Skip to main content

ORIGINAL RESEARCH article

Front. Public Health, 22 July 2022
Sec. Public Health Education and Promotion
This article is part of the Research Topic COVID-19: Risk Communication and Blame View all 23 articles

How is “solidarity” understood in discussions about contact tracing apps? An overview

  • Department of Systematic Theology, Friedrich-Alexander-Universität Erlangen-Nürnberg, Erlangen, Germany

Background: In the context of the COVID-19 pandemic, there is much discussion about contact tracing apps, their use to contain the spread of the virus as well as the ethical, legal, and social aspects of their development, implementation, acceptance, and use. In these discussions, authors frequently mention “solidarity” when making key points in arguments. At the same time, authors rarely specify how they understand “solidarity”. This lack of specification about how they understand “solidarity” can lead to misunderstandings in discussions.

Objective: To prevent such misunderstandings, it is important to specify how one understands “solidarity” when mentioning it in the discussions on contact tracing apps. Therefore, the aim of this paper is to elaborate how “solidarity” is understood in the context of contact tracing apps, i.e., how different authors understand “solidarity” when using it in discussions about these apps.

Methods: In order to find out how different authors understand “solidarity” when discussing contact tracing apps, I conduct a literature review. I collect papers from several databases, inductively work out central differences and similarities between the different uses of “solidarity”, and use them to code and analyze relevant passages.

Results: In the final sample, five different understandings of “solidarity” in the context of contact tracing apps can be identified. These understandings differ in how different authors (1) imagine the basic concept of solidarity, i.e., what “solidarity” refers to, (2) how they temporally relate solidarity to contact tracing apps, and (3) how they perceive the causal interactions between solidarity and contact tracing apps, i.e., the different ways in which solidarity and contact tracing apps influence each other.

Conclusions: The five understandings of “solidarity” in the context of contact tracing apps presented here can serve as guidance for how “solidarity” can be understood in discussions—thus contributing to a better mutual understanding and preventing communicative misunderstandings.

Introduction

During the COVID-19 pandemic digital contact tracing was introduced as a vital part of public health surveillance strategies. Countries (13) as well as private sector companies (4) develop and deploy their own apps for contact tracing. Such contact tracing apps (CTA) are typically used to collect and combine two sets of data: first, the user's contacts; second, their COVID-19 infection status. Contact information is often captured by collecting user location data either automatically via WiFi, cellular or GPS location data or manually via QR codes and transmitting it to central servers. There, they are subsequently analyzed by health authorities who identify contacts (3, 5). Alternatively, contact data can be collected through Bluetooth data exchange between smart devices. Typically, contacts are identified when two smart devices with compatible CTA are within a certain distance to each other for a certain period of time (5). If users are tested positive for COVID-19 or manually report an infection, their detected contacts often receive an anonymized exposure message saying that they have recently had contact with a person infected with COVID-19. Based on this data, some CTA may also display their users their risk of infection—for example, the German Corona-Warn-App shows whether the user is at none, low, or high risk of infection (6)—as well as provide guidance for managing potential exposure and infection (e.g., get themselves tested for COVID-19 or enter voluntary self-quarantine). The goal is to use CTA to detect at-risk contacts more quickly than through manual contact tracing and to be able to take action sooner (7), thus breaking chains of infection more effectively and containing the COVID-19 pandemic in the long term.

The effectiveness of CTA in combating COVID-19 depends centrally on how many people use CTA and are informed about risk contacts (8). Particularly because initial data suggest that “contact-tracing apps help reduce COVID infections” (9, 10) and are effective complementary tools for containing the spread of the virus (1114) it is important to further increase their number of users to make them even more effective. This requires knowing the factors that drive their public acceptance or rejection in order to be able to adapt them (15, 16). While concern for one's own health and the prospect of more activity opportunities increase their acceptance, it is mainly privacy concerns and fear if government control that prevent their acceptance (15, 17). The latter can be countered by building and maintaining strong public trust (18)—just as these concerns can be solidified or increased by a lack of trust (19, 20). To preserve the former, it is important not to create overly optimistic expectations, which in the long term could lead to disappointment with CTA and subsequent loss of acceptance (5).

Digital contact tracing and CTA have already been used in other epidemiological events prior to the COVID-19 pandemic, e.g., the outbreak of Ebola in Sierra Leone in 2014–2016 (21, 22). During the COVID-19 pandemic, CTA are used for the first time worldwide. This stimulates many discussions about CTA, with one central issue being privacy (23, 24). From a legal and moral perspective, there is discussion about how much the state, public health authorities, or private institutions may monitor the movements (in the case of a GPS-based CTA) and contacts of individuals (25); how much this surveillance and invasion of privacy limits the freedom and autonomy of individuals (26); and how digital contact tracing relates to existing moral principles (27, 28) and legal data protection laws (29), particularly the GDPR (30). From a technical perspective, there is discussion about how to protect privacy best by asking what form of anonymization and encryption of data would be most effective (31) and whether to store data centrally or decentrally (32). Other questions are how high how high the acceptance rate needs to be (7) to guarantee the effectiveness of CTA (33); how the uptake of CTA could be increased (34, 35); whether the use of CTA should be legally mandated; and whether there is a moral obligation to use them (36). In addition, there is moral discussion about the principles and guidelines that should be implemented in CTA (27, 28) as well as sociological discussion concerning the public acceptance of CTA (37), and the expected social consequences of introducing CTA (38). These discussions about CTA are persistently relevant, because COVID-19 continues to spread and needs to be contained, but also because there may be future pandemics. In fact, the risk of pandemic outbreaks is currently higher than ever before, making future pandemics “inevitable” (39). It is therefore all the more important to be prepared for them and to be able to counter them effectively as soon as they break out (40). This preparation includes developing the necessary (contact tracing) technologies now and without pandemic constraints and time pressure (41), discussing and finding solutions to the relevant social, moral and legal issues now as well as establishing public trust in governments, institutions, and technologies now (42, 43)—to have these resources present and not to have to build them in the last minute when they are urgently needed.

While scoping the literature on CTA, I made two observations. First, the discussions often refer to “solidarity” in central points of the discussion. Especially when some of the moral or legal issues mentioned above are addressed. Solidarity, thus, seems to play an important role in legal, moral, societal, and public health discussions about CTA and captures a “spotlight” (44) in discussions about the COVID-19 pandemic. Second, authors rarely define how they understand the notion in their discussions, instead assuming that everybody intuitively understands what they mean when using “solidarity”. However, this assumption is deceptive and problematic. On the one hand, it is deceptive because no notion has a permanently fixed meaning and is understood the same way every time it is used. Instead, a notion acquires its meaning only when it is used and can only be understood by considering the context (45). As Bayertz (46) points out in his studies on solidarity, the same notion can even have contradictory meanings: “The concept of solidarity thus shares the same fate as other central concepts within ethical and political terminology, namely that of not being defined in a binding manner, and consequently of being used in very different and sometimes very contradictory ways” (46). On the other hand, it is problematic to assume that solidarity has a fixed meaning and not to specify how one understands the term when using it as this can lead to serious misunderstandings in discussions. Where two (or more) people use the same notion but understand it differently, one polysemous notion (47) can be understood in multiple ways and can become lexically ambivalent (48). This lexical ambivalence might in turn result in these people talking past, misunderstanding, and disagreeing with each other (49)—while in the worst case not even realizing it.

Especially when discussing important concerns as the fight against the COVID-19 pandemic and when using the notion “solidarity” at crucial points in arguments, it is important to avoid these communicative pitfalls. This means specifying exactly how one understands “solidarity” whenever one uses it and making clear for what purpose one is using it in the particular context. To help specifying the notion “solidarity”, I ask the research question: what does solidarity mean in the context of the CTA? Or, to be more precise: how do different authors understand “solidarity” when using it in the context of CTA?

Methodologically, I approach this research question by means of a literature review. After compiling a comprehensive sample, I analyze the passages that mention solidarity. By doing so, I identify central differences and similarities in their uses of “solidarity” and use these to elaborate different understandings of solidarity in the context of CTA. I then assign the papers to these understandings and thus work out which author understands solidarity in which way. Afterwards I discuss the Results, ask how these understandings of solidarity relate to each other, what limitations the study has, and finally give some practical recommendations.

Methods

In conducting my review, I am guided by methodological frameworks for conducting a systematic review (5052). In large parts, I follow the methodological approach for conducting a systematic review by Tranfield et al. (51). I search databases using a search strategy, then select the literature according to both external and internal inclusion criteria. Next, I inductively extract criteria from the literature, which I then use to examine how solidarity is understood in the sample. Details on how I proceed in searching, selecting and collecting data will now be presented.

