and further decays continuously (cf. Figure E.7, top row in Appendix). Likewise, the belief systems quickly diverge from the initial state, after which global divergence increases less and less slowly and eventually settles, or so it seems, at some level (cf. Figure E.7, bottom row in Appendix). Both volatility and global divergence from the initial state are more pronounced for models trained on high-diversity corpora than those trained on low-diversity corpora. In sum, we find that belief systems are not only improved during self-training, but tend to converge to a new belief state.

Further evidence for the seeming convergence of a model's belief system during self-training is provided by the observation that the model's degrees of belief in the most dis-believed sentences of its self-generated texts substantially increase during self-training (cf. Figure E.6 in Appendix). More and more, the model reaches a point where it believes what it says (or writes). This increasing confidence in the self-generated texts means that, as training data, these texts will trigger ever smaller belief revisions.

5. Conclusion

Social choice theory may help us to understand why the output of neural language models is frequently inconsistent. We show, in a fully synthetic experimental set-up, that NLMs aggregate judgments according to sentence-wise vote ratios, which inevitably leads to so-called discursive dilemmas (cf. Section 4.1). In particular, we diagnose that a pre-trained model's beliefs are ceteris paribus more incoherent if the training corpus is highly diverse or not inferentially closed. As a remedy, we propose a self-training procedure—inspired by the method of reflective equilibrium—that effectively reduces the extent of logical incoherence in a model's belief system (cf. Section 4.2), corrects global mis-confidence (cf. Section 4.3), and eventually allows the model to settle on a new belief state (cf. Section 4.4). The logical improvements induced by self-training are especially pronounced if the initial beliefs are extremely inconsistent; and it's precisely in these cases where we observe the furthest deviations of a model's belief system from the initial state during self-training. Moreover, inconsistencies are not simply resolved by giving up more and more beliefs: On the contrary, the continuous coherence increase during self-training goes hand in hand with a simultaneous growth of informativeness.

Training on self-generated texts is not only instrumentally rational (in bringing about doxastic improvements), but seems to be driven by a mechanism of reasonable belief revision, as additional diagnostic evidence suggests. Specifically, we find that self-generated texts are inferentially structured and can hence be considered to locally spell out logical consequences of a model's beliefs. But as the model, occasionally, strongly disbelieves some of these consequences, training on self-generated texts leads to a gradual revision of the corresponding beliefs. Conceptually, the more a text is disbelieved, the stronger a belief revision it induces. If, conversely, a model's texts express more or less exactly what the model believes, text production and belief system are in sync and the model has reached an equilibrium belief state that is not revised any further. Accordingly, we observe that models which undergo the most far-reaching belief revisions (in terms of coherence improvement and global deviation from the initial state) most strongly doubt—at least initially—the sentences in their self-generated texts. Also, this rational revision mechanism may explain why models pre-trained on highly diverse text corpora initially suffer from wide-spread inconsistencies, but are able to considerably self-improve their belief state nonetheless. That is because what drives rational belief revision is the ability to spell out consequences of one's beliefs, i.e., to generate logically structured texts. Now, while corpus diversity obviously hampers the consistent memorization of facts, it still allows for, and possibly even facilitates the learning of inferential structures and the reproduction of argumentative patterns in texts.

So, for the self-training language model, logical coherence is an emergent phenomenon. Consistency is not built into our system as an explicit goal or constraint (unlike, e.g., in Kassner et al., 2021b). Accordingly, and pace theories of cognitive consistency (Festinger, 1964; Gawronski and Strack, 2012), consistency-conducive cognition does not necessarily require a corresponding psychological motivation (such as resolving emotional dissonance)—which is not to deny that a motive to resolve inconsistency, too, can trigger coherence-increasing changes in belief.

Our study is limited in various and obvious ways, some of which we shall highlight here.

Training regimes. We have set-up our particular pre-training regime in analogy to the original denoising training of T5 (Raffel et al., 2020); whereas the self-training design, inspired by the method of reflective equilibrium, has been informed by pre-studies without being systematically optimized. So, it is unclear whether variations of our self-training method give rise to different, stronger or weaker doxastic improvements. And it is equally unclear whether different pre-training tasks will exacerbate, or mitigate the emergence of logical incoherence in the first place.

