Skip to main content

OPINION article

Front. Sociol., 25 January 2022
Sec. Sociological Theory
Volume 7 - 2022 | https://doi.org/10.3389/fsoc.2022.814338

Neurosociology and Penal Neuroabolitionism: Rethinking Justice With Neuroscience

  • 1The Latin American Observatory of Human Rights and Enterprises, NeuroRights Research Group, Universidad Externado de Colombia, Bogotá, Colombia
  • 2Rizoma and Legal Psychology Research Groups, Universidad Nacional Abierta y a Distancia, Bogotá, Colombia

Introduction

Penal Neuroabolitionism is a complementary thesis to the sociological abolitionism of Nils Christie, Thomas Mathiesen and Louk Hulsman (Borbón, 2021). This new approach is based on the findings of science, especially neuroscience, to provide new arguments to the abolitionist perspective that criminal law is an illegitimate mechanism of social control. In that sense, it closely approximates neurosociology as a new scope for transdisciplinary social analysis. In this brief opinion, we offer three commentaries for future work: on the neuropsychological effects of prison, on the ability of neuroscience to analyze and prevent criminogenic social factors, and a critical perspective on free will as a narrative to justify criminal law as a mechanism of social control. These considerations invite scholars around the world to study, within the field of neuroscience, the new arguments for penal abolitionism.

Neurosociology and Penal Abolitionism

The sociological European penal abolitionism led by Christie, Mathiesen and Hulsman denounces the illegitimacy of criminal law, as a sterile and futile way of imposing pain. Abolitionism holds that the criminal justice system is a social problem in itself and the complete abolition of this system is considered to be the only adequate solution (De Folter, 1986). According to Christie, social systems should be built in a way that minimizes the need to impose pain to achieve social control, as the hell created by man through criminal law is avoidable (Christie, 1981). This argument is further supported by the fact that this pain imposed is usually selective, since it historically punishes particularly vulnerable groups of people (Vegh, 2017). In general, sociological abolitionism has created a body of theories to explain the necessary substitution of criminal law for more humane and restorative alternatives (Christie, 1981; Hulsman, 1991; Mathiesen, 2006; Mathiesen, 2015).

In this direction, neurosociology is a new label for thinking about the human brain and its relationship to human interaction and social organization (Franks and Turner, 2013). Indeed, with advances in science, it is possible to glimpse the usefulness of neurosociology as a new scope for transdisciplinary social analysis to provide innovative arguments in favor of the abolitionist thesis. In particular, a transdisciplinary approach is essential when considering individual and social deviant behaviors.

Adverse Neuropsychological Effects of Imprisonment

Imprisonment is the most widely used form of punishment in contemporary penal systems. In 2021, more than 11.5 million people were incarcerated in prisons worldwide (Fair and Walmsley, 2021). However, multiple authors have exposed the uselessness of imprisonment, except in a few cases of extreme danger, where the prison fulfills a dubious function of “quarantine” or isolation of the offender (Pereboom, 2003; 2019). Thomas Mathiesen (2006) devoted his intellectual effort to show that, when evaluated in terms of the penal system’s stated goals, prison is a complete failure. The empirical evidence shows that the objectives of imprisonment are not achieved for the most part: prisons do not rehabilitate, and they do not deter from future crimes (Davis, 2003; Mathiesen, 2006; Cid, 2009; Cullen et al., 2011; Mathiesen, 2015). Furthermore, neuropsychology can provide significant arguments against generalizing prison sentences to be the main sanction in penal systems.

Research has yielded valuable results on the adverse neuropsychological effects of prison (Nurse, 2003; Huey and Mcnulty, 2005; Haney, 2012; Schnittker et al., 2012; Brinkley-Rubinstein, 2013; Meijers et al., 2015; Constantino et al., 2016; Haney, 2017; Meijers et al., 2018; Edgemon and Clay-Warner, 2019; Piper and Berle, 2019; Reiter et al., 2020). Overall, these findings tend to correlate prison with poorer mental health, as impoverished spaces, punitive practices, and the prison environment are profoundly disadvantageous factors for mental health and general well-being. For example, the study by Meijers et al. (2018), suggests that 3 months of imprisonment may lead to reduced self-control, increased risk taking and significant deterioration in attention.