To identify literature for my review I formulate a search strategy that is based on the keyword of the review question: what does solidarity mean in the context of CTA? The final search strategy consists of combinations of the keywords “contact tracing” or “tracing apps” in combination with the keyword “solidarity” (see Table 1) that are used to search the databases: GIFT, Scopus, PubMed, Web of Science, and Google Scholar. I search the databases at regular intervals and add the papers that were new since the last search to the sample. The first search was on January 07, 2021, and the last search was on December 21, 2021. During 2021, the GIFT database was discontinued by WHO for public use, so this database could not be included in the most recent searches. The results of previous searches in this database are retained in the final sample and not subsequently removed. The final sample includes publications from January 1, 2020 [when the first academic papers on COVID-19 were published (53)] to December 21, 2021 (when the final search was completed).

TABLE 1
www.frontiersin.org

Table 1. Overview of the search, listing the names of the databases, the search strategies used, and the number of results.

The search strategy results in a corpus of 533 publications. Due to my language skills, I limit the review to articles written in English or German. Also, the review is limited to articles that are academic, already published, and reviewed to assure their quality (52). Based on these limitations pre-prints, gray literature, self-publications, student theses, and blog entries as well as publications in other languages are excluded (226)—leaving 307 journal articles, books, edited volumes, and articles in edited volumes that meet the formal requirements. After removing the duplicates (52) and the articles that I have no access to (11), I screen the remaining 244 full-text publications to examine whether they meet the content requirements to include them in my review or not (Appendix 1 in Supplementary Material 1). A paper is included in my final review if it mentions solidarity in connection with CTA. A paper is excluded if it does not make a connection between solidarity and CTA. The latter could be due to these papers using the notion “solidarity” as a proper name [e.g., WHO's Solidarity Trial in (54) or France's Ministry of Solidarity and Health in (55)] (22), mentioning tracing apps (56) or the notion “solidarity” (57) only in the references (58), or discussing both topics in different contexts without making a connection between them [e.g., when Brown et al. (59) discuss the challenges of immunity passports, they discuss the possibilities of a combining immunity certificates and CTA once and another time discuss the impact of immunity certificates on social solidarity—but both considerations are independent of each other] (60). After sorting out 197 papers, 47 papers are included in my final review (Appendix 1 in Supplementary Material 1). For a visual representation of procedure for selecting literature, see Figure 1.

FIGURE 1
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 1. Procedure for selecting literature for my final review (created by the author).

The final 47 papers come from different disciplines (e.g., ethics, sociology, psychology, law, and tourism studies) and address different issues concerning CTA. I analyze them with a focus on the passages mentioning solidarity. The goal is to find out how different authors understand the “solidarity” when they use it in the context of CTA. Starting from a structuralist understanding of language (61), one must analyze the central differences (and similarities) between the various uses of the notion in the various papers and passages in order to work out how an author understands the notion “solidarity”. In short: to find out how an author understands “solidarity” in the context of CTA, one must show how her or his understanding differs from or relates to other authors' understanding of the notion.

In order to work out these differences and similarities between the various understandings of solidarity, comparative criteria are needed. As comparative criteria I use binary distinctions, which I call “key distinctions”. Each use of the term solidarity can be assigned to one side of the key distinctions. If two uses of the term solidarity are similar, they can be assigned to the same side of the key distinction; if they are different, they are assigned to different sides of the key distinction. Thus, differences and similarities between the different uses of the notion “solidarity” can be worked out. A binary distinction is a key distinction only if each use of the notion “solidarity” can be assigned to exactly one of its sides. There are several of these key distinctions. The more different key distinctions there are and the more often one use of the notion “solidarity” can be assigned to one of their sides, the more precisely one can work out its understanding of solidarity, i.e., the more precisely one can identify its differences and similarities to other uses of the notion “solidarity”.

The more key distinctions and the better they are, i.e., the more they help to make central differences visible, the more useful they are for elaborating the understanding of the uses of “solidarity”. Therefore, the central question is how to get specific key distinctions. There are two ways to get key distinctions: either one takes them from existing conceptual discussions of solidarity and uses them deductively to distinguish the understandings in the passages analyzed; or one or one extracts the key distinctions inductively from the passages that are being analyzed. In order not to pre-determine, limit, or bias the results by making prior assumptions about the notion's key distinctions (58) and to ensure that the key distinctions are tailored to the sample—i.e., they contribute as best as possible to making central differences visible—I choose the inductive approach. During several iterations I extract distinctions from the analyzed passages and test their validity on the other passages. I keep a distinction as key distinction if all analyzed passages could be assigned to one of its sides and discard or modify it if this does not work—thus arriving at the final key distinctions.

With these key distinctions, I code the passages mentioning solidarity and assign their use of “solidarity” to the corresponding sides of the different key distinctions. This assignment is based on criteria called “operators”. These operators act as rules for which side of the key difference a use of the notion “solidarity” should be assigned to. I extract these operators, like the key distinctions, inductively from the passages themselves in an iterative process. By coding the passages, I arrive at an understanding of how different authors understand solidarity in the context of CTA.

Based on the key distinctions, different understandings of the concept of solidarity in the context of CTA can be distinguished. The operators help to assign the different passages in which solidarity is mentioned to the different understandings and thus to answer the question: how do different authors understand “solidarity” when they use it in the context of CTA?

Results

The sample first shows that different authors use “solidarity” with different degrees of precision: some authors mention the term only once as an “ethical buzzword” (62) without further specifying how they understand it, some authors define the term precisely and use it throughout. Second, it can be shown that different authors understand the notion “solidarity” differently in the context of CTA. In the sample, two key distinctions play a central role and help to distinguish the different understandings of “solidarity” in the context of CTA.

• The first key distinction I call “basic concepts of solidarity”: there are two different basic concepts of solidarity in the sample, which differ in how they understand solidarity and what they refer to.

• The second key distinction I call “temporal relations between solidarity and contact tracing apps”: there are two different ways in which solidarity temporally relates to CTA in the sample.

• In addition to the two key distinctions, two different “causal interactions between solidarity and CTA” can be distinguished, i.e., different ways in which solidarity and CTA interact with and influence each other in the sample.

In the results, I present these key distinctions—first, the different basic concepts; second, the different relations of solidarity and CTA—as well as the third distinction of different causal interactions. In doing so, I subordinate the distinctions to each other, i.e., the second key distinction is a sub-key distinction of the first key distinction and the different causal interactions are a sub distinction to the second key distinction.

Basic concepts of solidarity

In the sample, one can first distinguish between two basic concepts of solidarity: Solidarity can either be understood as a factual form of social cohesion. As a factual form of social cohesion, solidarity describes the modes of how different individuals or groups of people live together (63) as well as the different bonds and organizational forms with which they structure their living together (46). Thus, as a form of social cohesion, solidarity always refers to existing collectives—and explores the interactions between CTA and the modes and organizational forms of their coexistence. Or solidarity can be understood as a moral value: something that people care about, that they consider good, and that grounds their judgment (64). As a moral value, solidarity comes into play in moral reasoning (65)—and can represent a principle used in considerations and discussions about CTA, a good used to guide them, or a criterion used to evaluate future or past considerations and discussions. Thus, as a moral value, solidarity always refers to considerations and discussions about CTA, and examines how this moral value affects them. Both basic concepts of solidarity are not mutually exclusive. Instead, the distinction helps to hermeneutically highlight different aspects of the notion “solidarity” that are in focus when it is used in a specific context—which I will elaborate further in Section Discussion.

If solidarity is understood as a factual form of social cohesion of a society, it can either refer to a specific, individual nation such as Singapore (66), Ireland (67), France (68), Germany (69, 70), South Korea (68), the UK (71, 72), and China (70) or even the European Union (73), or to an unspecified, individual nation (7479). It can furthermore be an indeterminate collective of unknown size (36, 8087), a particular marginalized group of persons within an indeterminate collective (38, 8891), or an indeterminate human-technology-society called “post-digital hybrid assemblage” (92).

If solidarity is understood as a moral value, this moral value can be used in different discussions concerning CTA. It can be used when discussing or evaluating the development of CTA (28, 75, 80, 9395), their implementation, i.e., their introduction into a society (95100), or the organizational (101) or ethical (99, 102106) framework of CTA. It can be used when individuals question themselves about whether to use CTA (107) or when individuals reflect on whether and how others use CTA (108). Solidarity can also be used when several of these points are discussed at once, e.g., the development and implementation (109) or the development, implementation, and use of CTA (110).