Artificial language. Our simple artificial language is logically just rich enough to allow for discursive dilemmas. It is unclear how the findings would be affected if the corpora were composed of texts in a more complex language with much more syntactic diversity, e.g., a language with quantification, with complex sentences, or with modal operators. Such complications would also open up further possibilities for eliciting beliefs as well as for designing a self-training regime.

Social dynamics. Our models reflect and revise their belief states in isolation. What happens if the self-training models start to interact? We don't know, though the literature on the emergence of natural language in deep multi-agent systems (Lazaridou et al., 2017; Lazaridou and Baroni, 2020) suggests that adding social dynamics might have profound effects (e.g., meaning shifts, conceptual revisions) beyond mere inconsistency correction. There exist multiple kinds of interaction that could be investigated in this study's framework: Models could self-generate training texts in dialogues rather than monologically; models could train on texts generated by peers; and models could elicit each others' beliefs and assess mutual trustworthiness (cf. Zollman, 2013; Flache et al., 2017).

Ground truth. In the current experimental design, a corpus may be more or less diverse (reflecting the level of inter-author agreement), but there is no ground truth. However, such a ground truth may be easily introduced into the set-up. This would allow one to study (i) the models' ability to track the truth during pre- and self-training, and (ii) the extent to which this ability depends, e.g., on the accuracy or diversity of the underlying text corpus.

Transfer to natural language. To which degree do the clear results we obtain in our fully artificial set-up apply to NLMs trained on natural language data? Let us first note that our diagnosis and proposed remedy are consistent with previous findings on reporting frequencies (Shwartz and Choi, 2020), respectively self-improvement via iterative back-translation (Guo Y. et al., 2021). Nonetheless, we concede that this does not settle the transferability question. This paper's study merely suggests explanatory hypotheses. And it investigates specific mechanisms in isolation. To understand, e.g., whether the observed inconsistency of natural language NLMs is actually induced by discursive dilemmas, NLMs (of different architecture and size) and training datasets would have to be systematically probed in specific ways. Moreover, only experimental studies can reveal whether a self-training procedure, similar to the one described here, may help natural language NLMs to improve their belief state as well.

In sum, we submit that our study raises a variety of fruitful questions that may be pursued in future research. More generally, by demonstrating that NLMs' inconsistencies can be explained in terms of discursive dilemmas and may be resolved by reflective equilibration, it encourages the further exploration of philosophical concepts and theories in the domain of AI and NLP.

Data availability statement

The original contributions presented in the study are included in the article/Supplementary material, further inquiries can be directed to the corresponding author.

Author contributions

All authors listed have made a substantial, direct, and intellectual contribution to the work and approved it for publication.

Funding

This work was supported by the Helmholtz Association Initiative and Networking Fund on the HAICORE@KIT partition.

Acknowledgments

We would like to thank Georg Brun, Christian Seidel, and Christian Voigt as well as the participants of the research seminar at KIT's Department of Philosophy for helpful comments on an earlier version of this paper.

Conflict of interest

The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Publisher's note

All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article, or claim that may be made by its manufacturer, is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.

Supplementary material

The Supplementary Material for this article can be found online at: https://www.frontiersin.org/articles/10.3389/frai.2022.900943/full#supplementary-material

Footnotes

1. ^Prompting https://huggingface.co/xlm-roberta-large (as of 11/23/2021) with “Warsaw lies <mask> of Berlin.” etc.

2. ^Prompting https://delphi.allenai.org (as of 11/23/2021) with “Should I hurt the cat so that the dog can survive, which it couldn't otherwise?,” “Should I hurt the dog so that the cat can survive, which it couldn't otherwise?,” and “Should I let the cat and the dog die?”.

References

Alchourron, C. E., Gärdenfors, P., and Makinson, D. (1985). On the logic of theory change-partial meet contraction and revision functions. J. Symbolic Logic 50, 510–530.

Google Scholar

Arrow, K. J. (1951). Social Choice and Individual Values. New York, NY: Wiley.

Google Scholar

Banerjee, P., Baral, C., Luo, M., Mitra, A., Pal, K. K., Son, T. C., et al. (2020). Can transformers reason about effects of actions? CoRR, abs/2012.09938. doi: 10.48550/arXiv.2012.09938

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Baumberger, C., and Brun, G. (2016). “Dimensions of objectual understanding,” in Explaining Understanding (London: Routledge), 181–205.