According to research from the World Health Organization, within prisons the prevalence of mental disorders is significantly higher than in the general population (Durcan and Zwemstra, 2014) and it has also been suggested that there are ten times more individuals with a mental disorder in jail than in mental hospitals in the United States (Torrey et al., 2014; Semenza & Grosholz, 2019). Instead of fulfilling a positive function, the prison impoverished environments could end up violating minimum human rights standards (Ligthart et al., 2019), and even become criminogenic factors (Vieraitis et al., 2007; Cid, 2009; Cullen et al., 2011; Meijers et al., 2018; Wallace and Wang, 2020).

These are significant findings that should be understood as an open invitation for researchers around the world to study the neuropsychological effects of prison. It is possible to advise, as a criminal policy, to start the reduction of imprisonment as a form of social control, while prioritizing restorative, conciliatory, civil, and therapeutic alternatives to punishment, to reach abolition in the long term. In the medium term, the humanization of the prison, the improvement of the infrastructure and the prison service is an effective way to promote mental health (Gabrysch et al., 2020).

Neurocriminology and Neurosociology

Since the rise of neurolaw with Taylor et al. (1991), scientific evidence has shown that deviant behaviour has a neurobiological basis, and this has intensified judicial interest in the potential application of neuroscience to criminal law (Glenn and Raine, 2014). In line with this, neurocriminology combines multiple factors (Straiton and Lake, 2021) including genetics, parental influences, early life experiences, hormones, psychophysiology, brain structure, brain function, and neuroimaging to understand why certain individuals are driven to break the law (Glenn and Raine, 2014; Anderson, 2021; Straiton and Lake, 2021). Now that we are confident that neuroscience will have important implications for criminal justice systems (Greely and Farahany, 2019), research on the interaction between neuroscience and criminal law is booming.

Neurocriminology has identified structural and functional deficits in frontal, temporal and subcortical regions, as well as verbal, spatial, and executive dysfunction in antisocial behaviour, and these findings are largely supported by neurological studies of brain trauma in antisocial populations (Schug et al., 2015; Bellesi et al., 2019; van Dongen and Franken, 2019; Katzin et al., 2020). However, some criticize neurocriminology studies for being reductionist. Fallin et al. (2018) argue that most neuroscientists obfuscate legitimate social explanations, transforming complex socially situated behaviors into problems of neurocircuitry.

While this is a legitimate concern, we consider that it is possible to promote a collaboration of disciplines, instead of allowing them to become antagonistic towards each other. Understanding deviant behavior is complex, therefore the careful study of such behavior could benefit greatly from more constructive dialog and collaboration between sociological and neuroscientific disciplines (Aharoni et al., 2019).

Sociology has theoretically and empirically studied social facts such as extreme inequality, poverty, marginalization, and exclusion. In this context, neuroscience can explain how these supra-individual factors affect people’s psychological well-being and leave traces on their neural structures. In addition, lack of nutrition, stress, physical and psychological aggression, stigmatization, and other risk factors might produce adverse neuropsychological effects that can interest criminological studies. With this in mind, it is possible to consider prevention programs that avoid the occurrence of problematic situations related to aggressiveness, impulsivity, lack of empathy, stress and others.

The more effective social programs are implemented, the less criminal law will be seen as a bitter necessity used to threaten individuals in a society. In this transition, institutions such as the prison, or the penal system itself, will be gradually replaced by restorative, community, conciliatory, civil, and therapeutic alternatives. This evolution, under the framework of a true abolitionist proposal, should be far from a dangerousness1 perspective that would invade the mental privacy of offenders with neurotechnologies for predicting the risk of aggression or recidivism, which would be unnecessary, inaccurate and affect human dignity.

