Skip to main content

PERSPECTIVE article

Front. Psychol., 22 July 2014
Sec. Cognitive Science
This article is part of the Research Topic From is to ought: The place of normative models in the study of human thought View all 24 articles

How (not) to draw philosophical implications from the cognitive nature of concepts: the case of intentionality

  • 1Brain Science Institute, Tamagawa University, Tokyo, Japan
  • 2Japan Society for the Promotion of Science, Tokyo, Japan
  • 3Department of Basic Science, Graduate School of Arts and Sciences, The University of Tokyo, Tokyo, Japan

Philosophers have often appealed to intuitive judgments in various thought experiments to support or reject particular theses. Experimental philosophy is an emerging discipline that examines the cognitive nature of such intuitive judgments. In this paper, we assess the methodological and epistemological status of experimental philosophy. We focus on the Knobe effect, in which our intuitive judgment of the intentionality of an action seems to depend on the perceived moral status of that action. The debate on the philosophical implications of the Knobe effect has been framed in terms of the distinction between the competence and performance of the concept of intentionality. Some scholars seem to suggest that the Knobe effect reflects the competence (or otherwise, the performance error) of the concept of intentionality. However, we argue that these notions are purely functional and thus do not have philosophical implications, without assuming normativism, which we see as problematic in a psychological methodology. Finally, focusing on the gap between competence and rationality, we suggest future directions for experimental philosophy.

Competence and Performance in Experimental Philosophy

Since the beginning of the 21st century, a new research program, “experimental philosophy,” which systematically studies the nature of intuition with psychological methodologies, has become increasingly popular (Knobe and Nichols, 2008a; Alexander, 2012; Knobe et al., 2012; Knobe and Nichols, 2013). In this paper, we consider why philosophical arguments are not informed by the identification of the cognitive natures of philosophical concepts. In what follows, while we mainly focus on the concept of intentionality, our arguments are generalizable to other concepts, such as that of free will.

In constructing or criticizing theories, philosophers have appealed to intuitive judgments in thought experiments, as seen in discussions of epistemology (Gettier, 1963), philosophy of mind (Searle, 1980; Chalmers, 1996), philosophy of language (Kripke, 1980), and so on. In doing so, philosophers have appealed to the fact that their intuitive judgments in thought experiments reflect their own theories. However, experimental philosophy has found that people’s intuitive judgments are affected by unexpected factors, beyond those conceived by philosophers.

One famous example is intuitive judgments on the intentionality of action (Knobe, 2003). Participants were presented with a story about a person working in a company. The story indicates that the person is working on a new business program and knows that its side effect will harm the environment. However, the person says that he does not care about this outcome and carries out the program, which leads to the bad side effect (“Harm” condition). Another version of the story is the same, except that the side effect of the program is good for the environment (“Help” condition). The participants read one of these stories and were asked whether the person has intentionally harmed (helped) the environment. Surprisingly, a strong asymmetry was found between the two conditions: most participants in the Harm condition responded that his action was intentional, while most in the Help condition replied that it was not intentional, despite the identical structure of the stories. Thus, people’s intuitive judgments on the intentionality of an action vary, according to the perceived harmfulness/helpfulness of the action. It seems that, generally speaking, we attribute intentionality to harmful or morally bad side effects. This tendency of attribution is called the “Knobe effect.”

The Knobe effect may reflect the concept of intentionality. Intentionality attribution, which is the crucial function of our “theory of mind” (ToM), is partly driven by moral cognition in nature and is thus the result of the appropriate application of the concept of intentionality. In this case, the concept of intentionality can be regarded as being constituted by moral cognition. However, the Knobe effect may reflect the inappropriate interference of moral cognition that is not constitutive of the concept of intentionality (Nadelhoffer, 2004, 2006). This question about the nature of the Knobe effect has often been framed in terms of competence and performance. The Knobe effect reflects the competence of the concept of intentionality (i.e., the core of ToM) or an error in the performance of it (Alexander, 2012).

The distinction between competence and performance originates in generative linguistics. Chomsky (1965, p. 3) argues that competence is linguistic knowledge that is possessed by an ideal speaker-listener in a language community. Because the actual linguistic performance is affected by a variety of constraints, such as memory capacities, attention controls, vocal functions, and so on, language competence is perfectly reflected in performance only in the idealization of these functions. This distinction has yielded noteworthy results by factoring out heterogeneous, confounding factors from the main target of linguistic theories (see discussion by Jackendoff, 2002).