Looking at the absolute numbers, solidarity is more often understood as a factual form of social cohesion (29 papers) than as a moral value (22 papers). At the same time some papers understand solidarity as social cohesion and as moral value. For example, Lanzing understands solidarity both as the social cohesion that exists in an indeterminate country and as a moral value that guides decisions about the development of CTA (75). Leslie understands solidarity both as the social cohesion that exists in an indeterminate society and as a moral value that is used to guide the development of CTA (80).

Temporal relations between solidarity and contact tracing apps

In the sample, one can then distinguish between two different ways in which solidarity temporally relates to CTA. It proves to be useful to maintain the above distinction of basic concepts when considering solidarity's relation to CTA. If solidarity is understood as a factual form of social cohesion, it can either precede or follow the acceptance and use of CTA in time. This distinction depends on whether the text examines the consequences of different factual forms of social cohesion for the development, introduction, acceptance, or use of CTA or, conversely, the consequences of the introduction, acceptance, or use of CTA for existing forms of social cohesion. As moral value, solidarity can be used to consider decisions about CTA from an ex-ante or ex-post perspective. This distinction depends on whether the decisions about CTA that the moral value refers to have already been made and are now being evaluated, or whether they are still pending and being discussed.

If solidarity is a form of social cohesion that precedes CTA in time, this form of social cohesion can be a condition for their public acceptance (6771, 74, 7678, 82, 85), a motivation for their individual use (36, 84, 85), or a necessary condition for their coordinated development (73).

If solidarity as a form of social cohesion follows CTA in time, this may have two different results. On the one hand, the public acceptance and individual use of CTA may strengthen the factual forms of social cohesion that exist in a collective (67) or strengthen factors that are elementary for them (72, 82), it may prevent negative consequences for forms of social cohesion that would have happened if CTA were not accepted and used (66), or open up possibilities for reimagining old and establishing new relationships (92). On the other hand, the acceptance and use of CTA may also have a negative impact on a society's forms of social cohesion: by threatening or undermining the forms of social cohesion that exist in a collective (83), by weakening factors that are elementary for them (75, 77, 8082, 86), by reinforcing existing discriminations and worsening the situation for specific groups of people (38, 75, 90, 91), or by using resources for the development and implementation of CTA that would have had more positive effects on the community if used in an alternative way (88, 89).

As a moral value, solidarity can consider decisions about CTA—concerning their development, implementation into a society, or individual use—from an ex-ante perspective. Solidarity can guide or reflect the development of CTA morally (101, 106) and can prevent CTA from having negative impacts on their users (e.g., due to improper development) (75, 80, 93). Solidarity as a moral value can guide the introduction of CTA into a society morally (95, 98, 99, 104, 109), it can also motivate individuals to use CTA (72, 94, 107), and contribute to their public acceptance (110).

Similarly, solidarity as moral value can reflect on decisions about CTA that have already been made from an ex-post perspective, for example, by questioning past ethical discussions about CTA as to whether they have (sufficiently) taken into account the moral value of solidarity (28, 96, 102, 103, 105) or by evaluating how other people use CTA (108).

Looking at the absolute numbers, there are 16 papers in which solidarity as a factual form of social cohesion precedes CTA in time. There are 16 papers in which solidarity as a factual form of social cohesion follows CTA in time. There are 15 papers in which solidarity is used as a moral value to consider decisions about CTA from an ex-ante perspective. And there are eight papers in which solidarity is used as a moral value to reflect on decisions about CTA from an ex-post perspective. There are seven papers that relate solidarity and CTA in multiple ways at the same time. E.g., Gibney et al. (67) observe that the use of CTA at the same time “would benefit from and foster solidarity among the public in the national “figh” against the novel coronavirus” (9). Here, solidarity is understood as a form of social cohesion that precedes the use of CTA and results from their use.

Causal interactions between solidarity and contact tracing apps

By means of these two key distinctions—the two basic concepts of solidarity and the temporal relations between solidarity and CTA—several understandings of solidarity in the context of CTA can be identified in the sample. Three understandings can be attributed one causal interaction between solidarity and CTA, i.e., one particular way in which solidarity influences the development, use, or acceptance of CTA or decisions regarding them. Two different ways of causal interaction between solidarity and CTA can be attributed to the understanding of solidarity as a form of social cohesion that follows CTA in time.

• If solidarity is understood as a form of social cohesion that precedes CTA in time, it can be a crucial condition for the implementation (67, 76) of CTA or encourage their public acceptance (67, 6971, 76, 78, 79, 84, 85). See, for example, Milne and Costa (68) who describe solidarity as condition for the implementation and acceptance of CTA: “For example, CTA, such as those now implemented in France, Germany or South Korea, rely on adoption through a sense of solidarity”. In addition, solidarity itself or appeals to a “we are all in this together” sense of social cohesion can motivate single individuals to use CTA, argue Parker et al. (36).

• If solidarity is understood as a form of social cohesion that follows CTA in time, the implementation and use of the latter can reinforce the former. As Gibney et al. argue, the use of CTA could give individuals a common sense of working together to fight the battle against COVID-19 (67), or, as Samuel and Sims put forward, it could provide them with shared visions or impose equal social obligations (72). Both, according to the authors, could constitute, maintain, and strengthen forms of social cohesion itself or factors that are elementary for it. Conversely, the use of CTA can also prevent negative consequences for social cohesion that might have occurred if hey were not implemented and used (66). Furthermore, CTA can open up possibilities of reimagining old and establishing new relationships and create new forms of social cohesions, e.g., by creating new, digital bonds between actors who previously had no contact with each other (92).

• If solidarity is understood as a form of social cohesion that follows CTA in time, the implementation and use of the latter can weaken or undermine the former (86, 90). E.g., as Pila (83) suggest, by providing “too much information about individuals' health risks” CTA “can undermine solidarity by depriving people of the very uncertainty about their own and others' fates on which a commitment to sharing those fates depends.” This can result in existing vulnerabilities (75) or marginalizations being reinforced (38, 91). E.g., as Chang et al. point out, by warning CTA users not to have contact with homepless persons and drug users for health reasons—thereby adding another stigma to these groups of people (38). Alternatively, the resources used for the development and implementation of CTA could have had more positive effects on the community if used in an alternative way (88, 89).

• If solidarity is understood as a moral value that considers decisions on CTA from an ex-ante perspective, it can guide and orient decisions or actions concerning the development (75, 80, 102, 106, 109), implementation (75, 95, 98, 99, 104, 110), and use (94, 102) of CTA ethically. For example, Leslie advocates taking into account the UK Government's SUM values for safe and ethical AI, which include solidarity, when developing CTA (80), and Gasser et al. elaborate a diagram of six different values, one of which is solidarity, from which they then derive 17 moral challenges to be considered in the development of CTA (109). Also, educating individuals about the moral value of solidarity, as Roche notes, can help them become more aware of their role in fighting the virus (107).

• If solidarity is understood as a moral value that considers decisions on CTA from an ex-post perspective, it can serve as an ethical criterion for the evaluation of past discussions or decisions concerning the development (96, 102, 103) as well as the implementation (96, 97, 100, 102, 103, 105) of CTA. For example, Keating reflects on whether collaboration during the development and implementation of CTA would have worked better if solidarity had played a more central role (97), and Siffels wonders whether it would have been better to focus questions about CTA development and implementation not only on privacy and health, but also to consider other values, including solidarity (103). Furthermore, solidarity can be used as a criterion to evaluate other people's behavior toward CTA (108), when people consider other people's decision to use CTA as solidary or their decision not to use it as unsolidary (108).

The causal interactions assigned are not key distinctions, as they do not apply a binary distinction to all uses of the notion “solidarity” in the sample. Rather, these causal interactions specify the understandings of solidarity identified in the sample. This specification leads to adding a binary distinction to the second understanding, so that we can ultimately speak of five understandings of solidarity in the context of CTA.

Illustration of the five understandings of solidarity as a tree diagram

Given these two key differences and the different causal interactions between solidarity and CTA, there are five different understandings of solidarity in the context of CTA. These five understandings, as well as the distinctions that lead to them, can be illustrated as a tree diagram (see Figure 2). Starting from the general notion of “solidarity in the context of CTA” one can apply the first key distinction and distinguish between the two basic concepts of solidarity, then one can apply the second key distinction and distinguish between the different temporal relations of solidarity and CTA, thirdly one can further specify by adding the different causal interactions between solidarity and CTA.

FIGURE 2
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 2. Illustration of the five understandings of solidarity in the context of CTA (created by the author).

Assignment of the papers to the five understandings

Along this tree diagram, all 47 papers can be assigned to (at least) one of these understandings. To do so, one must first decide whether a paper understands solidarity as a form of social cohesion or as a moral value. There is a list of operators that indicates whether solidarity is understood as the former of the latter. Subsequently, one can use the next list of operators to assign each paper to (at least) one understanding of solidarity.