Free Will as a Narrative for Social Control

At least in continental European criminal law, with deep Italian and German influences, criminal law has been built unequivocally on free will. The German scholar Claus Roxin maintains that there is an agreement that criminal law must start from free will, although free will cannot exactly be demonstrated (Roxin, 1997). Free will is the foundation of the culpability principle that implies a judgement of reproach to a free and conscientious person who could act according to the law but decided to act against it.

However, in recent decades, neuroscience has provided experiments that suggest that free will does not exist (Libet et al., 1983; Haggard and Eimer, 1999; Soon et al., 2008, 2013; Fried et al., 2011). These studies have not been far from controversy, as several academics also argue against the methodology and conclusions from these findings (Trevena and Miller, 2010; Glannon, 2011; Guggisberg and Mottaz, 2013; Mele, 2014). The truth is that, in general, in philosophy of free will there are two dominant positions: compatibilism and incompatibilism. Compatibilism assumes that even if determinism is true, we would still have free will, while incompatibilism,2 excludes the possibility that free will exists if determinism is assumed to be true. (McKenna and Pereboom, 2016). It is also interesting to note that, within sociology, there is a strong debate around structure versus agency, which could imply that society determines human behavior (Stones, 2015).

In that sense, many scholars have pointed out the great challenges that criminal law must face. Jurists such as Gimbernat (1971) have affirmed that attempting to found criminal law on the unprovable free will is a battle lost beforehand; fighting it can only increase the irritation of empirical scientists. On the other hand, Winfried Hassemer (2011) argued that the consequences of human biology for criminal justice are obvious and that the only advisable approach is to avoid this discussion, or it will be the end of the criminal justice system.

In this brief commentary we will not deal with the question of whether criminal law can exist without free will. Several scholars such as Günther Jakobs (1992) and Morse (2015) have challenged the idea that the free will debate poses a real threat to criminal law. Rather, we want to point out that free will, despite not being a direct object of sociological questioning (Durkheim, 1966), is of interest in a transdisciplinary debate on penal abolitionism. Free will, in addition to being a metaphysically refutable concept, is a functional idea to achieve social control, as it serves as a justification for holding others morally responsible and facilitates punishment (Clark et al., 2014). This is not only applicable to criminal matters, Nietzsche (1968) argued that the idea of free will, despite being false, served as a narrative for Christianity and priests, for punishment, and therefore, for social control and the maintenance of the status quo. From this perspective, under the allegedly false narrative of free will in the penal system, the State ignores the causes of crime by holding the offender responsible and leaving the social structure intact. In that case, prisons would embody a hidden role in the wider field of political domination and general social control, which would be different from prison’s declared objective of disciplining individuals (Foucault, 1977; Garland, 1991).

Conclusion

The new thesis of Penal Neuroabolitionism can be nourished by scientific findings. If neuroscience can show that voluntary decisions are not in fact consciously taken nor available to a responsible agent, and furthermore, if physics demonstrates that classical determinism and quantum indeterminism are true, then criminal law might lose its foundations. Without free will, it will be possible to stop simplifying criminal phenomenon and instead to scientifically understand the neurobiological, social, and cultural risk factors behind deviant behavior. With these inputs, it will be possible to offer more effective social programs and eliminate archaic concepts of moral or criminal responsibility. In addition, since it is possible to identify the adverse neuropsychological consequences of prisons, rigorous programs of humanization in the medium term, and of abolition in the long term, should be considered. In the future, neuroscience could even be useful to intervene in brains that clearly present severe pathologies related to deviant behavior. Penal Neuroabolitionism is a new approach, to invite researchers and academics to join in collective efforts to determine how we want to shape criminal policies of the future.

Author Contributions

The author confirms being the sole contributor of this work and has approved it for publication.

Conflict of Interest

The author declares that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Publisher’s Note

All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors, and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article, or claim that may be made by its manufacturer, is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.

Acknowledgments

Some ideas of this manuscript have appeared previously in Spanish in Borbón (2021). The author would like to thank Laura Amy Daines for her kind comments that helped improve the paper.

