Skip to main content

GENERAL COMMENTARY article

Front. Psychol., 02 March 2016
Sec. Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology

On the prospect of an experimental account of argumentation. Commentary: Toward an experimental account of argumentation: the case of the slippery slope and the ad hominem arguments

  • Division of Philosophy, Department of Humanities, University of the Philippines Los Baños, Los Baños, Philippines

A commentary on
Toward an experimental account of argumentation: the case of the slippery slope and the ad hominem arguments

by Lillo-Unglaube, M., Canales-Johnson, A., Navarrete, G., and Bravo, C. F. (2014). Front. Psychol. 5: 1420. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2014.01420

Lillo-Unglaube et al. (2014) argue for the employment of more descriptive and experimental accounts on the psychology of argumentation. By utilizing experimental studies concerning the slippery slope and ad hominem arguments using Bayesian (Hahn and Oaksford, 2007) and pragma-dialectic frameworks (Van Eemeren and Grootendorst, 2004), they seek to show how psychology can bring “the cognitive and normative accounts of argumentation closer” (Lillo-Unglaube et al., 2014, p. 5) for an integrated area of research on the psychology of argumentation.

Argumentation is a complex human activity. Its complexity stems from the fact that cognitive agents in various situations perform multiple tasks in real-time to assess an argument presented to them. These tasks involve the quantity, quality, and relevance of the statements that make up the argument. To illustrate, suppose cognitive agent A is presented with an argument for assessment. The quantity of statements included in the premise set has repercussions on what A can correctly infer (e.g., an argument with a single statement for a premise greatly reduces the number of inferential moves that A can make). It is also important for A to consider the quality of the statements included in the premise set (i.e., whether or not they are true). Finally, A must also consider the relevance of the statements included in the premise set to the conclusion of the argument (i.e., the premise set must be connected to the conclusion). As an additional complication, most of the time, cognitive agents are characterized by a condition of uncertainty. For example, all the relevant premises are oftentimes unavailable to cognitive agents, they are not always “in a position to know” (Sosa, 1995, p. 28), for instance, whether or not the premises of an argument are true.

Lillo-Unglaube et al.'s paper seeks to explain the “rhetorical effectiveness” of some of the informal fallacies. For Lillo-Unglaube et al., when cognitive agents are confronted with the slippery slope and ad hominem arguments, they evaluate “the persuasiveness of the slippery slope argument or the degree of unreasonableness of the ad hominem argument” (2014, p. 5).

It needs mentioning that Lillo-Unglaube et al.'s work benefited immensely from the works of Hahn and Oaksford (2007). For Hahn and Oaksford, the Bayesian approach helps explain how some informal fallacies can be reasonable inferential moves in some argumentation situations. Viewed in its proper context (i.e., that the inference involved in the slippery slope and ad hominem arguments is inductive), one can safely say that Hahn and Oaksford's analysis is concerned with argument strength which can be understood in terms of degrees unlike logical validity. This creates a potential problem for Lillo-Unglaube et al.'s proposal. Suppose cognitive agent A is persuading B that C will cheat in the upcoming final examinations on the basis that C cheated in their final examinations in the previous terms. To be sure, such an argument is persuasive or reasonable to hold. However, from the point of view of traditional normative approaches, there is a straightforward answer as to why A's argument is defective: its conclusion is not a logical consequence of the premise set. From the point of view of the experimental account by Lillo-Unglaube et al., however, the persuasiveness and the degree of reasonableness of A's conclusion would depend on the prior probabilities that we attach to the premise set. Mindful of the fact that these two approaches are different in the sense that the nature of the inferences involved are different (i.e., logical validity applies to deductive whereas argument strength applies to inductive arguments), one may ask as to how Lillo-Unglaube et al. can hope to bring these approaches closer together. If this is correct, then it is also unclear as to how Lillo-Unglaube et al. can maintain that the “psychology of argumentation provides an integrative scientific perspective unlike normative or aprioristic approaches” (2014, p. 5).