Operators indicating that solidarity is understood as a form of social cohesion are: Solidarity explicitly refers to a social system (e.g., societies and communities); solidarity denotes an organizational form of social systems (e.g., nations, countries, the public sphere, and community initiatives); solidarity refers to groups or individuals of social systems (e.g., poor people, citizens of a state, the public, and population); solidarity describes the cohesion of a social system or an essential factor for it (e.g., shared feelings); solidarity describes a group of persons close to each other (e.g., families); solidarity describes the cooperation of different actors; or solidarity describes a relationship between different actors (e.g., human and technology). Operators indicating that solidarity is understood as a moral value are: Solidarity is explicitly described as a moral value or ethical principle; solidarity is mentioned in a series with other moral values or ethical principles; solidarity is described as belonging to the good; Solidarity is mentioned in reference to concerns, considerations, decision, evaluations or failures; or solidarity is taught through moral education.

Subsequently, the second key distinction and the causal interactions—which I have summarized in the following list of operators for the sake of clarity—can be used to classify how solidarity relates to CTA in terms of time and causality.

• If solidarity is understood as a form of social cohesion, operators indicating that solidarity precedes CTA in time are (understanding 1): Solidarity is described as condition for the implementation and acceptance of CTA; solidarity promotes the acceptance and use of CTA; or solidarity is necessary for the development of CTA.

• If solidarity is understood as a form of social cohesion, operators indicating that solidarity follows from CTA and that CTA constitute or strengthen solidarity are (understanding 2a): The text explicitly states that CTA constitute or strengthen social cohesion; CTA strengthen factors that are elementary for social cohesion; CTA prevent negative consequences for the social cohesion; or CTA open up possibilities of reimagining old and establishing new relationships.

• If solidarity is understood as a form of social cohesion, operators indicating that solidarity follows from CTA and that CTA weaken or undermine solidarity are (understanding 2b): The text explicitly states that CTA threaten, weaken or undermine social cohesion; CTA weaken factors that are elementary for social cohesion or reinforce factors that damage social cohesion; the introduction of CTA worsens the situation of a group of people or increases existing vulnerabilities or marginalizations; or the resources used for the development and implementation of CTA would have had more positive effects on the community if used in an alternative way.

• If solidarity is understood as a moral value, operators indicating that solidarity considers CTA from an ex-ante perspective are (understanding 3): Solidarity is referred to as a central criterion for ethical or legal concerns, considerations or decision; solidarity is introduced to orient or guide a decisions or actions; solidarity imposes obligations to act; or solidarity helps individuals to become aware of their role.

• If solidarity is understood as a moral value, operators indicating that solidarity considers CTA from an ex-post perspective are (understanding 4): Solidarity refers to past discussions or decisions; solidarity serves as criterion for the evaluation of past discussions or decisions; solidarity is presented as a moral value with which past failures could have been avoided; or solidarity is a criterion to evaluate other people's behavior.

Since the list of operators in the text can be somewhat confusing, there is a table of the various understandings of solidarity and their corresponding operators in Appendix 2 (Supplementary Material 2, starting from page 1).

Using the operators to identify how “solidarity” is understood in the passages mentioning the notion, one can assign the papers to the understandings. A paper is assigned to an understanding if the operators indicate that solidarity is understood in this way in at least one passage of the paper. A paper can also be assigned to several understandings if the operators identify different understandings in several passages of a paper. A detailed overview of the passages analyzed and their assignment to an understanding of solidarity in the context of CTA using the above operators can be found in Appendix 3 (Supplementary Material 2, starting from page 3).

As Table 2 with the overview of the different understandings and the authors shows, the five understandings of solidarity in the context of CTA occur with different frequency in the sample: most frequently, the notion “solidarity” is understood as a form of social cohesion that precedes CTA, is a condition for their implementation, and encourages their public acceptance and individual use (understanding 1, 16 times), closely followed by the understanding of solidarity as a moral value that considers CTA from an ex-ante perspective that orients and guides decisions about future actions concerning CTA (understanding 3, 15 times). Third most common is the understanding of solidarity as a form of social cohesion that is undermined or weakened by the implementation and use of CTA (understanding 2b, 12 times). Less frequently, the notion “solidarity” is understood as a moral value that considers CTA from an ex-post perspective, reflects and evaluates past decisions concerning their development, implementation, and use (understanding 4, 8 times), or as a form of social cohesion that is reinforced or created by the implementation and use of CTA (understanding 2a, 5 times).

TABLE 2
www.frontiersin.org

Table 2. Overview of the different understandings and the authors.

Discussion

The results show that there are five different understandings of solidarity in the context of CTA in the sample. These different understandings differ in how authors determine the basic concept of solidarity (solidarity as a form of social cohesion or as a moral value), the temporal relation between solidarity and CTA (solidarity either precedes or follows CTA) and the causal interactions between solidarity and CTA. The five different understandings vary in frequency in the sample. These results raise further questions: First, how do the different understandings of solidarity in the context of CTA relate to each other—are they mutually exclusive or complementary? Second, are the key distinctions on which these different understandings are based valid—i.e., are they really five different understandings of solidarity in the context of CTA? Third, what is the scope of these findings and what are their limitations? And fourth, how can these results help address the communication problems mentioned in the Introduction?

Relations between the five understandings of solidarity

These five different understandings of the notion “solidarity” in the context of CTA can relate to each other in different ways.

On the one hand, there are a total of seven papers out of 47 papers—and thus a significant portion—which can be assigned to more than one understanding of solidarity. Assuming that these papers are not incoherent in how they understand or use the notion “solidarity” and do not contain self-contradictions, these seven papers suggest that the five different understandings do not need to be contradictory. Instead, the different understandings can stand side by side, indicating that they are mutually complementary. For example, Nijsingh, van Bergen, and Wild describe the relationship between solidarity and CTA as feedback loops: “Attempts to responsibly introduce CT technology are thus confronted with feedback loops: low effectiveness raises costs and decreases uptake, attempts to counter this by raising effectiveness may decrease privacy, which then potentially decreases uptake, while raising uptake by implementing more or less mandatory approaches creates risks of backlash and crumbling public support, which then again lowers effectiveness. Of course, scenarios where positive reinforcing feedback loops take place are also possible. A fair and reliable system would lead to an increase in trust and potentially a shared feeling of solidarity, which will lead to a further increase in use and therefore effectiveness, etc.” (82) (italics added). When they describe solidarity as a shared feeling, they understand it, as the wider context of the passage makes clear, as an essential factor for the cohesion of a social system. The effective use of CTA can contribute to increasing this form of solidarity (understanding 2a), just as, conversely, the non-effective use of CTA can lead to a decrease in it (understanding 2b). At the same time, a circular relationship between CTA and solidarity as a feedback loop implies that solidarity contributes to the acceptance of CTA (understanding 1). A second example is Samuel and Sims and their accounts of solidarity and CTA: “Our findings showed how, through the mixture of both promissory discourses and altruistic discourses of solidarity, an imaginary was created that was imbued with implicit understandings of what is good or desirable in the social world. The future-oriented visions and promises attached to the app, along with calls of social obligation, constructed the trial of the app as a venture which was morally good, which was valued because of its ability to bring health benefits, and which was desirable in the social world of the Isle of Wight” (72) (italics added). They present solidarity as a currently imagined, future form of social cohesion in a particular social environment. The use of CTA, according to these visions, has a positive effect on social cohesion itself or central factors for it (understanding 2a). At the same time, solidarity is presented as a moral value that belongs to the morally good and from which a social obligation to use CTA arises (understanding 3). The understanding of solidarity as a moral value thereby emerges from the understanding of solidarity as an imagined form of social cohesion. In both Nijsingh, van Bergen, and Wild and Samuel and Sims, different understandings of solidarity in the context of CTA simultaneously coexist and complement each other.

On the other hand, the different understandings of solidarity can also contradict each other and lead to opposing recommendations. This becomes evident, when contrasting how, e.g., Kahn (110) understands “solidarity” with how Chang et al. (38), or how Pila (83) understand the notion. Kahn (110) assumes that the implementation and use of CTA will have a positive effect on society by counteracting the spread of COVID-19. Accordingly, he favors CTA and uses the notion “solidarity” to promote their implementation and use (understanding 1). In contrast, Chang et al. (38) and Pila (83) demonstrate how the introduction of CTA has negative effects on society or individual groups within it. They use “solidarity” to show how CTA can undermine it and to warn against the use of CTA in the name of solidarity (understanding 2b). These authors' examples show how different understandings of solidarity in the context of CTA can contradict each other and lead to different recommendations.