Google Scholar

Beisbart, C., Betz, G., and Brun, G. (2021). Making reflective equilibrium precise. a formal model. Ergo 8, 15. doi: 10.3998/ergo.1152

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Betz, G, Richardson, K., and Voigt, C. (2021a). Thinking aloud: Dynamic context generation improves zero-shot reasoning performance of GPT-2. arXiv:2103.13033. doi: 10.48550/arXiv.2103.13033

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Betz, G., Voigt, C., and Richardson, K. (2021b). “Critical thinking for language models,” in Proceedings of the 14th International Conference on Computational Semantics (IWCS) (Association for Computational Linguistics). Available online at: https://aclanthology.org/2021.iwcs-1.7.

Google Scholar

Bosselut, A., Bras, R. L., and Choi, Y. (2019a). Dynamic neuro-symbolic knowledge graph construction for zero-shot commonsense question answering. arXiv preprint arXiv:1911.03876. doi: 10.48550/arXiv.1911.03876

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bosselut, A., Rashkin, H., Sap, M., Malaviya, C., Çelikyilmaz, A., and Choi, Y. (2019b). “Comet: commonsense transformers for automatic knowledge graph construction,” in Proceedings of the 57th Annual Meeting of the Association for Computational Linguistics (Florence: Association for Computational Linguistics).

Google Scholar

Bostrom, K., Zhao, X., Chaudhuri, S., and Durrett, G. (2021). “Flexible generation of natural language deductions,” in Proceedings of the 2021 Conference on Empirical Methods in Natural Language Processing, EMNLP 2021, Virtual Event / Punta Cana, Dominican Republic, 7-11 November, 2021, eds M, Marie-Francine, H. Xuanjing, S. Lucia, and Y. Scott Wen-tau (Association for Computational Linguistics), 6266–6278. Available online at: https://aclanthology.org/2021.emnlp-main.506.

Google Scholar

Brown, T. B., Mann, B., Ryder, N., Subbiah, M., Kaplan, J., Dhariwal, P., et al. (2020). Language models are few-shot learners. arXiv:2005.14165. doi: 10.48550/arXiv.2005.14165

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Brun, G. (2014). Reflective equilibrium without intuitions? Ethical Theory Moral Pract. 17, 237–252. doi: 10.1007/s10677-013-9432-5

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Chen, J., Lin, S. T., and Durrett, G. (2019). Multi-hop question answering via reasoning chains. ArXiv abs/1910.02610. doi: 10.48550/arXiv.1910.02610

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Clark, P., Tafjord, O., and Richardson, K. (2020). “Transformers as soft reasoners over language,” in Proceedings of the Twenty-Ninth International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence (Yokohama), 3882–3890.

Google Scholar

Conneau, A., Khandelwal, K., Goyal, N., Chaudhary, V., Wenzek, G., Guzmán, F., et al. (2019). Unsupervised cross-lingual representation learning at scale. CoRR, abs/1911.02116. doi: 10.48550/arXiv.1911.02116

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Corbière, C., Thome, N., Bar-Hen, A., Cord, M., and Pérez, P. (2019). “Addressing failure prediction by learning model confidence,” in NeurIPS (Vancouver, BC).

Google Scholar

Da, J., Le Bras, R., Lu, X., Choi, Y., and Bosselut, A. (2021). “analyzing commonsense emergence in few-shot knowledge models,” in 3rd Conference on Automated Knowledge Base Construction (London).

Google Scholar

Dalvi, B., Jansen, P., Tafjord, O., Xie, Z., Smith, H., Pipatanangkura, L., et al. (2021). Explaining answers with entailment trees. arXiv preprint arXiv:2104.08661. doi: 10.48550/arXiv.2104.08661

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Daniels, N. (1996). Justice and Justification: Reflective Equilibrium in Theory and Practice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Google Scholar

Desai, S., and Durrett, G. (2020). Calibration of pre-trained transformers. ArXiv abs/2003.07892. doi: 10.48550/arXiv.2003.07892

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Devlin, J., Chang, M. W., Lee, K., and Toutanova, K. (2019). “Bert: pre-training of deep bidirectional transformers for language understanding,” in NAACL-HLT (Minneapolis, MN).

