Skip to main content

GENERAL COMMENTARY article

Front. Psychol., 20 December 2019
Sec. Consciousness Research
This article is part of the Research Topic Cognition during Sleep: Hyperassociativity, Associativity and New Connections View all 12 articles

Commentary: Measuring Counterintuitiveness in Supernatural Agent Dream Imagery

  • 1Online Department, TCA College, Singapore, Singapore
  • 2School of Intercultural Studies, Fuller Theological Seminary, Pasadena, CA, United States

A Commentary on
Measuring Counterintuitiveness in Supernatural Agent Dream Imagery

by Nordin, A., and Bjälkebring, P. (2019). Front. Psychol. 10:1728. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2019.01728

Nordin and Bjälkebring's research on counterintuitiveness (CI) in the dreams of Nepali Hindus is seemingly the first case of applying Barrett's (2008) coding scheme to dream reports. This commentary briefly addresses Nordin and Bjälkebring's main findings with the coding scheme before considering their proposal for the manifestation of supernatural agents (SAs) in dreams. As discussed below, their proposal is vague and ignores other factors that are relevant to oneiric SA manifestation.

Counterintuitive Objects in Dreams

According to Barrett (2008, 2011), whose work grounds Nordin and Bjälkebring's empirical study, humans naturally develop five general object categories/domains. CI applies to objects with properties that defy basic expectations for its domain (Barrett, 2008, 2011; Purzycki and Willard, 2015). “Talking tree” and “invisible statue that cries” meet CI qualifications because they defy basic expectations for plant and artifact domains. According to Barrett's (2008) coding scheme, these examples have respective CI scores of 1 and 2, given the number of violated expectations per domain.

Using the aforementioned coding scheme on a selection of Hindu supernatural/religious dream reports, Nordin and Bjälkebring report the vast majority of counterintuitive objects in their sample had a CI score of 1. This is consistent with expectations of minimal counterintuitiveness theory concerning cognitive load and narrative transmission (Barrett, 2008; Barrett et al., 2009). Additionally, they found just one counterintuitive object in the majority of dream reports, and counterintuitive agents greatly outnumbered other types of counterintuitive objects in their sample. Altogether, these findings are generally consistent with Barrett et al.'s (2009) study of folktales. The latter employed the CI scheme on an international sample and found artifacts possessing agent properties to be relatively rare. In contrast, artifacts were the most frequent counterintuitive agent in Nordin and Bjälkebring's study. A plausible way of accounting for this difference would be to consider the culture of Nordin and Bjälkebring's subjects. Idols (murti) are quite common in the villages and cities of Nepal, and a prominent part of Hindu religious life in particular. Thus, in association with the continuity hypothesis (see e.g., Domhoff, 1996; Bulkeley, 2009), I propose the frequency of counterintuitive object types in a dream report sample is a function of waking circumstances. Hence, a Christian or Muslim sample should reveal a lower frequency of counterintuitive artifacts than a Hindu one.

Supernatural Agent Cognition

Following McNamara and Bulkeley (2015), Nordin and Bjälkebring argue that the physiology of dreaming entails a diminished sense of personal agency, which could undergird SA cognition in light of the self's corresponding search for extrinsic event causes. Why, however, would subjects interact with SA concepts rather than other non-self concepts during dreaming? Nordin and Bjälkebring argue that certain situations the dreamer faces, viz., those involving perceived threat or anxiety, create inferential demands that make SA concepts attractive because of the latter's association with strategic information. While I would not want to discount their proposal entirely, several important concepts (threat, anxiety, strategic information) are vaguely defined, and other factors related to SA manifestation are ignored.

To support these contentions, I will briefly consider Nordin and Bjälkebring's second dream report example (p. 9). Though Nordin and Bjälkebring's theory applies to dreams rather than dream reports, the latter may nonetheless indicate features of the oneiric experience. Based on the report's details and Nordin and Bjälkebring's generic usage of threat and anxiety terminology, I am unable to conclude that the dreamer experienced these prior to the appearance of SAs. The dreamer's situation is more obviously a case of “unexpectedness” following a domain violation (involving a bowl). The concept of unexpectedness is lacking in Nordin and Bjälkebring's discussion, but it features prominently in several researchers' portrayals of religious/supernatural cognition (e.g., Taves, 2009; Hermans, 2015; Sears, 2016, in press). According to Fortier and Kim (2017), unexpectedness (resulting from drops in algorithmic complexity between expected and actual circumstances) begets agency detection, which leads to SA cognition if naturalistic concepts fail to account. Their “complexity drop model of the supernatural” (CDMS) arguably applies to the example under consideration1.

Nordin and Bjälkebring's threat theory and the CDMS explain SA concept activation rather than the visual experience of SAs. The latter is dependent on the former but requires special circumstances. From the perspective of hierarchical predictive coding, sensory data essentially acts as a corrective to mental modeling of perception (Hobson and Friston, 2012; Clark, 2013; Andersen et al., 2014). Based on this perspective, Hobson and Friston (2012) suggest the “bizarre” content of dreams may be due to sensory gating that normally occurs when the body is asleep. Following their reasoning, once SA cognition is activated during dreaming, subjects may continue to envision SAs without their appearance being impeded by sensory information (Sears, in press).

In sum, Nordin and Bjälkebrings's description of oneiric SA cognition is vague and limited. Besides diminished personal agency and threat/anxiety, unexpectedness, and sensory gating/deprivation play important roles in at least some SA dreams. Other factors—such as “ideal” content situations (Sears, 2016)—may likewise be relevant. Interestingly, each of the foregoing factors mentioned with respect to oneiric SA cognition has precedence in treatments of waking SA cognition (cf. Barrett, 2004, 2011; Taves, 2009; Andersen et al., 2014; Fortier and Kim, 2017). This statement is a testament to the principle of continuity between waking and dreaming. Given the typical physiology of dreaming, supernatural cognition and visual SA manifestation may be generally more common during dreaming than waking, though such possibilities stand in need of further research.

