Skip to main content

GENERAL COMMENTARY article

Front. Psychol., 05 September 2017
Sec. Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology

Commentary: Integrative Modeling and the Role of Neural Constraints

  • Department of Analytic Philosophy, Institute of Philosophy (ASCR), Prague, Czechia

A commentary on
Integrative Modeling and the Role of Neural Constraints

by Weiskopf, D. A. (2016). Philos. Sci. 83, 674–685. doi: 10.1086/687854

Daniel Weiskopf has recently argued that the mechanistic integration of cognitive and mechanistic models can't help resolve the potential conflicts between these two types of models (Weiskopf, 2016). I will show that his argument rests on a mistaken picture of mechanistic integration.

In cognitive science, the “Many-Models Problem” (Weiskopf, 2016) arises when one believes in three incompatible propositions: that a cognitive and a neurocognitive model are both true of a target system, that they are made true by the way the world is and that they ascribe incompatible properties to this system. According to the received view, cognitive explanations are functional (Cummins, 1985). To explain our having a given capacity, one puts forward a model representing a system constituted of distinct mechanisms—functionally characterized, i.e., by the role they play in the system—causally related to one another. For example, Donald Broadbent explained the selectivity of attention by hypothesizing that a filter operated a selection on the input in order to reduce the quantity of information transmitted upstream so that it could be transmitted through a limited capacity channel (Broadbent, 1958). A cognitive model is accurate to the extent that it predicts the data produced by subjects in experimental contexts. There is therefore no guarantee that the structure ascribed to the target system will match the one ascribed by a neurocognitive model. Sometimes, a Many-Model problem may arise.

How can mechanistic integration help? Mechanisms are sets of entities and their activities organized in such a way that they produce, underlie, or maintain a phenomenon (Craver and Darden, 2013). To explain a phenomenon mechanistically one puts forward a model representing a system constituted of distinct mechanisms structurally characterized (Craver, 2007). For example, to explain the rat's capacity for spatial memory, researchers have put forward a hierarchical model bottoming out in the phenomenon of Long Term Potentiation (a long-lasting strengthening of a synapse) of the neurons of the dentate gyrus of the rat's hippocampus, and a mechanism underlying this phenomenon in which Ca2+ ions in the post-synaptic neuron play a key role (Granger and Nicoll, 2014). A cognitive and a neurocognitive model are mechanistically integrated when the mechanisms functionally characterized by the former are identical to the mechanisms structurally characterized by the later and when the former is a sketch of the later (Piccinini and Craver, 2011). In this situation, the two models do not ascribe incompatible properties to the same system.

Weiskopf thinks that in many cases such an integration is not forthcoming. In this situation, applying a neural plausibility constraint to cognitive models is misguided. A mechanistic integration has two steps: the development of the cognitive and the neurocognitive model; the mapping of the functional characterizations to the structural characterizations (the “localization” step). Here is in a nutshell Weiskopf's argument. First, “if localization is successful, cognitive functions will end up being assigned to distinct spatially and structurally well-defined components of the brain,” that is, a one-to-one mapping is a necessary condition for localization. Second, recent evidence from systems neuroscience in which brain functions—i.e., cognitive functions—are to be understood in terms of whole networks, shows that some brain regions are multifunctional. To start with, anatomically disjoint brain regions can contribute “processing to partially anatomically disjoint structural networks” and “support different modes of processing within one and the same anatomical network.” Moreover, “extrinsic modulations of regional functions [are] commonplace.” Third, it follows that localization will fail in many cases. Consequently, in many cases, mechanistic integration will fail. I won't discuss Weiskopf's neuroscientific evidence (Anderson, 2010; Sporns, 2010). Instead, I will argue that mechanists are not, by being mechanists, committed to this view of localization. Weiskopf doesn't provide any textual evidence that mechanists subscribe to it but, in any case, this would be an additional commitment on their part.

