Your new experience awaits. Try the new design now and help us make it even better

EDITORIAL article

Front. Polit. Sci.

Sec. Peace and Democracy

Volume 7 - 2025 | doi: 10.3389/fpos.2025.1668190

This article is part of the Research TopicReview Symposium: The Problem of DemocracyView all 8 articles

Introduction: Review Symposium on Shadi Hamid's The Problem of Democracy

Provisionally accepted
  • University of Pittsburgh, Pittsburgh, United States

The final, formatted version of the article will be published soon.

The contributors to this symposium engage with Hamid's thesis from a variety of angles, often highlighting points of tension or disagreement. A central debate revolves around whether democracy can truly be separated from liberalism without jeopardizing democratic stability. Several authors caution that completely decoupling liberal norms might undermine democracy in the long run. Sam Mace contends that Hamid's minimalist formula is inherently fragile. In Mace's analysis, a democracy that limits itself to electoral procedures while neglecting liberal protections can open the door for illiberal elected leaders to erode democracy from within. Citing contemporary Hungary as an example of a democracy that retained formal elections but suffered severe backsliding, Mace argues that procedural minimalism is "too thin" a foundation-without a thicker bedrock of liberal institutions or civic norms, democracy may not be self-sustaining. Omar Sadr offers a related critique: rather than abandoning liberalism, Sadr believes democracies should adopt a pluralistic approach that accommodates a range of cultural and religious values. He suggests that Hamid's vision paints liberalism, secularism, and Islamism with too broad a brush. By developing a democratic pluralism that allows for diversity and dialogue (instead of a strict minimalist bargain of democracy in exchange for illiberal governance), Sadr argues it's possible to reconcile Islamic political movements with certain liberal principles over time. Both Mace and Sadr, in different ways, raise the concern that a democracy needs more than just ballots and acceptance of results -it also requires either normative guardrails or a pluralistic openness to truly thrive.Other contributors focus on what democratic minimalism might overlook in terms of public expectations and effective governance. Salih Yasun points out that many citizens, especially in Arab countries, judge democracy by its ability to deliver tangible benefits like jobs and economic growth. If a minimalist democracy does not improve people's lives, Yasun warns, it could quickly lose legitimacy. In his analysis of survey data, a recurring theme is that "democracy with adjectives" -democracy coupled with social goods like economic development -is what people often desire. Hamid's minimalism deliberately sets aside these performance expectations, but Yasun's findings suggest that this separation may be hard to sustain politically: voters might not remain content with procedural democracy alone if it doesn't meet their needs, leading to disenchantment or a turn back toward authoritarian "deliverers." Jennifer Brick Murtazashvili similarly argues that Hamid's blueprint is incomplete, but from an institutional angle. Drawing on the state-building experience in Afghanistan, she observes that simply holding elections (a minimalist democracy) did little to produce a stable or accountable government there. The missing ingredient, she contends, was good governance -effective institutions, rule of law, and inclusion of local self-governance. Thus, both Yasun and Murtazashvili highlight that real-world democracies are judged by more than just their electoral process: economic outcomes and governance quality are critical to their success or failure. Hamid's call for a "democracy-first" U.S. foreign policy -embracing electoral legitimacy even when outcomes are illiberal -receives careful scrutiny. John J. Chin is skeptical of such a pivot and challenges three core assumptions. First, he questions whether the divergence between democracy and liberalism is as sharp or consequential as Hamid claims, noting that even illiberal democracies need basic rights protections. Second, he doubts Hamid's portrayal of Arab autocracies as inherently brittle, warning that sudden democratization could lead to instability. Third, Chin critiques the suggested trade-off between supporting Arab democracy and maintaining Arab-Israeli peace, arguing that abandoning the long-standing "stability-first" approach could have unintended consequences. In contrast, Haroun Rahimi engages Hamid from a historical and philosophical angle. He agrees that efforts to impose liberalism in Muslimmajority societies have often failed but argues Hamid does not go far enough. Rahimi suggests rethinking the nation-state model itself, drawing on pre-modern Islamic governance traditions that allowed local communities autonomy. This approach, he argues, could reduce conflict between secularists and Islamists by enabling democratic pluralism within decentralized systems-an alternative Hamid's framework largely overlooks. Throughout these discussions, the tone of the symposium remains analytical and constructive. Ilia Murtazashvili, for example, while generally positive about Hamid's contributions, points out that incorporating economic liberty, especially market freedoms, might further reinforce democratic resilience. In doing so, he echoes a common theme among the contributors: that democracy's survival may depend on factors beyond the minimal procedural elements. Whether it is liberal values, pluralistic accommodation, economic performance, strong governance, or innovative constitutional frameworks, each author identifies something additional that democratic minimalism must consider or contend with. Hamid's The Problem of Democracy succeeds in provoking the kind of debate urgently needed about the relationship between democracy and liberalism. His argument for democratic minimalism -prioritizing electoral legitimacy over liberal outcomes -raises pressing questions that scholars and policymakers will continue to grapple with. Is minimalist democracy a stable political order or a regime continually on the brink of autocracy? Should the promotion of democracy still include concern for liberal values and not just state capacity? How well can U.S. foreign policy navigate the tension between its ideals and its strategic interests? These questions are especially salient amid the evolving trajectory of the Abraham Accords, the twelve-day war with Iran in the summer of 2025, and continuing uncertainty over what kind of democracy, if any, might emerge in Gaza. By disentangling democracy from liberalism, Hamid forces a reexamination of assumptions that have long shaped U.S. engagement abroad. The provocative and uncomfortable ideas in this book are part of an ongoing conversation about the future of democracy in an illiberal age.

Keywords: Democracy, democracy promotion, Middle East, U.S. Foreing Policy, Pluralism, liberalism

Received: 17 Jul 2025; Accepted: 22 Jul 2025.

Copyright: © 2025 Murtazashvili and Murtazashvili. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) or licensor are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

* Correspondence: Ilia Murtazashvili, University of Pittsburgh, Pittsburgh, United States

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.