Contrasting both positions shows that the different understandings of solidarity in the context of CTA can both complement but also contradict each other—and even lead to opposing recommendations. This makes it even more important to define exactly what the notion means whenever it is used.

The hermeneutic nature of the key distinctions

One result of the review is that in the context of CTA two basic concepts of solidarity can be distinguished. Solidarity is understood either as a factual form of social cohesion or as a moral value—this key distinction is the basis of the five understandings of solidarity.

At first glance, this distinction seems to be contradictory to the concept of solidarity, as it is outlined in the discussions about solidarity. As, e.g., Bayertz (46) shows in his study Four uses of “solidarity”, this distinction cannot be strictly maintained. He refers to the history of the concept solidarity and shows that only the earliest academic uses of solidarity understand it solely as a factual form of social cohesion. Yet, already Émile Durkheim at the end of the nineteenth century presents a concept of solidarity, that includes both, factual and moral aspects. For him, solidarity primarily refers to the various ties that bind members of a society together and thus ensure its cohesion (111). But he continues to show that this social cohesion has considerable influence on morality and moral obligations of the community (112)—thus indicating that factual forms of social cohesion and moral values can never be separated from each other (113). Durkheim's contemporaries, as Bayertz (46) and ter Meulen (114) show, share this understanding of solidarity. Bourgeois (115), for instance, uses the notion “solidarity” to refer to the factual forms of social cohesion in a society as well as to describe the moral obligations that arise from it. This understanding of solidarity as both factual form of social cohesion and moral value, prevails, so that: “‘Solidarity’ is now comprehended as a mutual attachment between individuals, encompassing two levels: a factual level of actual common ground between the individuals and a normative level of mutual obligations to aid each other, as and when should be necessary.” (46).

This understanding of solidarity as a moral value, which is based on factual forms of social cohesion and aims at maintaining the community through its members solidary supporting each other, is common sense today in almost all publications concerned with solidarity (60, 114, 116120). While there are still different understandings of how a solidarity community is constituted, what forms of cohesion exist within it, and what moral values arise from it, the simultaneity and mutuality of moral values and factual forms of social cohesion is set.

When I speak of solidarity either as a factual form of social cohesion or of solidarity as a moral value, I do not intend to fall behind the state of research and do not wish to separate and isolate moral values and factual forms of social cohesion from each other. By distinguishing between these two basic concepts, I want to do justice to the observation that many authors in the sample, when they use “solidarity”, put an emphasis—and they understand solidarity either rather as a factual form of social cohesion or rather as a moral value. The distinction between both basic concepts should help to identify these emphases in a hermeneutic way—without separating factual forms of social cohesion and moral values or ignoring their reciprocity.

If the underlying key distinction is already hermeneutic in nature and indicates different emphases without introducing a strict separation between two basic concepts, the resulting five understandings of solidarity are also hermeneutic in nature—and serve to capture the various aspects, nuances and emphases of “solidarity” in the context of CTA.

Limitations

The review shows how “solidarity” is understood by different authors in the context of CTA. It proceeds inductively and is oriented toward the passages that mention solidarity in the context of CTA. Still—or maybe due to this approach—the review has some limitations.

First, the results are based on a relatively small database of only 47 papers, which are included in the final review. The database could be expanded if non-reviewed, non-academic papers, and gray literature were included. But this would, in turn, reduce the average assessed quality of the papers (52). So, although the database is small, it is of high quality. Second, the question about the different understandings of solidarity in the context of CTA is very specific—it focuses on only one notion in one single context. However, the same applies here: precisely due to its narrow focus, the review is highly informative.

Both limitations raise the question of whether the results are valid beyond this one context. On the one hand, it must be noted that the five understandings of solidarity as elaborated here are only valid for the context of CTA. On the other hand—as shown not least by the above discussion on the distinction between the two basic concepts—some of the distinctions made here can be found elsewhere in the discussions on the concept of solidarity. Thus, while the five understandings of solidarity have no validity beyond the context of CTA, they offer representative distinctions within the concept of solidarity that also prove to be valid elsewhere.

Practical recommendations

In conclusion, some practical recommendations can be given regarding the different understandings of the notion “solidarity” in the context of CTA. First, it is important to specify precisely how one understands “solidarity” when using the notion in academic (or political) discussions about CTA. This helps to avoid polysemy, lexical ambiguity, and talking past each other, and thus contributes to preventing the central communicative misunderstandings identified in Section Introduction—as well as the negative consequences that result from them. The five understandings of “solidarity” in the context of CTA, presented in Section Results, can serve as orientation and help specify the notion in discussions.

Second, communication problems and misunderstandings also limit the success of public health communication (121, 122). Therefore, when using the term “solidarity” in public health communication, it is important to be specific about how it is understood. Because failing to do so, and not being clear about how and why the notion “solidarity” is used to promote public health intervention, e.g., the use of CTA, may in the worst case lead, as Guttman and Lev show (123), to the public beginning to distrust the notion—as well as the goals or public health measures it promotes and the institutions that use it. To prevent this loss of public trust, it is important not to strain the notions in public health communication (124) and to use them as clearly as possible—which, in the case of solidarity and CTA, the five understandings in Section Results can help to do.

Data availability statement

The original contributions presented in the study are included in the article/supplementary material, further inquiries can be directed to the corresponding author/s.

Author contributions

The author confirms being the sole contributor of this work and has approved it for publication.

Funding

This work has been funded by a Grant from the Federal Ministry of Research and Education (Grant Number: 01GP1905B). The funder played no role in conducting the research or writing the paper.

Acknowledgments

The author is grateful to Matthias Braun, Lorenz Garbe, Isabella Auer, and Serena Bischoff for helpful discussions and comments.

Conflict of interest

The author declares that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Publisher's note

All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article, or claim that may be made by its manufacturer, is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.

Supplementary material

The Supplementary Material for this article can be found online at: https://www.frontiersin.org/articles/10.3389/fpubh.2022.859831/full#supplementary-material

References

1. O'Neill PH, Ryan-Mosley T, Bobbie J. A Flood of Coronavirus Apps Are Tracking Us. Now It's Time to Keep Track of Them. (2020). Available online at: https://www.technologyreview.com/2020/05/07/1000961/launching-mittr-covid-tracing-tracker/ (accessed July 27, 2021).

2. European Commission. Mobile Contact Tracing Apps in Eu Member States. (2021). Available online at: https://ec.europa.eu/info/live-work-travel-eu/coronavirus-response/travel-during-coronavirus-pandemic/mobile-contact-tracing-apps-eu-member-states_en (accessed August 2, 2021).

3. Ahmad S, Chitkara P, Khan FN, Kishan A, Alok V, Ramlal A, et al. Mobile technology solution for Covid-19: surveillance and prevention. In: Raza K, editor. Computational Intelligence Methods in Covid-19: Surveillance, Prevention, Prediction and Diagnosis. Singapore: Studies in Computational Intelligence (2021). p. 79–108.

Google Scholar

4. Scassa T. Pandemic innovation: the private sector and the development of contact-tracing and exposure notification apps. Bus Hum Rights J. (2021) 6:352–9. doi: 10.1017/bhj.2021.12

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

5. Stanley K, Granick JS. The Limits of Location Tracking in an Epidemic. (2020). Available online at: https://www.aclu.org/sites/default/files/field_document/limits_of_location_tracking_in_an_epidemic.pdf (accessed March 30, 2022).

Google Scholar

6. Corona-Warn-App. Corona-Warn-App Open Source Project. (2022). Available online at: https://www.coronawarn.app/en/ (accessed March 30, 2022).

7. Ferretti L, Wymant C, Kendall M, Zhao L, Nurtay A, Abeler-Dorner L, et al. Quantifying SARS-CoV-2 transmission suggests epidemic control with digital contact tracing. Science. (2020) 368:abb6936. doi: 10.1126/science.abb6936

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

8. Grekousis G, Liu Y. Digital contact tracing, community uptake, and proximity awareness technology to fight Covid-19: a systematic review. Sustain Cities Soc. (2021) 71:102995. doi: 10.1016/j.scs.2021.102995

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

9. Lewis D. Contact-tracing apps help reduce covid infections, data suggest. Nature. (2021) 591:18–9. doi: 10.1038/d41586-021-00451-y

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

10. Rodriguez P, Grana S, Alvarez-Leon EE, Battaglini M, Darias FJ, Hernan MA, et al. A population-based controlled experiment assessing the epidemiological impact of digital contact tracing. Nat Commun. (2021) 12:587. doi: 10.1038/s41467-020-20817-6

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

11. Salathe M, Althaus C, Anderegg N, Antonioli D, Ballouz T, Bugnon E, et al. Early evidence of effectiveness of digital contact tracing for SARS-CoV-2 in Switzerland. Swiss Med Wkly. (2020) 150:w20457. doi: 10.4414/smw.2020.20457

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

12. Jenniskens K, Bootsma MCJ, Damen J, Oerbekke MS, Vernooij RWM, Spijker R, et al. Effectiveness of contact tracing apps for SARS-CoV-2: a rapid systematic review. BMJ Open. (2021) 11:e050519. doi: 10.1136/bmjopen-2021-050519

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

13. Colizza V, Grill E, Mikolajczyk R, Cattuto C, Kucharski A, Riley S, et al. Time to evaluate covid-19 contact-tracing apps. Nat Med. (2021) 27:361–2. doi: 10.1038/s41591-021-01236-6

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

14. Chiusi F. Digital Contact Tracing Apps: Do They Actually Work? A Review of Early Evidence. (2021). Available online at: https://algorithmwatch.org/en/analysis-digital-contact-tracing-apps-2021/ (accessed August 02, 2021).