There is an ongoing debate on how to characterize psychologically the relationships between competence and performance (Phillips, 2004; Marantz, 2005; Neeleman and van de Koot, 2010; Phillips and Lewis, 2013). Neeleman and van de Koot (2010) argue that competence and performance should be understood as theories of the same language system but at different descriptive levels. In this case, competence and performance would roughly correspond to different levels of analysis, i.e., the computational and algorithmic levels introduced by Marr (1982). However, we will not discuss this issue further in this paper, and we hereafter use the term competence/performance in Chomsky’s (1965) original sense, which seems to be dominant in the literature in experimental philosophy.

The distinction between competence and performance can be applied to concepts. The Knobe effect may reflect the competence of the concept of intentionality, such that moral cognition underlies the application of the concept. For example, Knobe (2006, p. 226) states that “moral considerations are playing a helpful role in people’s underlying competence itself.” Otherwise, the Knobe effect is a sort of performance error, where moral cognition distorts the application of the concept. Generally speaking, when a judgment involving a concept is affected by some psychological factor, it may reflect the competence of the concept, or it may be the result of error in its performance.

We can also pose this type of question in relation to many other studies. For instance, people’s intuitive judgments about free will have been examined, focusing on whether the concept of free will is compatible with determinism. Some scholars argue that the concept of free will is compatibilist, since the participants attribute free will to fictional characters in a deterministic world (Nahmias et al., 2005). However, other studies suggest that people’s judgments are sensitive to whether they are presented with abstract or concrete scenarios. People attribute free will in concrete scenarios much more than they do in abstract ones (Nichols and Knobe, 2007; cf. De Brigard et al., 2009; Mandelbaum and Ripley, 2012). Although this may be the case, an issue regarding the nature of the concept of free will remains to be resolved. Even if our attribution of free will is affected by the perception of concreteness, it is unclear whether such an effect reflects the competence of the concept of free will.

Interestingly, some scholars seem to suggest that the nature of people’s concepts has philosophical implications. When discussing how to interpret the Knobe effect, Adams and Steadman (2004, p. 173) mention the philosophical view that intentionality does not require intention, which the Knobe effect “may be taken to support.” In discussing free will, Nahmias et al. (2006, p. 30) maintain that “[b]ecause the free will debate is intimately connected to ordinary intuitions and beliefs via these values and practices, it is important that a philosophical theory of free will accounts for and accords with ordinary people’s understanding of the concept and their judgments about relevant cases.” In discussing the general background of experimental philosophy, Knobe and Nichols (2008b, p. 12) state, “[m]ore and more, philosophers are coming to feel that questions about how people ordinarily think have great philosophical significance in their own right.” Indeed, these scholars often seek to grasp the concepts of intentionality and free will in terms of competence/performance.

Here two questions arise. First, do experimental results, such as the Knobe effect, reflect the competence of the intentionality concept or a mere performance error? Second, how and why does such an understanding inform philosophical debates about intentionality? In what follows, we consider these two questions in turn.

Developmental and Disability Studies

Practices in linguistics may provide a clue in distinguishing between competence and performance. In linguistics, when competing theories possess identical explanatory powers, the possibility of language acquisition has been successfully used to constrain the range of theory (Chomsky, 1965; Yang, 2010). Moreover, agrammatism, which is a type of aphasia specific to syntactic processing, has been useful in clarifying domain-specific linguistic competence by dissociating domain-general components (Friedmann and Grodzinsky, 1997; Kinno et al., 2009). In a similar way, developmental and disability studies of the concept of intentionality may also help us to theorize the nature of the concept.

First, the cognitive nature of the concept of intentionality may be clarified by considering developmental studies of the Knobe effect. According to the experimental study of Leslie et al. (2006a), children as young as four showed the same tendency as adults. Moreover, the Knobe effect appeared as soon as the children learned to understand the concept of “do not care [bad side effects]” that was included in the experiment’s scenario. These results suggest that our innate concept of intentionality grows and fits with the Knobe effect. Segal (2008) argues, “it is difficult to believe that they learned it from observation of adult patterns of judgment, or that they inferred it from something else. It looks as though this is just how FP [folk psychology] grows” (ibid, p. 101). Thus, the Knobe effect is essentially associated with the concept of intentionality within ToM and reflects the competence of this concept.