Google Scholar

Du, J., Grave, E., Gunel, B., Chaudhary, V., Celebi, O., Auli, M., et al. (2021). ‘Self-training improves pre-training for natural language understanding,” in Proceedings of the 2021 Conference of the North American Chapter of the Association for Computational Linguistics: Human Language Technologies, NAACL-HLT 2021, Online, June 6-11, 2021, eds K. Toutanova, A. Rumshisky, L. Zettlemoyer, D. Hakkani-Tür, I. Beltagy, S. Bethard, R. Cotterell, T. Chakraborty, and Y. Zhou (Association for Computational Linguistics), 5408–5418. [Epub ahead of print].

Google Scholar

Elazar, Y., Kassner, N., Ravfogel, S., Ravichander, A., Hovy, E. H., Schütze, H., et al. (2021). Measuring and improving consistency in pretrained language models. Trans. Assoc. Comput. Linguist. 9, 1012–1031. doi: 10.48550/arXiv.2102.01017

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Elgin, C. Z. (2017). True Enough. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Google Scholar

Ettinger, A. (2020). What bert is not: Lessons from a new suite of psycholinguistic diagnostics for language models. Trans. Assoc. Comput. Linguist. 8, 34–48. doi: 10.48550/arXiv.1907.13528

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Festinger, L. (1964). Conflict, Decision, and Dissonance, Vol. 3. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

Google Scholar

Flache, A., Mäs, M., Feliciani, T., Chattoe-Brown, E., Deffuant, G., Huet, S., et al. (2017). Models of social influence: towards the next frontiers. J. Artif. Soc. Soc. Simul. 20, 2. doi: 10.18564/jasss.3521

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gawronski, B., and Strack, F. (2012). Cognitive Consistency: A Fundamental Principle in Social Cognition. New York, NY: Guilford Press.

Google Scholar

Goldstein, A., Zada, Z. K., Buchnik, E., Schain, M., Price, A. R., and Aubrey, B. (2020). Thinking ahead: spontaneous prediction in context as a keystone of language in humans and machines. bioRxiv. doi: 10.1101/2020.12.02.403477

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gontier, N., Sinha, K., Reddy, S., and Pal, C. (2020). “Measuring systematic generalization in neural proof generation with transformers,” in Advances in Neural Information Processing Systems. p. 22231–22242.

Google Scholar

Goodman, N. (1955). Fact, Fiction, and Forecast. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Google Scholar

Guo, C., Pleiss, G., Sun, Y., and Weinberger, K. (2017). On calibration of modern neural networks. ArXiv abs/1706.04599. doi: 10.48550/arXiv.1706.04599

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Guo, H., Pasunuru, R., and Bansal, M. (2021). “An overview of uncertainty calibration for text classification and the role of distillation,” in Proceedings of the 6th Workshop on Representation Learning for NLP (RepL4NLP-2021). Available online at: https://aclanthology.org/2021.repl4nlp-1.29.

Google Scholar

Guo, Y., Zhu, H., Lin, Z., Chen, B., Lou, J. G., and Zhang, D. (2021). “Revisiting iterative back-translation from the perspective of compositional generalization,” in AAAI.

Google Scholar

Habermas, J. (1996). Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Google Scholar

He, X., Nassar, I., Kiros, J., Haffari, G., and Norouzi, M. (2021). Generate, annotate, and learn: generative models advance self-training and knowledge distillation. CoRR, abs/2106.06168. doi: 10.48550/arXiv.2106.06168

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hendrycks, D., Burns, C., Basart, S., Zou, A., Mazeika, M., Song, D., et al. (2020). “Measuring massive multitask language understanding,” in International Conference on Learning Representations.

Google Scholar

Holtzman, A., Buys, J., Du, L., Forbes, M., and Choi, Y. (2019). “The curious case of neural text degeneration,” in International Conference on Learning Representations (New Orleans, LA).

Google Scholar

Jang, M., Kwon, D. S., and Lukasiewicz, T. (2021). Accurate, yet inconsistent? consistency analysis on language understanding models. ArXiv abs/2108.06665. doi: 10.48550/arXiv.2108.06665

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Jeffrey, R. (1965). The Logic of Decision. Chicago: University of Chicago Press..