Footnotes

1We use the concept of dangerousness in the context of expansive proposals of the punitive power of the State under the narrative that there are dangerous individuals who must be arrested without even having committed a crime. In recent years the concept of Neuroprediction has become popular, which uses neurotechnologies to assess the risk of violence, crime, or recidivism. However, these technologies are still limited in accuracy, and are ethically problematic (Tortora et al., 2020).

2We have argued that Penal Neuroabolitionism as a criminal policy proposal should be based on an adaptation of hard incompatibilism (Borbón, 2021), which implies that our actions are either deterministic or truly random events and both possibilities exclude free will and moral responsibility (Pereboom, 2003). Now, in our vision, we should adopt a theoretical nuance that we have called humanistic incompatibilism, which would imply, in addition to the fact that free will does not exist and that we are not morally and criminally responsible, that human dignity must be a limit to the advancement of science and justice (Borbón, 2021).

References

Aharoni, E., Anderson, N. E., Barnes, J. C., Allen, C. H., and Kiehl, K. A. (2019). Mind the gap: toward an Integrative Science of the Brain and Crime. BioSocieties 14, 463–468. doi:10.1057/s41292-019-00167-3

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Anderson, N. E. (2021). “Neurocriminology,” in The Encyclopedia of Research Methods in Criminology and Criminal Justice, Volume II. (New Jersey USA: Wiley-Blackwell), 633–641. doi:10.1002/9781119111931.ch122

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bellesi, G., Barker, E. D., Brown, L., and Valmaggia, L. (2019). Pediatric Traumatic Brain Injury and Antisocial Behavior: Are They Linked? A Systematic Review. Brain Inj. 33 (10), 1272–1292. doi:10.1080/02699052.2019.1641621

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Borbón, D. (2021). Incompatibilismo humanista: Una contrapropuesta del neuroabolicionismo penal. Cefd 45, 46–72. doi:10.7203/CEFD.45.20713

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Brinkley-Rubinstein, L. (2013). Incarceration as a Catalyst for Worsening Health. Health Justice 1 (1). doi:10.1186/2194-7899-1-3

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Christie, N. (1981). Limits to Pain. Oxford: Martin Robertson & Company Ltd.

Google Scholar

Cid, J. (2009). Is Imprisonment Criminogenic. Eur. J. Criminology 6 (6), 459–480. doi:10.1177/1477370809341128

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Clark, C. J., Luguri, J. B., Ditto, P. H., Knobe, J., Shariff, A. F., and Baumeister, R. F. (2014). Free to Punish: A Motivated Account of Free Will Belief. J. Pers Soc. Psychol. 106 (4), 501–513. doi:10.1037/a0035880

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Constantino, P., Assis, S. G., and Pinto, L. W. (2016). The impact of prisons on the mental health of prisoners in the state of Rio de Janeiro, Brazil. Cien Saude Colet 21 (7), 2089–2100. doi:10.1590/1413-81232015217.01222016

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Cullen, F. T., Jonson, C. L., and Nagin, D. S. (2011). Prisons Do Not Reduce Recidivism. Prison J. 91 (3 Suppl. l), 48S–65S. doi:10.1177/0032885511415224

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Davis, A. (2003). Are Prisons Obsolete. New York: Seven Stories Press.

Google Scholar

Durcan, G., and Zwemstra, J. (2014). “Mental Health in Prison,” in Prisons and Health. Editors S. Enggist, L. Møller., G. Galea., and C. Udesen (Copenhagen: World Health Organization).

Google Scholar

Durkheim, E. (1966). The Rules of Sociological Method. New York: Free Press.

Google Scholar

Edgemon, T. G., and Clay-Warner, J. (2019). Inmate Mental Health and the Pains of Imprisonment. Soc. Ment. Health 9 (1), 33–50. doi:10.1177/2156869318785424

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Fair, H., and Walmsley, R. (2021). World Prison Population List. Thirteenth Edition. London: Institute for Crime & Justice Policy Research at Birkbeck University of London. https://www.prisonstudies.org/sites/default/files/resources/downloads/world_prison_population_list_13th_edition.pdf.