Author Contributions

The author confirms being the sole contributor of this work and has approved it for publication.

Conflict of Interest

The author declares that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Acknowledgments

I wish to thank Andreas Nordin and Pär Bjälkebring for giving me this opportunity to comment on their stimulating article. Justin Barrett deserves thanks for the initial referral.

Footnotes

1. ^Readers of Fortier and Kim's essay will see that they associate complexity drops with domain-general (prototypical) violations rather than the domain-specific (ontological/basic) violations associated with counterintuitiveness in the technical sense (cf. Purzycki and Willard, 2015). They do not defend this division adequately, and I do not think it can be maintained, given that “atypical” objects occasion complexity drops (cf. Dessalles, 2007; Fortier and Kim, 2017, p. 287). Phenomenologically speaking, both types of violations generally create unexpectedness; furthermore, both types of violations have been linked to SA cognition (Fortier and Kim, 2017).

References

Andersen, M., Schjoedt, U., Nielbo, K. L., and Sørensen, J. (2014). Mystical experience in the lab. Method Theor. Stud. Relig. 26, 217–245. doi: 10.1163/15700682-12341323

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Barrett, J. L. (2004). Why Would Anyone Believe in God? Lanham, MD: AltaMira Press.

Google Scholar

Barrett, J. L. (2008). Coding and quantifying counterintuitiveness in religious concepts: theoretical and methodological reflections. Method Theor. Stud. Relig. 20, 308–338. doi: 10.1163/157006808X371806

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Barrett, J. L. (2011). Cognitive Science, Religion, and Theology: From Human Minds to Divine Minds. West Conshohocken, PA: Templeton Press.

Google Scholar

Barrett, J. L., Burdett, E. R., and Porter, T. J. (2009). Counterintuitiveness in folktales: finding the cognitive optimum. J. Cogn. Cult. 9, 271–287. doi: 10.1163/156770909x12489459066345

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bulkeley, K. (2009). The religious content of dreams: a new scientific foundation. Pastor. Psychol. 58, 93–106. doi: 10.1007/s11089-008-0180-8

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Clark, A. (2013). Whatever next? Predictive brains, situated agents, and the future of cognitive science. Behav. Brain Sci. 36, 181–204. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X12000477

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Dessalles, J.-L. (2007). Spontaneous Assessment of Complexity in the Selection of Events. Technical Reports. Ecole Nationale Supérieure des Télécommunications, Paris. Available online at: https://pdfs.semanticscholar.org/39b7/82e3731b38a442d0bafc3384723bbfe9d5ff.pdf

Google Scholar

Domhoff, G. W. (1996). Finding Meaning in Dreams: A Quantitative Approach. New York, NY: Plenum Press.

Google Scholar

Fortier, M., and Kim, S. (2017). “From the impossible to the improbable: a probabilistic account of magical beliefs and practices across development and cultures,” in The Science of Lay Theories: How Beliefs Shape Our Cognition, Behavior, and Health, eds C. M. Zedelius, B. C. N. Müller, and J. W. Schooler (Cham: Springer), 265–315. doi: 10.1007/978-3-319-57306-9_12

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hermans, C. A. M. (2015). Towards a theory of spiritual and religious experiences: a building block approach of the unexpected possible. Arch. Psychol. Relig. 37, 141–167. doi: 10.1163/15736121-12341306

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hobson, J. A., and Friston, K. J. (2012). Waking and dreaming consciousness: neurobiological and functional considerations. Prog. Neurobiol. 98, 82–98. doi: 10.1016/j.pneurobio.2012.05.003

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

McNamara, P., and Bulkeley, K. (2015). Dreams as a source of supernatural agent concepts. Front. Psychol. 6:283. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2015.00283

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Purzycki, B. G., and Willard, A. K. (2015). MCI theory: a critical discussion. Relig. Brain Behav. 6, 207–248. doi: 10.1080/2153599X.2015.1024915

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Sears, R. E. (2016). Spiritual Dreams and the Nepalese: Attribution Theory and the Dream-Related Cognition of Nepali Christians and Hindus (Dissertation). Fuller Theological Seminary, Pasadena, CA, United States.

Google Scholar

Sears, R. E. (in press). “Conceiving religious dreams and mystical experiences: a predictive processing investigation,” in The Oxford Handbook of the Cognitive Science of Religion, ed J. L. Barrett (New York, NY: Oxford University Press).

Google Scholar

Taves, A. (2009). Religious Experience Reconsidered: A Building Block Approach to the Study of Religion and Other Special Things. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Google Scholar

Keywords: dreaming, cognition, counterintuition, supernatural agent concept, CI scheme, complexity drops, unexpectedness, continuity hypothesis

Citation: Sears RE (2019) Commentary: Measuring Counterintuitiveness in Supernatural Agent Dream Imagery. Front. Psychol. 10:2855. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2019.02855

Received: 25 September 2019; Accepted: 03 December 2019;
Published: 20 December 2019.

Edited by:

Caroline L. Horton, Bishop Grosseteste University, United Kingdom

Reviewed by:

Roumen Kirov, Institute of Neurobiology (BAS), Bulgaria
Mark Blagrove, Swansea University, United Kingdom

Copyright © 2019 Sears. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Robert Eugene Sears, rsears777@gmail.com

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.