Skip to main content

PERSPECTIVE article

Front. Psychol., 21 December 2023
Sec. Neuropsychology
This article is part of the Research Topic Law and Neuroscience: Justice as a Challenge for Neurorights, Neurolaw, and Forensic Psychology View all 14 articles

Neuromodulation and memory: exploring ethical ramifications in memory modification treatment via implantable neurotechnologies

  • School of Law, The University of Edinburgh, Edinburgh, United Kingdom

Invasive implantable neurotechnologies capable of simultaneously altering and recording neural activity are no longer the exclusive province of science fiction but a looming reality that will revolutionize medical practice. These advancements, particularly in their memory-altering capabilities, herald a vast array of opportunities for addressing the complex landscape of neurodegenerative and psychiatric conditions linked to memory impairments. However, the panoply of ethical implications arising from such a novel neurotechnology remains relatively unexplored by the neuroethics literature. This study examines and contrasts the potential ethical implications of memory modification treatment via implantable neurotechnologies. The study contends that undesired side effects resulting from memory modulation can lead to significant identity harms, disrupting the coherence of self-narratives and impinging on our authenticity. To evince the practical impact of this moral argument, the study conducts a practical ethical assessment of how employing implantable neurotechnologies to modulate memory may jeopardize (i) our moral responsiveness to events and core system of values and (ii) the emotional component associated with the altered memory. From a first-person standpoint, changes to the way we reasonably feel and react to past events and future intentions may be deemed ethically problematic as these profound changes can yield significant moral disruptions and negatively impact our personal lives and interpersonal relationships. In addition, the study discusses further ethical conundrums from a third-person perspective as these disruptions can inhibit social activism against structural injustices, thereby hindering societal progress. Thus, taking into account this societal dimension is paramount when evaluating the ethical permissibility of memory modification procedures.

1 Introduction

Implantable neurotechnologies and cutting-edge developments in the field of memory neuromodulation present new promising avenues for treating severe cognitive and neurological impairments. However, the panoply of ethical implications arising from such a novel invasive neuromodulatory context remains relatively unexplored by the neuroethics literature. The central aim of this study is to explore, highlight, and contrast the potential ethical implications of employing implantable neurotechnologies for memory modification.

This study argues that side effects arising from memory modification treatment (“MMT”) can entail significant identity harm by disrupting the coherence of our self-narratives and impinging our authenticity. To evince the practical impact of such a moral argument, the study contends that employing modulating memory may alter our moral and emotional responsiveness and the core value system. This study argues that changes to how we reasonably feel and react to past events and future intentions are ethically problematic as they can yield significant moral disruptions. The study discusses that such disruption also entails further ethical conundrums, from a third-person perspective, as it can generate a problematic collateral effect: rendering systemic change more difficult to attain. The study introduces a hypothetical case study to illustrate these issues and analyzes these potential moral harms, through a narrative lens, to personal identity. Such a perspective sheds light on ethical issues that have not been fully explored in previous identity theories and highlights the significance of the social context. The study concludes that the societal dimension must be taken into consideration when assessing the ethical permissibility of MMT.

2 Current debate

Drawing from the neuroethics literature on memory modification (understood as the technique of altering neural networks underlying memory), the scholarship has primarily focused on addressing ethical issues stemming from non-invasive techniques that have rendered limited success, such as transcranial magnetic stimulation or pharmacological interventions such as propranolol, chiefly due to their lack of spatial resolution and susceptibility to noise in comparison to implanted electrodes (Carter et al., 2011; Kraemer, 2013; Hui and Fisher, 2015; Racine and Affleck, 2016; Gilbert et al., 2017, 2021a; Siegel et al., 2017; Zuk et al., 2018; Cutsuridis, 2019; Klein et al., 2022). However, recent developments in the field of cognitive neuroscience pave a new horizon of neural stimulation possibilities through novel forms of memory modulation such as optogenetics, molecular modification, and implantable neural interfaces, which may overcome current limitations in non-invasive alternatives by offering higher focality and reaching deeper brain areas (Hui and Fisher, 2015; Erler, 2021; Soekadar et al., 2023). These groundbreaking prospects hold promise for patients with memory dysfunctions as they may allow us to therapeutically intervene in unprecedented ways that cannot be achieved with non-invasive means.

Among the novel memory-modifying technologies, invasive brain–computer interfaces (“iBCIs”) that target site-specific neurons through direct contact with neuronal tissue can manipulate neural circuits at high temporal and spatial resolution through, for example, ‘electrical neuromodulation’––a stimulation mechanism of electrical neural signaling––for, in this case, altering memory (Kozai et al., 2014; Ponce, 2014; Glannon, 2017; Opris, 2017; Gulino et al., 2019). For instance, a distinguishing feature of iBCIs is the possibility of selectively deactivating or dampening the emotional impact of undesired memories by inhibiting selected groups of neurons (Kolber, 2008; Han et al., 2009; Adamczyk and Zawadzki, 2020; Costanzi et al., 2021; Mihailov et al., 2021). Such a prospect of intentionally controlling our forgetting by modulating the stabilization process of a memory trace could erase the sting of bad memories or lessen their emotional intensity at will (Huff et al., 2013; Adamczyk and Zawadzki, 2020; Blitz and Barfield, 2023; Zawadzki, 2023).

