Skip to main content

CORRECTION article

Front. Psychol., 27 November 2018
Sec. Cognitive Science

Corrigendum: Is There a Conjunction Fallacy in Legal Probabilistic Decision Making?

  • 1Department of Clinical and Forensic Psychology, Institute of Psychology, University of Silesia of Katowice, Katowice, Poland
  • 2Department of Psychology, City, University of London, London, United Kingdom

A Corrigendum on
Is There a Conjunction Fallacy in Legal Probabilistic Making?

by Wojciechowski, B. W., and Pothos, E. M. (2018). Front. Psychol. 9:391. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2018.00391

In the original article, there was an error.

In the Discussion section, a small error was made in one of the quantum computations, which requires minor adjustment of the discussion. None of the empirical results, analyses, and other conclusions are affected.

A correction has been made to Discussion, paragraph 7. The original sentence was: For a double CF, we have: Prob(A), Prob(B)>Prob(A&B), that is a CF occurs for both conjuncts. This has been corrected to: For a double CF, we have: Prob(A), Prob(B) < Prob(A&B), that is a CF occurs for both conjuncts.

A correction has been made to Discussion, paragraph 8. The original sentence was: For the participants with no legal background, we have a situation where Prob(A), Prob(B)>Prob(A&B), for when evaluating criminal cases for which the suspect was guilty for both crimes. This has been corrected to: For the participants with no legal background, we have a situation where Prob(A), Prob(B) < Prob(A&B), for when evaluating criminal cases for which the suspect was guilty for both crimes.

A correction has been made to Discussion, paragraph 10. The original sentences were: The observed results require an initial representation for the mental space in a tensor product structure as above, but also a thought process which “mixes” thoughts and beliefs between the two crimes (Pothos and Busemeyer, 2009; Broekaert et al., 2017). It is not our purpose presently to outline in detail a full cognitive model for the consideration of criminal cases and we focus on the technical elements of QPT that allow for coverage of the results (for more relevant details see e.g., Pothos and Busemeyer, 2009; Trueblood and Busemeyer, 2011; Pothos et al., 2013; Wang et al., 2013; Narens, 2014). This has been corrected to: The observed results motivate the consideration of an initial representation for the mental space in a tensor product structure as above, but also a thought process which “mixes” thoughts and beliefs between the two crimes (Pothos and Busemeyer, 2009; Broekaert et al., 2017). It is not our purpose presently to outline in detail a full cognitive model for the consideration of criminal cases and we focus on the technical elements of QPT potentially relevant for coverage of the results (for more relevant details see Pothos and Busemeyer, 2009; Trueblood and Busemeyer, 2011; Pothos et al., 2013; Wang et al., 2013; Narens, 2014).

A correction has been made to Discussion, paragraph 11, |a−c|2 has been replaced by |a|2+|c|2, and |ab|2 has been replaced by |a|2+|b|2. A sentence has also been added, the corrected paragraph appears below.

Prob(Crime1yes;ψ)=PCrime1yes I·U·ψ2                                      =  ​|(1000010000000000)· ​(1000001001000001) ​· ​(abcd) ​|2=|a|2+|c|2
                  Prob(Crime2yes;ψ)=|I PCrime2yes·U·ψ|2=|a|2+|b|2 Prob(Crime1yes&Crime2yes;ψ)=|a|2

Recall that a mental state vector in QPT is normalized, therefore |a|2+|b|2+|c|2+|d|2 = 1. But it should be clear that this scheme still cannot accommodate a CF, which illustrates that only certain space structures can produce a single CF (e.g., as in Pothos and Busemeyer, 2009) and it is unclear whether a double CF is possible at all.

A correction has been made the Discussion, paragraph 12. A sentence was added, the corrected paragraphs appear below.

Overall, the present results revealed a double CF, for lay (regarding legal knowledge) individuals, but not for participants with more advanced levels of legal knowledge/experience with legal proceedings. As an empirical finding, this constitutes a salutary message regarding the ability of humans to embody rational decision making, in situations where there is a high expectation for such decision making. The double CF presents a challenge for decision models specifically developed to account for the CF and related fallacies. We focussed on one model, based on QPT. So far, QPT theory for the CF has been applied to the single CF, which is by far the most common finding. Modeling of the single CF with QPT involves incompatible questions, which lead to a psychological explanation based on how one question alters our perspective for the other. Regarding the double CF, we have outlined one possibility based on QPT, corresponding to compatible questions, and a “mixing” thought process; our outline was intended to simply show indicative calculations, noting that for a single CF only particular space structures will work.

Psychologically this corresponds to a consideration of the two questions in a way that thoughts making each one individually more likely interfere with each other in the conjunctive case to produce probabilities inconsistent with CPT.

The authors apologize for this error and state that this does not change the scientific conclusions of the article in any way. The original article has been updated.

Conflict of Interest Statement

The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

References

Broekaert, J., Basieva, I., Blasiak, P., and Pothos, E. M. (2017). Quantum-like dynamics applied to cognition: a consideration of available options. Proc. R. Soc A 375:20160387. doi: 10.1098/rsta.2016.0387

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Narens, L (2014). Alternative Probability theories for cognitive psychology. Top. Cogn. Sci, 6, 114–120. doi: 10.1111/tops.12071

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pothos, E. M., and Busemeyer, J. R. (2009). A quantum probability explanation for violations of “rational” decision theory. Proc. R. Soc. B Biol. Sci. 276, 2171–2178. doi: 10.1098/rspb.2009.0121

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pothos, E. M., Shiffrin, R. M., and Busemeyer, J. R. (2013). The dynamics of decision making when probabilities are vaguely specified. J. Math. Psychol. 59, 6–17. doi: 10.1016/j.jmp.2013.09.001

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Trueblood, J. S., and Busemeyer, J. R. (2011). A quantum probability model of casual reasoning. Front. Cogn. Sci. 3:138. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2012.00138

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Wang, Z., Busemeyer, J. R., Atmanspacher, H., and Pothos, E. M. (2013). The potential of using quantum theory to build models of cognition. Top. Cogn. Sci. 5, 672–688. doi: 10.1111/tops.12043

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Keywords: conjunction fallacy, legal decision making, quantum cognition, quantum probability theory, legal psychology

Citation: Wojciechowski BW and Pothos EM (2018) Corrigendum: Is There a Conjunction Fallacy in Legal Probabilistic Decision Making? Front. Psychol. 9:2281. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2018.02281

Received: 25 October 2018; Accepted: 01 November 2018;
Published: 27 November 2018.

Edited and reviewed by: Eldad Yechiam, Technion – Israel Institute of Technology, Israel

Copyright © 2018 Wojciechowski and Pothos. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Bartosz W. Wojciechowski, bartosz.wojciechowski@us.edu.pl

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.