15. Garrett P, White J, Dennis S, Little D, Perfors A, Kashima Y, et al. Attitudes of Australians to the Government's COVIDSafe Contact Tracing App. (2020). Available online at: https://psychologicalsciences.unimelb.edu.au/chdh/news/attitudes-of-australians-to-the-governments-covidsafe-contact-tracing-app (accessed March 30, 2022).

16. Oldeweme A, Martins J, Westmattelmann D, Schewe G. The role of transparency, trust, and social influence on uncertainty reduction in times of pandemics: empirical study on the adoption of Covid-19 tracing apps. J Med Internet Res. (2021) 23:e25893. doi: 10.2196/25893

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

17. Villius Zetterholm M, Lin Y, Jokela P. Digital contact tracing applications during covid-19: a scoping review about public acceptance. Informatics. (2021) 8:48. doi: 10.3390/informatics8030048

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

18. Samuel G, Lucivero F, Johnson S, Diedericks H. Ecologies of public trust: the Nhs Covid-19 contact tracing app. J Bioeth Inq. (2021) 18:595–608. doi: 10.1007/s11673-021-10127-x

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

19. Chugh R. By Persisting with COVIDSafe, Australia Risks Missing Out on Globally Trusted Contact Tracing. (2020). Available online at: https://theconversation.com/by-persisting-with-covidsafe-australia-risks-missing-out-on-globally-trusted-contact-tracing-141369 (accessed March 30, 2022).

20. Akinbi A, Forshaw M, Blinkhorn V. Contact tracing apps for the covid-19 pandemic: a systematic literature review of challenges and future directions for neo-liberal societies. Health Inf Sci Syst. (2021) 9:18. doi: 10.1007/s13755-021-00147-7

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

21. Olu OO, Lamunu M, Nanyunja M, Dafae F, Samba T, Sempiira N, et al. Contact tracing during an outbreak of ebola virus disease in the western area districts of sierra leone: lessons for future ebola outbreak response. Front Public Health. (2016) 4:130. doi: 10.3389/fpubh.2016.00130

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

22. Danquah LO, Hasham N, MacFarlane M, Conteh FE, Momoh F, Tedesco AA, et al. Use of a mobile application for ebola contact tracing and monitoring in northern sierra leone: a proof-of-concept study. BMC Infect Dis. (2019) 19:810. doi: 10.1186/s12879-019-4354-z

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text

23. Wen H, Zhao Q, Lin Z, Xuan D, Shroff N. A study of the privacy of covid-19 contact tracing apps. In: Park N, Sun K, Foresti S, Butler K, Saxena N, editors. Security and Privacy in Communication Networks. Lecture Notes of the Institute for Computer Sciences, Social Informatics and Telecommunications Engineering. Cham: Springer (2020). p. 297–317.

Google Scholar

24. Seto E, Challa P, Ware P. Adoption of covid-19 contact tracing apps: a balance between privacy and effectiveness. J Med Internet Res. (2021) 23:e25726. doi: 10.2196/25726

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

25. Akbari A. Authoritarian surveillance: a corona test. Surveill Soc. (2021) 19:98–103. doi: 10.24908/ss.v19i1.14545

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

26. Rowe F. Contact tracing apps and values dilemmas: a privacy paradox in a neo-liberal world. Int J Inf Manage. (2020) 55:102178. doi: 10.1016/j.ijinfomgt.2020.102178

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

27. Morley J, Cowls J, Taddeo M, Floridi L. Ethical guidelines for covid-19 tracing apps. Nature. (2020) 582:29–31. doi: 10.1038/d41586-020-01578-0

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

28. Braun M, Hummel P. Contact-tracing apps: contested answers to ethical questions. Nature. (2020) 583:360. doi: 10.1038/d41586-020-02084-z

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

29. Schneble CO, Elger BS, Martin Shaw D. Data protection during the coronavirus crisis. EMBO Rep. (2020) 21:e51362. doi: 10.15252/embr.202051362

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

30. Bradford L, Aboy M, Liddell K. Covid-19 contact tracing apps: a stress test for privacy, the gdpr, and data protection regimes. J Law Biosci. (2020) 7:lsaa034. doi: 10.1093/jlb/lsaa034

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

31. Sowmiya B, Abhijith VS, Sudersan S, Sakthi Jaya Sundar R, Thangavel M, Varalakshmi P, et al. Survey on security and privacy issues in contact tracing application of covid-19. SN Comput Sci. (2021) 2:136. doi: 10.1007/s42979-021-00520-z

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

32. Criddle C, Kelion L. Coronavirus Contact-Tracing: World Split Between Two Types of App. (2020). Available online at: https://www.bbc.com/news/technology-52355028 (accessed August 02, 2021).

33. Dahdad M, Alam MJ. Tracing Apps to Fight Covid-19: Are Surveillance Technologies Effective? (2020). Available online at: https://booksandideas.net/Tracing-Apps-to-Fight-Covid-19.html (accessed October 27, 2020).

Google Scholar

34. Toussaert S. Upping uptake of covid contact tracing apps. Nat Hum Behav. (2021) 5:183–4. doi: 10.1038/s41562-021-01048-1

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

35. Munzert S, Selb P, Gohdes A, Stoetzer LF, Lowe W. Tracking and promoting the usage of a covid-19 contact tracing app. Nat Hum Behav. (2021) 5:247–55. doi: 10.1038/s41562-020-01044-x

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

36. Parker MJ, Fraser C, Abeler-Dorner L, Bonsall D. Ethics of instantaneous contact tracing using mobile phone apps in the control of the covid-19 pandemic. J Med Ethics. (2020) 46:427–31. doi: 10.1136/medethics-2020-106314

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

37. Lewandowsky S, Dennis S, Perfors A, Kashima Y, White JP, Garrett P, et al. Public acceptance of privacy-encroaching policies to address the covid-19 pandemic in the United Kingdom. PLoS ONE. (2021) 16:e0245740. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0245740

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

38. Chang J, Agliata J, Guarinieri M. Covid-19 - enacting a ‘new normal’ for people who use drugs. Int J Drug Policy. (2020) 83:102832. doi: 10.1016/j.drugpo.2020.102832

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

39. Smith J. Q&A: Future Pandemics Are Inevitable, But We Can Reduce the Risk. (2021). Available online at: https://ec.europa.eu/research-and-innovation/en/horizon-magazine/qa-future-pandemics-are-inevitable-we-can-reduce-risk (accessed March 30, 2022).

Google Scholar

40. The Lancet Respiratory Medicine. Future pandemics: failing to prepare means preparing to fail. Lancet Respiratory Med. (2022) 10:221–2. doi: 10.1016/S2213-2600(22)00056-X

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

41. O'Connell J, O'Keeffe DT. Contact tracing for covid-19 - a digital inoculation against future pandemics. N Engl J Med. (2021) 385:484–7. doi: 10.1056/NEJMp2102256

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

42. Abdalla SM, Koya SF, Jamieson M, Verma M, Haldane V, Jung AS, et al. Investing in trust and community resilience: lessons from the early months of the first digital pandemic. BMJ. (2021) 375:e067487. doi: 10.1136/bmj-2021-067487

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

43. Majid U, Wasim A, Truong J, Bakshi S. Public trust in governments, health care providers, and the media during pandemics: a systematic review. J Trust Res. (2022) 11:1–23. doi: 10.1080/21515581.2022.2029742

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

44. Visvizi A, Lytras M. Editorial. Trans Gov People Process Policy. (2020) 14:125–31. doi: 10.1108/TG-05-2020-128

CrossRef Full Text

45. Wittgenstein L. Philosophical Investigations. 3rd ed. Oxford: Basil Blackwell (1967).

Google Scholar

46. Bayertz K. Four uses of “solidarity”. In: Bayertz K, editor. Solidarity. Philosophical Studies in Contemporary Culture. Dordrecht, Boston, London: Kluwer Academic (1999). p. 3–28.