I will first note that Weiskopf's second step wrongly assumes that mechanists have to say that the brain regions to be mapped are anatomical brain regions (“dentate gyrus of the hippocampus,” “inferotemporal cortex”). Mechanists traffic in entities, their activities, and the organization thereof: there is no reason why the entities of the higher-level couldn't be those of systems neuroscience (networks) instead of those of anatomy. This reply won't do, however, as Weiskopf could reformulate his argument in terms of networks: the evidence he provides does show that networks are multifunctional. Mechanists, however, are not committed to the view of localization Weiskopf starts with. It is open to them to say that the same entity (here, a network) performs distinct functions, as long as they explain these functions by invoking the distinct activities of this entity's parts and their organization. There being extrinsic modulations of regional functions doesn't add anything to the argument. This amounts to saying that for the mapping to be possible, a modulator will have to be part of the cognitive model. But there might be good psychological evidence for this.

Weiskopf gives two arguments in favor of a one-to-one mapping being a necessary condition for localization. First, if two or more brain regions performing distinct functions overlap, these functions are not always independently modifiable. This casts doubt on the reality of distinct cognitive mechanisms performing these distinct functions. However, Weiskopf assumes once more that the brain regions to be mapped are anatomical brain regions. We would need to be shown evidence that networks overlap. Second, reverse inference—the inference from brain activity to psychological states—should be possible. But, according to the mechanistic view, were future brain imaging techniques to give us a window on the activities of parts of the brain and their interactions then neuroscientists would have the data on which to base reverse inferences. And this may very well happen.

Weiskopf calls for humility in applying constraints such as neural plausibility. I don't know whether mechanists lack humility. But, their work should, hopefully, help give cognitive neuroscience its proper place inside the cognitive sciences.

Author Contributions

The author confirms being the sole contributor of this work and approved it for publication.

Conflict of Interest Statement

The author declares that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Acknowledgments

The author wishes to thank both referees for their helpful comments on this paper.

References

Anderson, M. L. (2010). Neural reuse: a fundamental organizational principle of the brain. Behav. Brain Sci. 33:245. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X10000853

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Broadbent, D. E. (1958). Perception and Communication. London, UK: Pergamon Press.

Google Scholar

Craver, C. F. (2007). Explaining the Brain: Mechanisms and the Mosaic Unity of Neuroscience. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press; Clarendon Press.

Craver, C. F., and Darden, L. (2013). In Search of Mechanisms: Discoveries across the Life Sciences. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

Google Scholar

Cummins, R. (1985). The Nature of Psychological Explanation. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Google Scholar

Granger, A. J., and Nicoll, R. A. (2014). Expression mechanisms underlying long-term potentiation: a postsynaptic view, 10 years on. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. B Biol. Sci. 369:20130136. doi: 10.1098/rstb.2013.0136

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Piccinini, G., and Craver, C. (2011). Integrating psychology and neuroscience: functional analyses as mechanism sketches. Synthese 183, 283–311. doi: 10.1007/s11229-011-9898-4

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Sporns, O. (2010). Networks of the Brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Google Scholar

Weiskopf, D. A. (2016). Integrative modeling and the role of neural constraints. Philos. Sci. 83, 674–685. doi: 10.1086/687854

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Keywords: mechanistic explanation, functional analysis, mechanistic integration, reverse inference, neural plasticity, neural networks

Citation: Bantegnie B (2017) Commentary: Integrative Modeling and the Role of Neural Constraints. Front. Psychol. 8:1531. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2017.01531

Received: 18 June 2017; Accepted: 23 August 2017;
Published: 05 September 2017.

Edited by:

Tuomas K. Pernu, King's College London, United Kingdom

Reviewed by:

Raoul Gervais, University of Antwerp, Belgium
Carlos Zednik, Otto von Guericke University of Magdeburg, Germany

Copyright © 2017 Bantegnie. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) or licensor are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Brice Bantegnie, bricebantegnie@gmail.com

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.