Google Scholar

Fallin, M., Whooley, O., and Barker, K. K. (2018). Criminalizing the Brain: Neurocriminology and the Production of Strategic Ignorance. BioSocieties 14, 438–462. doi:10.1057/s41292-018-0135-y

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Folter, R. S. (1986). On the Methodological Foundation of the Abolitionist Approach to the Criminal justice System. A Comparison of the Ideas of Hulsman, Mathiesen and Foucault. Contemp. Crises 10 (1), 39–62. doi:10.1007/BF00728495

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Foucault, M. (1977). Discipline and Punish. London: Allen Lane.

Google Scholar

Franks, D., and Turner, J. (2013). “Chapter 1: Introduction: Summaries and Comments,” in Handbook of Neurosociology. Editors D. Franks, and J. Turner (New York: Springer).

Google Scholar

Fried, I., Mukamel, R., and Kreiman, G. (2011). Internally Generated Preactivation of Single Neurons in Human Medial Frontal Cortex Predicts Volition. Neuron 69, 548–562. doi:10.1016/j.neuron.2010.11.045

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gabrysch, C., Sepúlveda, C., Bienzobas, C., and Mundt, A. P. (2020). 'Maybe it Is Only in Prison that I Could Change like This' the Course of Severe Mental Illnesses during Imprisonment - A Qualitative 3-Year Follow-Up Study from Chile. Front. Psychol. 11, 1208. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2020.01208

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Garland, D. (1991). Sociological Perspectives on Punishment. Crime and Justice 14, 115–165. doi:10.1086/449185

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gimbernat, E. (1971). “Tiene un futuro la dogmática jurídicopenal,” in Problemas actuales de Derecho penal y procesal (Salamanca: Universidad de Salamanca).

Google Scholar

Glannon, W. (2011). Brain, Body, and Mind: Neuroethics with a Human Face. Oxford: Oxford Scholarship Online.

Google Scholar

Glenn, A. L., and Raine, A. (2014). Neurocriminology: Implications for the Punishment, Prediction and Prevention of Criminal Behaviour. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 15 (1), 54–63. doi:10.1038/nrn3640

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Greely, H. T., and Farahany, N. A. (2019). Neuroscience and the Criminal Justice System. Annu. Rev. Criminol. 2 (1), 451–471. doi:10.1146/annurev-criminol-011518-024433

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Guggisberg, A. G., and Mottaz, A. (2013). Timing and Awareness of Movement Decisions: Does Consciousness Really Come Too Late. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 7, 385. doi:10.3389/fnhum.2013.00385

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Haggard, P., and Eimer, M. (1999). On the Relation between Brain Potentials and the Awareness of Voluntary Movements. Exp. Brain Res. 126, 128–133. doi:10.1007/s002210050722

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Haney, C. (2012). “The Psychological Effects of Imprisonment,” in The Oxford Handbook of Sentencing and Corrections (Oxford: Oxford University Press). doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199730148.013.0024

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Haney, C. (2017). “Madness” and Penal Confinement: Some Observations on Mental Illness and Prison Pain. Punishment Soc. 19 (3), 310–326. doi:10.1177/1462474517705389

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hassemer, W. (2011). Neurociencias y culpabilidad en Derecho penal. Barcelona, Spain: InDret V2. Available at: https://indret.com/neurociencias-y-culpabilidad-en-derecho-penal/.

Google Scholar

Huey, M. P., and Mcnulty, T. L. (2005). Institutional Conditions and Prison Suicide: Conditional Effects of Deprivation and Overcrowding. Prison J. 85 (4), 490–514. doi:10.1177/0032885505282258

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hulsman, L. (1991). The Abolitionist Case: Alternative Crime Policies. Isr. Law Rev. 25 (3-4), 681–709. doi:10.1017/S0021223700010694

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Jakobs, G. (1992). El Principio de Culpabilidad. Anuario de derecho penal y ciencias penales 45 (3), 1051–1084.