Second, the cognitive nature of the concept of intentionality may be further clarified by considering people with autism spectrum disorder, who generally show some impairment in the ToM. On the autism spectrum, adults with Asperger’s syndrome or high-functioning autism (hereafter, AS/HFA) have no apparent disabilities in general intelligence and language and can generally pass a simple false-belief task, which is a simple test of the ToM. Moreover, with regard to basic moral perception, several studies have shown that there is no large difference between people on the autism spectrum and people with typical development (Blair, 1996; Grant et al., 2005; Leslie et al., 2006b). People with AS/HFA have difficulties, however, in understanding the mental states of others in complex situations and in passing higher level ToM tests, which involve sarcasm, irony, bravado, and the like. From these observations, it has been suggested that adults with AS/HFA use heuristics, which differ from the core of ToM, in order to understand the minds of others (Happé, 1995; Tager-Flusberg and Joseph, 2003). Thus, people with AS/HFA have impairments in the core of the ToM and use specific heuristics for the attribution of intentionality to complement these impairments, while their basic moral perceptions are normal.

A hypothesis regarding the Knobe effect in people with AS/HFA can be derived from these assumptions. If the Knobe effect reflects the competence of the concept of intentionality (i.e., the core of the ToM), we will not observe it in people with AS/HFA who have impairments in the core. Otherwise, if the Knobe effect is not a manifestation of the core of the ToM but is at best only a sign of heuristics in intentionality attribution, we will observe it in people with AS/HFA. In the light of the current empirical literature, the latter possibility is likely. A recent study of the Knobe effect in the autism spectrum group has revealed that even people with AS/HFA show the Knobe effect similarly to people with typical development (Zalla and Leboyer, 2011). Although further studies were needed, in this case, the Knobe effect would be regarded as a sign of heuristics in intentionality attribution and therefore irrelevant to the nature of the concept of intentionality.

As shown above, disability and developmental studies offer us a theoretical advance in understanding the nature of the Knobe effect. At the moment, there is conflicting evidence from such studies regarding whether the Knobe effect reflects competence.

Normativist Psychology and Experimental Philosophy

Here, we question the implications of the above findings. What are the philosophical implications of the fact that the Knobe effect reflects competence or performance error? One related philosophical problem is the relationship between intentionality and intention. While it seems that intention is required for an action to be intentional, some philosophers reject this conclusion (cf. Bratman, 1984; Adams, 1986). If the Knobe effect exactly reflects the competence of the intentionality concept, then the idea of disconnecting intentionality and intention may be supported, since intentionality could be attributed to the side effects of an action that were not intended (and such an attribution reflects the competence of the concept of intentionality). However, we would like to point out that an assumption is required for this philosophical implication.

The assumption is that the distinction between competence and performance error implies the distinction between the rationality and irrationality of concepts. Generally speaking, when a particular intuitive judgment cannot be regarded as rational, a philosophical argument based on this judgment is not justified, even if the intuitive judgment reflects the competence of the related concept. For example, when the Knobe effect does not reflect a rational thought, philosophical arguments on intentionality need not necessarily take the Knobe effect into account, even if the concept of intentionality is constituted by moral cognition. Here, we tentatively characterize the rationality of thought, including judgments and reasoning, as the disposition to produce true beliefs. This type of rationality, which has been regarded as essential in philosophical discussions, is called epistemic rationality, and it is distinct from other types of rationality, such as instrumental or ecological rationality. As long as our main concern is how we should think about the nature of intentionality, than we do think about it; there is no reason for philosophical theories to take into account whether the Knobe effect reflects competence, since it does not guarantee epistemic rationality.

Here, we can follow Elqayam and Evans (2011) in making a distinction between descriptivism and normativism in psychology. In general, normativist psychology directly relates competence and performance error to rational and irrational thought, respectively. By assuming particular norms, normativist psychology classifies thoughts as rational or irrational, depending on whether the nature of the thoughts accords with certain norms, and judges the distinction between the competence and performance error of the thoughts. Elqayam and Evans (2011) argue that psychology should follow linguistics, which adopts descriptivism and proposes a theory regarding the competence of language. In other words, psychology should dedicate itself to describe competence in accordance with descriptivism. They claim that psychology may distinguish competence and performance, but it should not engage in judging whether thoughts are rational or irrational. Otherwise, it draws ought from is, whose inference is generally unsupported.