Google Scholar

Jiang, L., Bosselut, A., Bhagavatula, C., and Choi, Y. (2021a). “i'm not mad”: Commonsense implications of negation and contradiction. ArXiv abs/2104.06511. doi: 10.48550/arXiv.2104.06511

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Jiang, L., Hwang, J. D., Bhagavatula, C., Bras, R. L., Forbes, M., Borchardt, J., et al. (2021b). Delphi: towards machine ethics and norms. arXiv preprint arXiv:2110.07574. doi: 10.48550/arXiv.2110.07574

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, Fast and Slow, 1st Edn. New York, NY: Farrar; Straus and Giroux.

Google Scholar

Kassner, N., Krojer, B., and Schütze, H. (2020). “Are pretrained language models symbolic reasoners over knowledge?” in Proceedings of the 24th Conference on Computational Natural Language Learning (Association for Computational Linguistics), 552–564. Available online at: https://www.aclweb.org/anthology/2020.conll-1.45.

Google Scholar

Kassner, N., and Schütze, H. (2020). “Negated and misprimed probes for pretrained language models: Birds can talk, but cannot fly,” in Proceedings of the 58th Annual Meeting of the Association for Computational Linguistics (Association for Computational Linguistics), 7811–7818. Available online at: https://www.aclweb.org/anthology/2020.acl-main.698.

Google Scholar

Kassner, N., Tafjord, O., Schutze, H., and Clark, P. (2021a). “Beliefbank: adding memory to a pre-trained language model for a systematic notion of belief,” in EMNLP (Punta Cana).

Google Scholar

Kassner, N., Tafjord, O., Schütze, H., and Clark, P. E. (2021b). Enriching a model's notion of belief using a persistent memory. ArXiv abs/2104.08401. doi: 10.48550/arXiv.2104.08401

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kelly, K. T. (1996). The Logic of Reliable Inquiry. Logic and Computation in Philosophy. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Kumar, A., and Sarawagi, S. (2019). Calibration of encoder decoder models for neural machine translation. arXiv [Preprint]. arXiv: 1903.00802. doi: 10.48550/arXiv.1903.00802

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Lakshminarayanan, B., Pritzel, A., and Blundell, C. (2017). “Simple and scalable predictive uncertainty estimation using deep ensembles,” in NIPS (Long Beach, CA).

Google Scholar

Lazaridou, A., and Baroni, M. (2020). Emergent multi-agent communication in the deep learning era. ArXiv abs/2006.02419. doi: 10.48550/arXiv.2006.02419

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Lazaridou, A., Peysakhovich, A., and Baroni, M. (2017). Multi-agent cooperation and the emergence of (natural) language. ArXiv abs/1612.07182. doi: 10.48550/arXiv.1612.07182

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Lewis, P. S. H., Perez, E., Piktus, A., Petroni, F., Karpukhin, V., Goyal, N., et al. (2020). “Retrieval-augmented generation for knowledge-intensive NLP tasks,” in Advances in Neural Information Processing Systems 33: Annual Conference on Neural Information Processing Systems 2020, NeurIPS 2020, December 6-12, 2020, virtual, eds H. Larochelle, M. Ranzato, R. Hadsell, B. Maria-Florina, and L. Hsuan-Tien Lin. Available online at: https://proceedings.neurips.cc/paper/2020/hash/6b493230205f780e1bc26945df7481e5-Abstract.html.

Google Scholar

List, C. (2013) “Social choice theory,” in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed E. N. Zalta (Stanford, CA: Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University).

Google Scholar

Liu, Y., Ott, M., Goyal, N., Du, J., Joshi, M., Chen, D., et al. (2019). RoBERTa: A robustly optimized BERT pretraining approach. arXiv [Preprint]. arXiv 1907.11692. doi: 10.48550/arXiv.1907.11692

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Manning, C. D., and Schütze, H. (1999). Foundations of Statistical Natural Language Processing. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Google Scholar

Mi, F., Zhou, W., Kong, L., Cai, F., Huang, M., and Faltings, B. (2021). “Self-training improves pre-training for few-shot learning in task-oriented dialog systems,” in Proceedings of the 2021 Conference on Empirical Methods in Natural Language Processing, EMNLP 2021, Virtual Event / Punta Cana, Dominican Republic, 7–11 November, 2021, eds M. Marie-Francine, H. Xuanjing, S. Lucia, and Y. Scott Wen-tau (Association for Computational Linguistics), 1887–1898. Available online at: https://aclanthology.org/2021.emnlp-main.142.