Google Scholar

Katzin, S., Andiné, P., Hofvander, B., Billstedt, E., and Wallinius, M. (2020). Exploring Traumatic Brain Injuries and Aggressive Antisocial Behaviors in Young Male Violent Offenders. Front. Psychiatry 11, 507196. doi:10.3389/fpsyt.2020.507196

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Libet, B., Gleason, C. A., Wright, E. W., and Pearl, D. K. (1983). Time of Conscious Intention to Act in Relation to Onset of Cerebral Activity (Readiness-potential). The Unconscious Initiation of a Freely Voluntary Act. Brain 106 (Pt 3), 623–642. doi:10.1093/brain/106.3.623

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ligthart, S., van Oploo, L., Meijers, J., Meynen, G., and Kooijmans, T. (2019). Prison and the Brain: Neuropsychological Research in the Light of the European Convention on Human Rights. New J. Eur. Criminal L. 10 (3), 287–300. doi:10.1177/2032284419861816

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Mathiesen, T. (2006). Prison on Trial. Winchester: Waterside Press.

Google Scholar

Mathiesen, T. (2015). The Politics of Abolition Revisited. New York: Routledge.

Google Scholar

McKenna, M., and Pereboom, P. (2016). Free Will a Contemporary Introduction. New York: Routledge.

Google Scholar

Meijers, J., Harte, J. M., Jonker, F. A., and Meynen, G. (2015). Prison Brain? Executive Dysfunction in Prisoners. Front. Psychol. 6, 43. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2015.00043

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Meijers, J., Harte, J. M., Meynen, G., Cuijpers, P., and Scherder, E. J. A. (2018). Reduced Self-Control after 3 Months of Imprisonment; A Pilot Study. Front. Psychol. 9, 69. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2018.00069

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Mele, A. (2014). Free: Why Science Hasn't Disproved Free Will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Morse, S. (2015). Neuroscience, Free Will, and Criminal Responsibility. Pennsylvania: Faculty Scholarship at Penn Law. 1604. https://scholarship.law.upenn.edu/faculty_scholarship/1604.

Google Scholar

Nietzsche, F. (1968). The Twilight of the Idols and the Anti-christ: Or How to Philosophize with a Hammer. Harmondsworth: Penguin.

Google Scholar

Nurse, J., Woodcock, P., and Ormsby, J. (2003). Influence of Environmental Factors on Mental Health within Prisons: Focus Group Study. BMJ 327 (7413), 480. doi:10.1136/bmj.327.7413.480

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pereboom, D. (2019). “Free Will Skepticism and Prevention of Crime,” in Free Will Skepticism in Law and Society: Challenging Retributive Justice. Editors E. Shaw, D. Pereboom, and G. Caruso (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 99–115. doi:10.1017/9781108655583.005

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pereboom, D. (2003). Living without Free Will. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Google Scholar

Piper, A., and Berle, D. (2019). The Association between Trauma Experienced during Incarceration and PTSD Outcomes: a Systematic Review and Meta-Analysis. J. Forensic Psychiatry Psychol. 30, 854–875. doi:10.1080/14789949.2019.1639788

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Reiter, K., Ventura, J., Lovell, D., Augustine, D., Barragan, M., Blair, T., et al. (2020). Psychological Distress in Solitary Confinement: Symptoms, Severity, and Prevalence in the United States, 2017-2018. Am. J. Public Health 110 (S1), S56–S62. doi:10.2105/ajph.2019.305375

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Roxin, C. (1997). Derecho Penal parte general, Tomo I: Fundamentos, la estructura de la teoría del delito. Madrid: Civitas.