In the same way, we want to point out that the distinction between competence and performance error has philosophical implications, only when we adopt normativism and assume the following norm: To be rational in the sense of being disposed to produce true beliefs, thoughts should reflect the competence of concepts. Indeed, if we assume this norm, we obtain the following consequence: If the Knobe effect reflects competence, it can be regarded as a rational judgment and thus should be considered in philosophical arguments. However, we suggest that how we ought to think about the nature of intentionality has to be distinguished from how typically developed people do think about it in everyday life.

Let us consider the above research on disabilities of the ToM where people with AS/HFA evince the Knobe effect. From this fact, we might infer that the Knobe effect reflects the heuristics but not the competence of the concept of intentionality (the core of the ToM). However, this view alone does not lead to the conclusion that the Knobe effect is not a rational judgment. In order to obtain such a conclusion, we must also assume that judgments in accordance with the functioning of the core can be regarded as rational. This assumption is a normative assertion regarding human thoughts. On what ground do thoughts based on the core have priority in terms of rationality? The fact that they were acquired in typical development cannot offer the reason, since the reason why typical development is directed to rational thought is questioned here. Whether the Knobe effect reflects competence is not directly relevant to truths about intentionality, since one cannot infer norms, at least in psychological facts, that make some judgments rational and others irrational.

Thus, we cannot draw philosophical implications without normativism, even while we can identify the cognitive concepts in terms of competence and performance. This requirement of normativism has not been explicated in the debates within experimental philosophy. While the importance of whether the Knobe effect reflects the competence of the concept of intentionality has often been suggested, the idea of competence/performance does not guarantee anything like (ir)rationality. Notice that this is also the case in linguistic studies, where the idea of competence is a kind of biological function, which implies nothing about epistemic rationality. This is true regardless of the general characterization of biological functions. Even if our moral cognition has some causal role in the application of the concept of intentionality or if the interaction between moral cognition and intentionality attribution is important for biological adaptation, it has nothing to do with how often we arrive at the truth about intentionality (cf. Stich, 1990). Therefore, we conclude that there is a large gap between the idea of competence, which is a kind of biological function, and (ir)rationality.

Conclusions

We suggest that it is empirically possible to determine whether the application of the concept of intentionality reflects its competence or error in performance. However, we point out that this fact about competence/performance does not imply anything positive about the nature of intentionality, contrary to the assumption made by some scholars in experimental philosophy. Drawing these implications from competence/performance requires a normativist psychology, which we think is a doubtful methodology. Thus, we have to bring something from outside psychology to bridge the gap between the competence/performance and (ir)rationality of concepts. For example, we might suggest that the concept of intentionality works for social interaction (cf. Knobe, 2006) and thus that socially admitted norms about its use should be reflected in any theory of intentionality. Otherwise, we might suggest a constitutive approach in general, which claims that our intuitions produce conceptual truth “by drawing on constructs such as reflective equilibrium and constitutive norms” (Evans and Elqayam, 2011, p. 283; cf. Thomasson, 2012). While we do not believe that experimental results do not inform philosophy, it seems better to explore something beyond the competence/performance of concepts. In any case, we have to be aware of the gap between how we should think and how we think about intentionality.

Conflict of Interest Statement

The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Acknowledgments

This paper is largely based on our previous work, Iijima and Ota (2014). We appreciate Frontiers in Psychology for publishing this paper and The Nagoya Journal of Philosophy for admitting it. This work was supported by a Grant-in-Aid for Japan Society for the Promotion of Science (JSPS) Fellows (26-11465) and the Suntory Foundation.

References

Adams, F. (1986). Intention and intentional action: the simple view. Mind Lang. 1, 281–301. doi: 10.1111/j.1468-0017.1986.tb00327.x

CrossRef Full Text

Adams, F., and Steadman, A. (2004). Intentional action in ordinary language: Core concept or pragmatic understanding? Analysis 64, 173–181. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-8284.2004.00480.x

CrossRef Full Text

Alexander, J. (2012). Experimental Philosophy: An Introduction. Malden: Polity.