Google Scholar

Minervini, P., Bosnjak, M., Rocktäschel, T., Riedel, S., and Grefenstette, E. (2020). “Differentiable reasoning on large knowledge bases and natural language,” in The Thirty-Fourth AAAI Conference on Artificial Intelligence, AAAI 2020, The Thirty-Second Innovative Applications of Artificial Intelligence Conference, IAAI 2020, The Tenth AAAI Symposium on Educational Advances in Artificial Intelligence, EAAI 2020, New York, NY, USA, February 7–12, 2020 (New York, NY: AAAI Press), 5182–5190.

Google Scholar

Moon, J., Kim, J., Shin, Y., and Hwang, S. (2020). Confidence-aware learning for deep neural networks. ArXiv abs/2007.01458. doi: 10.48550/arXiv.2007.01458

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Noorbakhsh, K., Sulaiman, M., Sharifi, M., Roy, K., and Jamshidi, P. (2021). Pretrained language models are symbolic mathematics solvers too! ArXiv abs/2110.03501. doi: 10.48550/arXiv.2110.03501

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Nye, M. I., Tessler, M. H., Tenenbaum, J. B., and Lake, B. M. (2021). Improving coherence and consistency in neural sequence models with dual-system, neuro-symbolic reasoning. CoRR abs/2107.02794, 2021. doi: 10.48550/arXiv.2107.02794

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Petroni, F., Lewis, P., Piktus, A., Rocktäschel, T., Wu, Y., Miller, A. H., et al. (2020). “How context affects language models' factual predictions,” in Automated Knowledge Base Construction (Irvine, CA).

Google Scholar

Petroni, F., Rocktäschel, T., Riedel, S., Lewis, P., Bakhtin, A., Wu, Y., et al. (2019). “Language models as knowledge bases?” in Proceedings of the 2019 Conference on Empirical Methods in Natural Language Processing and the 9th International Joint Conference on Natural Language Processing (EMNLP-IJCNLP) (Hong Kong: Association for Computational Linguistics), 2463–2473.

Google Scholar

Pettit, P. (2001). Deliberative democracy and the discursive dilemma. Philos. Issues 11, 268–299. Available online at: https://www.jstor.org/stable/3050604

Google Scholar

Polu, S., and Sutskever, I. (2020). Generative language modeling for automated theorem proving. ArXiv abs/2009.03393. doi: 10.48550/arXiv.2009.03393

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Radford, A., Wu, J., Child, R., Luan, D., Amodei, D., and Sutskever, I. (2019). Language models are unsupervised multitask learners. Preprint. Available online at: https://cdn.openai.com/better-language-models/language_models_are_unsupervised_multitask_learners.pdf.

Google Scholar

Raffel, C., Shazeer, N., Roberts, A., Lee, K., Narang, S., Matena, M., et al. (2020). Exploring the limits of transfer learning with a unified text-to-text transformer. J. Mach. Learn. Res. 21, 1–67. doi: 10.48550/arXiv.1910.10683

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Rawls, J. (1971). A Theory of Justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Google Scholar

Ribeiro, M., Guestrin, C., and Singh, S. (2019). “Are red roses red? evaluating consistency of question-answering models,” in Proceedings of the 57th Conference of the Association for Computational Linguistics, ACL 2019, Florence, Italy, July 28-August 2, 2019, Volume 1: Long Papers, eds A. Korhonen, D. R. Traum, and L. Màrquez (Florence: Association for Computational Linguistics), 6174-6184.

Google Scholar

Saeed, M., Ahmadi, N., Nakov, P., and Papotti, P. (2021). “Rulebert: teaching soft rules to pre-trained language models,” in Proceedings of the 2021 Conference on Empirical Methods in Natural Language Processing, EMNLP 2021, Virtual Event / Punta Cana, Dominican Republic, 7-11 November, 2021, eds M. Marie-Francine, X. Huang, L. Specia, and Y. Scott Wen-tau (Association for Computational Linguistics), 1460–1476. Anvailable online at: https://aclanthology.org/2021.emnlp-main.110.