An option that is available for Lillo-Unglaube et al.'s proposal is to explain rhetorical effectiveness (e.g., persuasiveness, degree of unreasonableness) in relation to truth—a central epistemic concept that cognitive agents aim at (Corner and Hahn, 2013). This is in line with Hahn and Oaksford's (2006a) view that the Bayesian approach has considerable potential for advancing epistemic approaches to argumentation and evident in the very manner by which the Bayesian approach via probability theory provides explanations for the quality of arguments that cognitive agents encounter in real life (Hahn and Oaksford, 2006b; Corner et al., 2011; Hahn and Hornikx, 2015). As is well-known, the Bayesian approach interprets probabilities (which are measured in numbers from 0 to 1 where the probability of a necessary truth is 1) as “subjective degrees of belief” (Hahn and Oaksford, 2007, p. 707). Another advantage is that truth is a central notion to inference whether deductively or inductively. For example, it is truth that is supposedly preserved in deductively valid arguments (i.e., if the premise set is true, then the conclusion must be true). In addition, it is the truth of the conclusion in relation to the premise set that may vary in strength (e.g., weak, strong) in the case of inductive arguments. Finally, it can accommodate the lone reasoner by highlighting the idea that argumentation has an intrapersonal aspect evident in belief formation as well as belief change (Hahn and Hornikx, 2015). For instance, in deciding what to believe in, a cognitive agent interprets all the available evidences before her and then makes an inference. In the process, the cognitive agent may form beliefs that are epistemically responsible. A belief is epistemically responsible “if an agent holds those beliefs on the basis of good reasons, with the aim of attaining her epistemic goal. Both the reasons and the goal are evidently part of the agent's cognitive perspective” (Crumley, 2009, pp. 162–163).

In the end, if the goal is to have an integrated area of research on the psychology of argumentation, Lillo-Unglaube et al.'s proposal would benefit by including the notion of truth in explaining the rhetorical effectiveness of the slippery slope and ad hominem arguments in some contexts.

Author Contributions

The author confirms being the sole contributor of this work and approved it for publication.

Conflict of Interest Statement

The author declares that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Acknowledgments

The author would like to thank the associate editor and the reviewers for helpful comments on the previous version of this manuscript.

References

Corner, A., and Hahn, U. (2013). Normative theories of argumentation: are some norms better than others? Synthese 190, 3579–3610. doi: 10.1007/s11229-012-0211-y

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Corner, A., Hahn, U., and Oaksford, M. (2011). The psychological mechanism of the slippery slope argument. J. Mem. Lang. 64, 153–170. doi: 10.1016/j.jml.2010.10.002

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Crumley, J. II. (2009). An Introduction to Epistemology. Peterborough, ON: Broadview Press.

Google Scholar

Hahn, U., and Hornikx, J. (2015). A normative framework for argument quality: argumentation schemes with a Bayesian foundation. Synthese (Online first). doi: 10.1007/s11229-015-0815-0

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hahn, U., and Oaksford, M. (2006a). Why a normative theory of argument strength and why might one want it to be Bayesian? Informal Logic 26, 1–24.

Google Scholar

Hahn, U., and Oaksford, M. (2006b). A Bayesian approach to informal argument fallacies. Synthese 152, 207–236. doi: 10.1007/s11229-005-5233-2

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hahn, U., and Oaksford, M. (2007). The rationality of informal argumentation: a Bayesian approach to reasoning fallacies. Psychol. Rev. 114, 704–772. doi: 10.1037/0033-295X.114.3.704

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Lillo-Unglaube, M., Canales-Johnson, A., Navarrete, G., and Bravo, C. F. (2014). Toward an experimental account of argumentation: the case of the slippery slope and the ad hominem arguments. Front. Psychol. 5:1420. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2014.01420

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Sosa, E. (1995). Knowledge in Perspective: Selected Essays in Epistemology. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.

Google Scholar

Van Eemeren, F. H., and Grootendorst, R. (2004). A Systematic Theory of Argumentation: The Pragma-Dialectical Approach, Vol. 14. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.

Google Scholar

Keywords: argumentation theory, epistemic aspects of argumentation, logic, persuasion, reasoning

Citation: Boongaling JIK (2016) On the prospect of an experimental account of argumentation. Commentary: Toward an experimental account of argumentation: the case of the slippery slope and the ad hominem arguments. Front. Psychol. 7:299. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2016.00299

Received: 29 August 2015; Accepted: 16 February 2016;
Published: 02 March 2016.

Edited by:

Richard Stöckle-Schobel, Ruhr-University Bochum, Germany

Reviewed by:

Ulrike Hahn, Birkbeck College, University of London, UK
Carlos Zednik, University of Magdeburg, Germany

Copyright © 2016 Boongaling. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) or licensor are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: John Ian K. Boongaling, johnianboongaling@gmail.com; jkboongaling@up.edu.ph

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.