Blair, R. J. R. (1996). Brief report: morality in the autistic child. J. Autism Dev. Disord. 26, 571–579. doi: 10.1007/BF02172277

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Bratman, M. (1984). Two faces of intention. Philos. Rev. 93, 375–405. doi: 10.2307/2184542

CrossRef Full Text

Chalmers, D. J. (1996). The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Chomsky, N. (1965). Aspects of the Theory of Syntax. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

De Brigard, F., Mandelbaum, E., and Ripley, D. (2009). Responsibility and the brain sciences. Ethical Theory Moral Pract. 12, 511–524. doi: 10.1007/s10677-008-9143-5

CrossRef Full Text

Elqayam, S., and Evans, J. St. B. T. (2011). Subtracting “ought” from “is”: descriptivism versus normativism in the study of human thinking. Behav. Brain Sci. 34, 233–248. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X1100001X

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Evans, J. St. B. T., and Elqayam, S. (2011). Towards a descripitivist psychology of reasoning and decision making. Behav. Brain Sci. 34, 275–290. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X11001440

CrossRef Full Text

Friedmann, N., and Grodzinsky, Y. (1997). Tense and agreement in agrammatic production: pruning the syntactic tree. Brain Lang. 56, 397–425. doi: 10.1006/brln.1997.1795

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Gettier, E. (1963). Is justified true belief knowledge? Analysis 23, 121–123. doi: 10.1093/analys/23.6.121

CrossRef Full Text

Grant, C. M., Boucher, J., Riggs, K. J., and Grayson, A. (2005). Moral understanding in children with autism. Autism 9, 317–331. doi: 10.1177/1362361305055418

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Happé, F. G. E. (1995). The role of age and verbal ability in the theory of mind task performance of subjects with autism. Child Dev. 66, 843–855. doi: 10.2307/1131954

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Iijima, K., and Ota, K. (2014). Competence and rationality: what does experimental philosophy have beyond psychological implications? [Japanese]. Nagoya J. Philos. 11, 39–61.

Jackendoff, R. (2002). Foundations of Language: Brain, Meaning, Grammar, Evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198270126.001.0001

CrossRef Full Text

Kinno, R., Muragaki, Y., Hori, T., Maruyama, T., Kawamura, M., and Sakai, K. L. (2009). Agrammatic comprehension caused by a glioma in the left frontal cortex. Brain Lang. 110, 71–80. doi: 10.1016/j.bandl.2009.05.001

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Knobe, J. (2003). Intentional action and side effects in ordinary language. Analysis 63, 190–194. doi: 10.1111/1467-8284.00419

CrossRef Full Text

Knobe, J. (2006). The concept of intentional action: a case study in the uses of folk psychology. Philos. Stud. 130, 203–231. doi: 10.1007/s11098-004-4510-0.

CrossRef Full Text

Knobe, J., Buckwalter, W., Nichols, S., Robbins, P., Sarkissian, H., and Sommers, T. (2012). Experimental philosophy. Annu. Rev. Psychol. 63, 81–99. doi: 10.1146/annurev-psych-120710-100350

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Knobe, J., and Nichols, S. (eds). (2008a). Experimental Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Knobe, J., and Nichols, S. (2008b). “An experimental philosophy manifesto,” in Experimental Philosophy, eds J. Knobe and S. Nichols (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 3–14.

Knobe, J., and Nichols, S. (eds). (2013). Experimental Philosophy: Vol. 2. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Kripke, S. A. (1980). Naming and Necessity. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Leslie, A. M., Knobe, J., and Cohen, A. (2006a). Acting intentionally and the side-effect effect: theory of mind and moral judgment. Psychol. Sci. 17, 421–427. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9280.2006.01722.x

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Leslie, A. M., Mallon, R., and Dicorcia, J. A. (2006b). Transgressors, victims, and cry babies: is basic moral judgment spared in autism? Soc. Neurosci. 1, 270–283. doi: 10.1080/17470910600992197

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Mandelbaum, E., and Ripley, D. (2012). Explaining the abstract/concrete paradoxes in moral psychology: the NBAR hypothesis. Rev. Philos. Psychol. 3, 351–368. doi: 10.1007/s13164-012-0106-3

CrossRef Full Text

Marantz, A. (2005). Generative linguistics within the cognitive neuroscience of language. Linguist. Rev. 22, 429–445. doi: 10.1515/tlir.2005.22.2-4.429

CrossRef Full Text

Marr, D. (1982). Vision: A Computational Investigation into the Human Representation and Processing of Visual Information. San Francisco: W. H. Freeman.