Google Scholar

Saha, S., Ghosh, S., Srivastava, S., and Bansal, M. (2020). “Prover: proof generation for interpretable reasoning over rules,” in Proceedings of the 2020 Conference on Empirical Methods in Natural Language Processing, EMNLP 2020, Online, November 16-20, 2020, eds B. Webber, T. Cohn, Y. He, and Y. Liu (Association for Computational Linguistics), 122–136. [Epub ahead of print].

Google Scholar

Saha, S., Yadav, P., and Bansal, M. (2021). multiprover: generating multiple proofs for improved interpretability in rule reasoning. ArXiv abs/2106.01354. doi: 10.48550/arXiv.2106.01354

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Schrimpf, M., Blank, I. A., Tuckute, G., Kauf, C., Hosseini, E. A., Kanwisher, N., et al. (2021). The neural architecture of language: Integrative modeling converges on predictive processing. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 118, e21056461. doi: 10.1073/pnas.2105646118

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Seo, J., Park, C., Eo, S., Moon, H., and Lim, H. (2021). Automatic knowledge augmentation for generative commonsense reasoning. CoRR abs/2111.00192. doi: 10.48550/arXiv.2111.00192

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Shwartz, V., and Choi, Y. (2020). “Do neural language models overcome reporting bias?,” in Proceedings of the 28th International Conference on Computational Linguistics, COLING 2020, Barcelona, Spain (Online), December 8–13, 2020, eds S. Donia, B. Núria, and Z. Chengqing (Barcelona: International Committee on Computational Linguistics), 6863–6870.

Google Scholar

Shwartz, V., West, P., Bras, R. L., Bhagavatula, C., and Choi, Y. (2020). “Unsupervised commonsense question answering with self-talk,” in Proceedings of the 2020 Conference on Empirical Methods in Natural Language Processing, EMNLP 2020, Online, November 16-20, 2020, eds W. Bonnie, C. Trevor, H. Yulan, and L. Yang (Association for Computational Linguistics), 4615–4629. [Epub ahead of print].

Google Scholar

Simon, D., Snow, C. J., and Read, S. J. (2004). The redux of cognitive consistency theories: evidence judgments by constraint satisfaction. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 86, 814–837. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.86.6.814

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Simon, D., Stenstrom, D. M., and Read, S. J. (2015). “The coherence effect: Blending cold and hot cognitions,” in University of Southern California Center for Law & Social Science (CLASS) Research Paper Series (Los Angeles, CA).

Google Scholar

Sinha, K., Sodhani, S., Dong, J., Pineau, J., and Hamilton, W. L. (2019). “CLUTRR: a diagnostic benchmark for inductive reasoning from text,” in Proceedings of the 2019 Conference on Empirical Methods in Natural Language Processing and the 9th International Joint Conference on Natural Language Processing, EMNLP-IJCNLP 2019, Hong Kong, China, November 3-7, 2019, eds I. Kentaro, J. Jing, N. Vincent, and W. Xiaojun (Hong Kong: Association for Computational Linguistics), 4505–4514.

Google Scholar

Tafjord, O., Mishra, B. D., and Clark, P. (2020). Proofwriter: generating implications, proofs, and abductive statements over natural language. arXiv preprint arXiv:2012.13048. doi: 10.48550/arXiv.2012.13048

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Talmor, A., Elazar, Y., Goldberg, Y., and Berant, J. (2020). olmpics-on what language model pre-training captures. Trans. Assoc. Comput. Linguist. 8, 743–758. doi: 10.48550/arXiv.1912.13283

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Tersman, F. (1993). Reflective Equilibrium. An Essay in Moral Epistemology. Stockholm: Almquist & Wiksells International.

Google Scholar

Thagard, P. (1992). Conceptual Revolutions. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Google Scholar

Thagard, P. (2000). Coherence in Thought and Action. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Google Scholar

Vaswani, A., Shazeer, N., Parmar, N., Uszkoreit, J., Jones, L., Gomez, A. N., et al. (2017). Attention is all you need. ArXiv abs/1706.03762. doi: 10.48550/arXiv.1706.03762

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Weber, L., Minervini, P., Münchmeyer, J., Leser, U., and Rocktäschel, T. (2019). “Nlprolog: reasoning with weak unification for question answering in natural language,” in Proceedings of the 57th Conference of the Association for Computational Linguistics, ACL 2019, Florence, Italy, July 28- August 2, 2019, Volume 1: Long Papers, eds K. Anna, R. T. David, and M. Lluís (Florence: Association for Computational Linguistics), 6151–6161.