Google Scholar

Schnittker, J., Massoglia, M., and Uggen, C. (2012). Out and Down: Incarceration and Psychiatric Disorders. J. Health Soc. Behav. 53 (4), 448–464. doi:10.1177/0022146512453928

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Schug, R. A., Raine, A., Gao, Y., Glenn, A., and Yang, Y. (2015). “Neurocriminology,” in The Evolution of Forensic Psychiatry: History, Current Developments, Future Directions (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 313–328. doi:10.1093/med/9780199393435.003.0029

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Semenza, D. C., and Grosholz, J. M. (2019). Mental and Physical Health in Prison: How Co-occurring Conditions Influence Inmate Misconduct. Health Justice 7 (1), 1. doi:10.1186/s40352-018-0082-5

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Soon, C. S., Brass, M., Heinze, H. J., and Haynes, J. D. (2008). Unconscious Determinants of Free Decisions in the Human Brain. Nat. Neurosci. 11, 543–545. doi:10.1038/nn.2112

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Soon, C. S., He, A. H., Bode, S., and Haynes, J. D. (2013). Predicting Free Choices for Abstract Intentions. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U S A. 110, 6217–6222. doi:10.1073/pnas.1212218110

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Stones, R. (2015). Structure and Agency. The Blackwell Encyclopedia of Sociology. doi:10.1002/9781405165518.wbeoss293.pub2

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Straiton, J., and Lake, F. (2021). Inside the Brain of a Killer: the Ethics of Neuroimaging in a Criminal Conviction. Biotechniques 70, 69–71. doi:10.2144/btn-2020-0171

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Taylor, J. S., Harp, J. A., and Elliott, T. (1991). Neuropsychologists and Neurolawyers. Neuropsychology 5 (4), 293–305. doi:10.1037/0894-4105.5.4.293

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Torrey, E. (2014). The Treatment of Persons with Mental Illness in Prisons and Jails: A State Survey. Arlington, VA: Treatment Advocacy Center.

Google Scholar

Tortora, L., Meynen, G., Bijlsma, J., Tronci, E., and Ferracuti, S. (2020). Neuroprediction and A.I. In Forensic Psychiatry and Criminal Justice: A Neurolaw Perspective. Front. Psychol. 11, 220. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2020.00220

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Trevena, J., and Miller, J. (2010). Brain Preparation before a Voluntary Action: Evidence against Unconscious Movement Initiation. Conscious. Cogn. 19 (1), 447–456. doi:10.1016/j.concog.2009.08.006

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

van Dongen, J. D. M., and Franken, I. H. A. (2019). Neuroscience in Forensic Psychiatry and Psychology: An Introduction to the Special Issue. Int. J. Forensic Ment. Health 18 (3), 179–186. doi:10.1080/14999013.2019.1652708

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Vegh, V. (2017). Marxism and Criminology: A History of Criminal Selectivity. Leiden: Brill.

Google Scholar

Vieraitis, L. M., Kovandzic, T. V., and Marvell, T. B. (2007). The Criminogenic Effects of Imprisonment: Evidence from State Panel Data, 1974?2002. Criminology Public Policy 6 (3), 589–622. doi:10.1111/j.1745-9133.2007.00456.x

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Wallace, D., and Wang, X. (2020). Does In-Prison Physical and Mental Health Impact Recidivism. SSM Popul. Health 11, 100569. doi:10.1016/j.ssmph.2020.100569

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Keywords: neurolaw, free will, neuropsychology, penal abolitionism, prison abolition, social control, neurocriminology, punishment

Citation: Borbón D (2022) Neurosociology and Penal Neuroabolitionism: Rethinking Justice With Neuroscience. Front. Sociol. 7:814338. doi: 10.3389/fsoc.2022.814338

Received: 15 November 2021; Accepted: 10 January 2022;
Published: 25 January 2022.

Edited by:

Vincenzo Auriemma, University of Salerno, Italy

Reviewed by:

Valeria Saladino, University of Cassino, Italy
Chiara Iannaccone, University of Salerno, Italy

Copyright © 2022 Borbón. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Diego Borbón, diego.borbon01@est.uexternado.edu.co

Download