Google Scholar

47. Derrida J. Margins of Philosophy. Brighton: The Harvester Press (1982).

Google Scholar

48. Kroeger P. Analyzing Meaning. An Introduction to Semantics and Pragmatics. 2nd ed. Berlin: Language Science Press (2019).

Google Scholar

49. Rancière J. Disagreement. Politics and Philosophy Minneapolis. London: University of Minnesota Press (1998).

Google Scholar

50. Strech D, Sofaer N. How to write a systematic review of reasons. J Med Ethics. (2012) 38:121–6. doi: 10.1136/medethics-2011-100096

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

51. Tranfield D, Denyer D, Smart P. Towards a methodology for developing evidence-informed management knowledge by means of systematic review. Br J Manag. (2003) 14:207–22. doi: 10.1111/1467-8551.00375

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

52. Jesson KK, Matheson L, Lacey FM. Doing Your Literature Review. Traditional and Systematic Techniques. New York, NY: SAGE (2011).

Google Scholar

53. Stoye E. China coronavirus: how many papers have been published? Nature. (2020) 395:684–5. doi: 10.1038/d41586-020-00253-8

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

54. Molenberghs G, Buyse M, Abrams S, Hens N, Beutels P, Faes C, et al. Infectious diseases epidemiology, quantitative methodology, and clinical research in the midst of the covid-19 pandemic: perspective from a European country. Contemp Clin Trials. (2020) 99:106189. doi: 10.1016/j.cct.2020.106189

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

55. Martin T, Karopoulos G, Hernández-Ramos JL, Kambourakis G, Nai Fovino I, Choo K-KR. Demystifying covid-19 digital contact tracing: a survey on frameworks and mobile apps. Wireless Commun Mobile Comput. (2020) 2020:1–29. doi: 10.1155/2020/8851429

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

56. Blumenthal-Barby J, Boyd K, Earp BD, Frith L, McDougall RJ, McMillan J, et al. Pandemic Medical Ethics. J Med Ethics. (2020) 46:353–4. doi: 10.1136/medethics-2020-106431

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

57. Brussow H. Covid-19: test, trace and isolate-new epidemiological data. Environ Microbiol. (2020) 22:2445–56. doi: 10.1111/1462-2920.15118

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

58. Burnard P. A method of analysing interview transcripts in qualitative research. Nurse Educ Today. (1991) 11:461–6. doi: 10.1016/0260-6917(91)90009-Y

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

59. Brown RCH, Savulescu J, Williams B, Wilkinson D. Passport to freedom? Immunity passports for Covid-19. J Med Ethics. (2020) 46:652–9. doi: 10.1136/medethics-2020-106365

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

60. Prainsack B, Buyx A. Solidarity in Biomedicine and Beyond. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (2017). doi: 10.1017/9781139696593

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

61. de Saussure F. Cours De Linguistique Générale. Paris: Payot (1995).

Google Scholar

62. Hayry M. Covid-19: another look at solidarity. Camb Q Healthc Ethics. (2020) 31:256–62. doi: 10.1017/S0963180120001115

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

63. Sennett R. Together. The Rituals, Pleasures and Politics of Co-Operation. New Haven, London: Yale University Press (2012).

Google Scholar

64. Schroeder M. Value theory. In: Zalta EN, editor. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2021). Available online at: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2021/entries/value-theory/ (accessed August 4, 2021).

Google Scholar

65. Richardson HS. Moral reasoning. In: Zalta EN, editor. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. (2018). Available online at: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/reasoning-moral/ (accessed January 15, 2021).

Google Scholar

66. Lee T, Lee H. Tracing surveillance and auto-regulation in singapore: ‘smart’ responses to covid-19. Media Int Aust. (2020) 177:47–60. doi: 10.1177/1329878X20949545

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

67. Gibney S, Bruton L, Doherty P. Covid Contact Tracing App: User Perspectives and Experience Research. Dublin: Government of Oreland (2020).

Google Scholar

68. Milne R, Costa A. Disruption and dislocation in post-covid futures for digital health. Big Data Soc. (2020) 7:567. doi: 10.1177/2053951720949567

CrossRef Full Text

69. Dowthwaite L, Fischer J, Perez Vallejos E, Portillo V, Nichele E, Goulden M, et al. Public adoption of and trust in the Nhs covid-19 contact tracing app in the United Kingdom: quantitative online survey study. J Med Internet Res. (2021) 23:e29085. doi: 10.2196/29085

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

70. Lu G, Razum O, Jahn A, Zhang Y, Sutton B, Sridhar D, et al. Covid-19 in Germany and China: mitigation versus elimination strategy. Glob Health Action. (2021) 14:1875601. doi: 10.1080/16549716.2021.1875601

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

71. Samuel G, Roberts SL, Fiske A, Lucivero F, McLennan S, Phillips A, et al. COVID-19 contact tracing apps: UK public perceptions. Critical Public Health. (2021) 32:31–43. doi: 10.1080/09581596.2021.1909707

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

72. Samuel G, Sims R. The UK covid-19 contact tracing app as both an emerging technology and public health intervention: the need to consider promissory discourses. Health. (2021) 2021:13634593211060768. doi: 10.1177/13634593211060768

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

73. Stefan OA. The future of european union soft law: a research and policy agenda for the aftermath of covid-19. J Int Comp Law. (2020) 7:329–50. doi: 10.2139/ssrn.3702534

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

74. Georgieva I, Beaunoyer E, Guitton MJ. Ensuring social acceptability of technological tracking in the covid-19 context. Comput Hum Behav. (2021) 116:639. doi: 10.1016/j.chb.2020.106639

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

75. Lanzing M. Contact tracing apps: an ethical roadmap. Ethics Inf Technol. (2020) 23:1–4. doi: 10.1007/s10676-020-09548-w

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

76. Nanni M, Andrienko G, Barabasi AL, Boldrini C, Bonchi F, Cattuto C, et al. Give more data, awareness and control to individual citizens, and they will help covid-19 containment. Ethics Inf Technol. (2021) 23:1–6. doi: 10.1007/s10676-020-09572-w

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

77. Sekalala S, Dagron S, Forman L, Meier BM. Analyzing the human rights impact of increased digital public health surveillance during the COVID-19 crisis. Health Hum Rights. (2020) 22:7–20.

PubMed Abstract | Google Scholar

78. Sagan A, Bryndova L, Kowalska-Bobko I, Smatana M, Spranger A, Szerencses V, et al. A reversal of fortune: comparison of health system responses to covid-19 in the visegrad group during the early phases of the pandemic. Health Policy. (2021) 126:446–55. doi: 10.1016/j.healthpol.2021.10.009

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

79. Saunes IS, Vrangbaek K, Byrkjeflot H, Jervelund SS, Birk HO, Tynkkynen LK, et al. Nordic responses to covid-19: governance and policy measures in the early phases of the pandemic. Health Policy. (2021) 126:418–26. doi: 10.1016/j.healthpol.2021.08.011

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

80. Leslie D. Tackling covid-19 through responsible AI innovation: five steps in the right direction. SSRN Electr J. (2020) 1–42. doi: 10.2139/ssrn.3652970

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

81. Mangan D, Gramano E, Kullmann M. An unprecedented social solidarity stress test. Eur Labour Law J. (2020) 11:247–75. doi: 10.1177/2031952520934585

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

82. Nijsingh N, van Bergen A, Wild V. Applying a precautionary approach to mobile contact tracing for covid-19: the value of reversibility. J Bioeth Inq. (2020) 17:823–7. doi: 10.1007/s11673-020-10004-z

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

83. Pila J. Covid-19 and contact tracing: a study in regulation by technology. Eur J Law Technol. (2020) 11:504. doi: 10.2139/ssrn.3749504

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

84. Matt C. Campaigning for the greater good? – How persuasive messages affect the evaluation of contact tracing apps. J Decis Syst. (2021) 31:1–18. doi: 10.1080/12460125.2021.1873493

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

85. Montanari Vergallo G, Zaami S, Marinelli E. The covid-19 pandemic and contact tracing technologies, between upholding the right to health and personal data protection. Eur Rev Med Pharmacol Sci. (2021) 25:2449–56. doi: 10.26355/eurrev_202103_25286

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

86. van Hees S, Greubel C, Moors E, Peine A. Valuation in health and ageing innovation practices. Ageing Soc. (2021) 1–19. doi: 10.1017/S0144686X21001483