Google Scholar

Wolf, T., Debut, L., Sanh, V., Chaumond, J., Delangue, C., Moi, A., et al. (2020). “Transformers: state-of-the-art natural language processing,” in Proceedings of the 2020 Conference on Empirical Methods in Natural Language Processing: System Demonstrations (Association for Computational Linguistics), 38–45. Available online at: https://www.aclweb.org/anthology/2020.emnlp-demos.6

Google Scholar

Yang, Y., Malaviya, C., Fernandez, J., Swayamdipta, S., Bras, R. L., Wang, J., et al. (2020). “G-daug: generative data augmentation for commonsense reasoning,” in Findings of the Association for Computational Linguistics: EMNLP 2020, Online Event, 16-20 November 2020, volume EMNLP 2020 of Findings of ACL, eds C. Trevor, H. Yulan, and L. Yang (Association for Computational Linguistics), 1008–1025. [Epub ahead of print].

Google Scholar

Yang, Z., Qi, P., Zhang, S., Bengio, Y., Cohen, W. W., Salakhutdinov, R., et al. (2018). Hotpotqa: a dataset for diverse, explainable multi-hop question answering. ArXiv abs/1809.09600. doi: 10.48550/arXiv.1809.09600

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Yilmaz, L., Franco-Watkins, A. M., and Kroecker, T. S. (2016). “Coherence-driven reflective equilibrium model of ethical decision-making,” in 2016 IEEE International Multi-Disciplinary Conference on Cognitive Methods in Situation Awareness and Decision Support (CogSIMA) (San Diego, CA|: IEEE), 42–48.

Google Scholar

Zaheer, M., Guruganesh, G., Dubey, K. A., Ainslie, J., Alberti, C., Ontañón, S., et al. (2020). “Big bird: transformers for longer sequences,” in Advances in Neural Information Processing Systems 33: Annual Conference on Neural Information Processing Systems 2020, NeurIPS 2020, December 6-12, 2020, virtual, eds L. Hugo, R. Marc'Aurelio, H. Raia, B. Maria-Florina, and L. Hsuan-Tien. Available online at: https://proceedings.neurips.cc/paper/2020/hash/c8512d142a2d849725f31a9a7a361ab9-Abstract.html.

Google Scholar

Zellers, R., Holtzman, A., Peters, M. E., Mottaghi, R., Kembhavi, A., Farhadi, A., et al. (2021). “Piglet: language grounding through neuro-symbolic interaction in a 3d world,” in ACL/IJCNLP (Bangkok).

Google Scholar

Zhou, P., Khanna, R., Lin, B. Y., Ho, D., Ren, X., and Pujara, J. (2020). Can BERT reason? logically equivalent probes for evaluating the inference capabilities of language models. CoRR abs/2005.00782, 2020. doi: 10.48550/arXiv.2005.00782

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Zimmermann, A. (Ed.). (2020). Daily Nous Blog: Philosophers On GPT-3. Available online at: http://dailynous.com/2020/07/30/philosophers-gpt-3/.

Google Scholar

Zollman, K. J. S. (2013). Network epistemology: communication in epistemic communities. Philos. Compass 8, 15–27. doi: 10.1111/j.1747-9991.2012.00534.x

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Keywords: neural language model (NLM), judgment aggregation, reflective equilibrium, text generation, logical consistency

Citation: Betz G and Richardson K (2022) Judgment aggregation, discursive dilemma and reflective equilibrium: Neural language models as self-improving doxastic agents. Front. Artif. Intell. 5:900943. doi: 10.3389/frai.2022.900943

Received: 21 March 2022; Accepted: 15 September 2022;
Published: 18 October 2022.

Edited by:

Tim Rocktäschel, University College London, United Kingdom

Reviewed by:

Shane Steinert-Threlkeld, University of Washington, United States
Parisa Kordjamshidi, Michigan State University, United States

Copyright © 2022 Betz and Richardson. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Gregor Betz, gregor.betz@kit.edu

Download