Nadelhoffer, T. (2004). On praise, side effects, and folk ascriptions of intentionality. J. Theor. Philos. Psychol. 24, 196–213. doi: 10.1037/h0091241

CrossRef Full Text

Nadelhoffer, T. (2006). Bad acts, blameworthy agents, and intentional actions: some problems for juror impartiality. Philos. Explor. 9, 203–219. doi: 10.1080/13869790600641905

CrossRef Full Text

Nahmias, E., Morris, S. G., Nadelhoffer, T., and Turner, J. (2005). Surveying freedom: folk intuitions about free will and moral responsibility. Philos. Psychol. 18, 561–584. doi: 10.1080/09515080500264180

CrossRef Full Text

Nahmias, E., Morris, S. G., Nadelhoffer, T., and Turner, J. (2006). Is incompatibilism intuitive? Philos. Phenomenol. Res. 73, 28–53. doi: 10.1111/j.1933-1592.2006.tb00603.x

CrossRef Full Text

Neeleman, A., and van de Koot, H. (2010). “Theoretical validity and psychological reality of the grammatical code,” in The Linguistics Enterprise: From Knowledge of Language to Knowledge in Linguistics, eds M. Everaert, T. Lentz, H. de Mulder, Ø. Nilsen, and A. Zondervan (Amsterdam: John Benjamins), 183–212.

Nichols, S., and Knobe, J. (2007). Moral responsibility and determinism: the cognitive science of folk intuitions. Noûs 41, 663–685. doi: 10.1111/j.1468-0068.2007.00666.x

CrossRef Full Text

Phillips, C. (2004). “Linguistics and linking problems,” in Developmental Language Disorders: From Phenotypes to Etiologies, eds M. Rice and S. Warren (Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates), 241–287.

Phillips, C., and Lewis, S. (2013). Derivational order in syntax: evidence and architectural consequences. Stud. Linguist. 6, 11–47.

Searle, J. R. (1980). Minds, brains, and programs. Behav. Brain Sci. 3, 417–424. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X00005756

CrossRef Full Text

Segal, G. (2008). “Poverty of stimulus arguments concerning language and folk psychology,” in The Innate Mind, Volume 3, Foundations and the Future, eds P. Carruthers, S. Laurence, and S. Stich (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 90–105.

Stich, S. (1990). The Fragmentation of Reason: Preface to a Pragmatic Theory of Cognitive Evaluation. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

Tager-Flusberg, H., and Joseph, R. M. (2003). Identifying neurocognitive phenotypes in autism. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B Biol. Sci. 358, 303–314. doi: 10.1098/rstb.2002.1198

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Thomasson, A. L. (2012). Experimental philosophy and the methods of ontology. Monist 95, 175–199. doi: 10.5840/monist201295211

CrossRef Full Text

Yang, C. D. (2010). Three factors in language variation. Lingua 120, 1160–1177. doi: 10.1016/j.lingua.2008.09.015

CrossRef Full Text

Zalla, T., and Leboyer, M. (2011). Judgment of intentionality and moral evaluation in individuals with high functioning autism. Rev. Philos. Psychol. 2, 681–698. doi: 10.1007/s13164-011-0048-1

CrossRef Full Text

Keywords: experimental philosophy, normativism, descriptivism, Knobe effect, intentionality, theory of mind

Citation: Iijima K and Ota K (2014) How (not) to draw philosophical implications from the cognitive nature of concepts: the case of intentionality. Front. Psychol. 5:799. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00799

Received: 28 February 2014; Accepted: 07 July 2014;
Published online: 22 July 2014.

Edited by:

Shira Elqayam, De Montfort University, UK

Reviewed by:

Maria Olkkonen, University of Pennsylvania, USA
Joshua Knobe, Yale University, USA

Copyright © 2014 Iijima and Ota. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) or licensor are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Kazuki Iijima, Brain Science Institute, Tamagawa University, 6-1-1 Tamagawa-Gakuen, Machida, Tokyo 194-8610, Japan e-mail: iijima.kazuki@14.alumni.u-tokyo.ac.jp

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.