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

87. Wnuk A, Oleksy T, Domaradzka A. Prosociality and endorsement of liberty: communal and individual predictors of attitudes towards surveillance technologies. Comput Human Behav. (2021) 125:106938. doi: 10.1016/j.chb.2021.106938

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

88. French M, Guta A, Gagnon M, Mykhalovskiy E, Roberts SL, Goh S, et al. Corporate contact tracing as a pandemic response. Crit Public Health. (2020) 32:1–8. doi: 10.1080/09581596.2020.1829549

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

89. Milan S. Techno-solutionism and the standard human in the making of the covid-19 pandemic. Big Data Soc. (2020) 7:781. doi: 10.1177/2053951720966781

CrossRef Full Text

90. Alemanno A, Bialasiewicz L. Certifying health: the unequal legal geographies of covid-19 certificates. Eur J Risk Regul. (2021) 12:273–86. doi: 10.1017/err.2021.38

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

91. Barocas S, Biega AJ, Boyarskaya M, Crawford K, Iii HD, Dudík M, et al. Responsible computing during covid-19 and beyond. Commun ACM. (2021) 64:30–2. doi: 10.1145/3466612

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

92. Price C. Covid-19: when species and data meet. Postdigital Sci Educ. (2020) 2:772–90. doi: 10.1007/s42438-020-00180-x

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

93. Findlay MJ, Remolina N. Regulating personal data usage in covid-19 control conditions. SSRN Electr J. (2020) 126:418–26. doi: 10.2139/ssrn.3607706

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

94. Mello MM, Wang CJ. Ethics and governance for digital disease surveillance. Science. (2020) 368:951–4. doi: 10.1126/science.abb9045

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

95. Batifoulier P, Diaz-Bone R. Perspectives on the economics and sociology of health. Contributions from the institutionalist approach of economics of convention – an introduction. Histor Soc Res Historische Sozialforschung. (2021) 46:7–34. doi: 10.12759/hsr.46.2021.1.7-34

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

96. Hendl T, Chung R, Wild V. Pandemic surveillance and racialized subpopulations: mitigating vulnerabilities in covid-19 apps. J Bioeth Inq. (2020) 17:829–34. doi: 10.1007/s11673-020-10034-7

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

97. Keating J. Responsible design through interdisciplinary collaboration: contact tracing apps, surveillance and the prospect of building user trust. Bull Tech Comm Data Eng. (2020) 43:11−22.

Google Scholar

98. Mbunge E, Fashoto SG, Akinnuwesi B, Metfula A, Simelane S, Ndumiso N. Ethics for integrating emerging technologies to contain covid-19 in Zimbabwe. Hum Behav Emerg Technol. (2021) 3, 876–90. doi: 10.1002/hbe2.277

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

99. Mbunge E, Millham RC, Sibiya MN, Fashoto SG, Akinnuwesi B, Simelane S, et al. Framework for ethical and acceptable use of social distancing tools and smart devices during covid-19 pandemic in Zimbabwe. Sustain Operat Comput. (2021) 2:190–9. doi: 10.1016/j.susoc.2021.07.003

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

100. Watson C, Ali R, Smeddinck JD. Tensions and mitigations: understanding concerns and values around smartphone data collection for public health emergencies. Proc ACM Hum Comput Interact. (2021) 5:1–31. doi: 10.1145/3476071

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

101. Hummel P, Braun M. Just data? Solidarity and justice in data-driven medicine. Life Sci Soc Policy. (2020) 16:8. doi: 10.1186/s40504-020-00101-7

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

102. Hoffman AS, Jacobs B, van Gastel B, Schraffenberger H, Sharon T, Pas B. Towards a seamful ethics of covid-19 contact tracing apps? Ethics Inf Technol. (2021) 23:1–11. doi: 10.1007/s10676-020-09559-7

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

103. Siffels LE. Beyond privacy vs. health: a justification analysis of the contact-tracing apps debate in the Netherlands. Ethics Inf Technol. (2021) 23:99–103. doi: 10.1007/s10676-020-09555-x

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

104. Blauth TF, Gstrein OJ. Data-driven measures to mitigate the impact of covid-19 in south america: how do regional programmes compare to best practice? Int Data Privacy Law. (2021) 11:18–31. doi: 10.1093/idpl/ipab002

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

105. Christofidou M, Lea N, Coorevits P. A literature review on the Gdpr, COVID-19 and the ethical considerations of data protection during a time of crisis. Yearb Med Inform. (2021) 30:226–32. doi: 10.1055/s-0041-1726512

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

106. El-Haddadeh R, Fadlalla A, Hindi NM. Is there a place for responsible artificial intelligence in pandemics? A tale of two countries. Inf Syst Front. (2021) 1–17. doi: 10.1007/s10796-021-10140-w

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

107. Roche S. Smile, You're being traced! Some thoughts about the ethical issues of digital contact tracing applications. J Locat Based Serv. (2020) 14:71–91. doi: 10.1080/17489725.2020.1811409

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

108. Kaspar K. Motivations for social distancing and app use as complementary measures to combat the covid-19 pandemic: quantitative survey study. J Med Internet Res. (2020) 22:e21613. doi: 10.2196/21613

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

109. Gasser U, Ienca M, Scheibner J, Sleigh J, Vayena E. Digital tools against covid-19: taxonomy, ethical challenges, and navigation aid. Lancet Digit Health. (2020) 2:e425–e34. doi: 10.1016/S2589-7500(20)30137-0

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

110. Kahn JP. Digital Contact Tracing for Pandemic Response: Ethics and Governance Guidance. Baltimore, MD: John Hopkins Project on Ethics and Governance of Digital Contact Tracing Technologies (2020).

Google Scholar

111. Durkheim É. The Division of Labour in Society. 2nd ed. London: Palgrave Macmillan (2013).

Google Scholar

112. Durkheim É. On Morality and Society. Selected Writings. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press (1973).

Google Scholar

113. Gofman A. Durkheim's theory of social solidarity and social rules. In: Jeffries V, editor. The Palgrave Handbook of Altruism, Morality, and Social Solidarity Formulating a Field of Study. New York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan (2014). p. 45–69.

Google Scholar

114. ter Meulen R. Solidarity and Justice in Health and Social Care. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (2017). doi: 10.1017/9781107707023

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

115. Bourgeois L. Solidarité. Paris: BnF (2016).

Google Scholar

116. Prainsack B, Buyx A. Solidarity: Reflections on an Emerging Concept in Bioethics. London: Nuffield Council on Bioethics (2011).

Google Scholar

117. Bayertz K, editor. Solidarity. Dordrecht; Boston; London: Kluwer Academic (1999).

Google Scholar

118. Komter A. Social Solidarity and the Gift. Cambridge; New York, NY: Cambridge University Press (2005). doi: 10.1017/CBO9780511614064

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

119. Van Hoyweghen I, Pulignano V, Meyers G, editors. Shifting Solidarities. Trends and Developments in European Societies. Cham: Palgrave Macmillan (2020).

Google Scholar

120. Rorty R. Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity. Cambridge; New York, NY: Cambridge University Press (1993).

Google Scholar

121. Robinson KL, Driedger MS, Elliott SJ, Eyles J. Understanding facilitators of and barriers to health promotion practice. Health Promot Pract. (2006) 7:467–76. doi: 10.1177/1524839905278955

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

122. Guldan GS. Obstacles to community health promotion. Soc Sci Med. (1996) 43:689–95. doi: 10.1016/0277-9536(96)00114-1

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

123. Guttman N, Lev E. Ethical Issues in covid-19 communication to mitigate the pandemic: dilemmas and practical implications. Health Commun. (2021) 36:116–23. doi: 10.1080/10410236.2020.1847439

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

124. Diefenbacher H, Frühbauer JJ, Held B, van Oorschot F, Rodenhäuser D, Vetter H. Die Idee Der Solidarität in Der Corona-Pandemie. (2020). Available online at: https://www.fest-heidelberg.de/wp-content/uploads/2020/06/FEST_Die_Idee_der_Solidarität_final.pdf (accessed July 18, 2020).

Google Scholar

Keywords: solidarity, contact tracing, digital tracing, COVID-19, SARS-CoV-2, review

Citation: Tretter M (2022) How is “solidarity” understood in discussions about contact tracing apps? An overview. Front. Public Health 10:859831. doi: 10.3389/fpubh.2022.859831

Received: 21 January 2022; Accepted: 05 July 2022;
Published: 22 July 2022.

Edited by:

Victoria Team, Monash University, Australia

Reviewed by:

Bernadette Hyland-Wood, Queensland University of Technology, Australia
Chinmayee Mishra, Utkal University, India

Copyright © 2022 Tretter. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Max Tretter, max.tretter@fau.de

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.