Remarkably, ample empirical findings support this theoretical proposal. For instance, research conducted in rodent models and non-human primates has proven effective in deactivating well-consolidated memories and reducing the emotional intensity (or valence) of specific episodes (Kindt et al., 2009; Goshen et al., 2011; Lavazza, 2018; El-Shamayleh and Horwitz, 2019; Adamczyk and Zawadzki, 2020; Mihailov et al., 2021; Li et al., 2022). It should be emphasized that this prospect of advanced memory modulation in humans remains theoretical, primarily due to the ongoing experimental and clinical status of iBCIs.

In contrast to non-invasive alternatives, iBCIs pose more intricate ethical dilemmas, owing to their capacity to exploit advanced degrees of memory modification related to deliberate and selective alterations (Zawadzki, 2023), distinguishing them from other memory-modifying technologies, such as deep-brain stimulation and drugs, which lack temporal precision and operate non-selectively (van Duuren et al., 2007; Bazaka and Jacob, 2013; Trimper et al., 2018; Howell and McIntyre, 2021; Riva et al., 2021).

In such respect, Gilbert et al. (2021b) identified potential ethical risks with memory modification in human subjects. For example, there is a reasonable risk that these interventions may result in undesired and unforeseeable side effects when targeting memory formation. Notable empirical studies indicate that targeted interference of well-consolidated memories can induce abrupt neural circuit changes, including weakening the emotional component of a memory held for the subject (Redondo et al., 2014). Given memory’s associative nature, selective memory modification poses a risk of adversely altering untargeted memory chains in similar domains, causing unwanted emotional and behavioral changes (Ramirez et al., 2013; Hui and Fisher, 2015; Hu et al., 2018).

While there is a prevailing concern that neuromodulation technologies could be employed to modify fundamental human value (Aplin and Fridman, 2019; Goering et al., 2021), the ethical aftermaths arising from unforeseen side effects remain relatively unexplored from a practical perspective that considers both potential individual and societal ramifications. As the memory-modifying potential at stake is latent (Won et al., 2020; Mihailov et al., 2021; Meyer and Benoit, 2022), it calls for ethical attention in order to safeguard a responsible development without hindering their promising therapeutic potential (Zawadzki and Adamczyk, 2021a,b). To illustrate these points, the study will now introduce a hypothetical case study.

3 Case study

For years, Claude grappled with a haunting memory of a traumatic childhood event and developed PTSD. This traumatic episode drove him to embark on a philanthropic career path, culminating in his founding of a local fund dedicated to aiding abuse victims. After consulting with his medical team, Claude learned that an iBCI could treat his PTSD by “erasing” specific memories. He underwent the MMT in an attempt to alleviate the persistent emotional distress associated with his trauma. The procedure was deemed successful, relieving him of the psychological burden. However, in the aftermath of the procedure, Claude began to experience a profound shift in his sense of self. The philanthropic career he had pursued with unwavering commitment was suddenly seen through a different lens as the dedication-driving memory was now absent. He began contemplating leaving his local job to explore more lucrative opportunities.

4 Correlation between memories and self-narratives

As memory plays a building block in one’s self-narrative (Lavallee et al., 2019; Blagov et al., 2022), neuroethics research suggests that altering memories could prompt a range of psychological disruptions that may impinge upon an agent’s narrative identity (Sutin and Stockdale, 2011; Singer et al., 2013; Gilbert and Viaña, 2018). The ‘first-personal aspects of memories,’ as acknowledged by Schechtman (2011), are paramount for the process of narrative construction as they shape who we are, which in turn dictates how we are more likely to feel, act, and react toward future events. Lavazza (2019) sustains such a dyad by accentuating the intrinsic parallel memories have as part of the construction of personal identity. Thus, accessing, reflecting upon, and interpreting our memories aids our narratives to become a progressive acquisition of purpose and meaning. Through such a recalling and evaluative process, we contextualize and justify the impact our embodied experiences have had on our past and set patterns for future intentions (Postan, 2021; Leuenberger, 2021a). This brief examination regarding the entangled nexus between our memories and self-narratives will now serve to begin discussing why abrupt changes brought about by MMT are ethically alarming.

5 Practical ethical issues from altering memories

5.1 Altering moral and emotional responsiveness: first-person concerns

A current collective concern highlighted in recent neuroethics debates is the risk that the incipient memory-modifying potential of iBCIs may be used to distort emotions or absolve emotions such as blame or guilt (Forooshani et al., 2021). These changes call for ethical scrutiny as they could cause a significant shift in an agent’s core value system. Touching upon the relationship between memory and emotional response is critical for understanding these ethical issues.

Empirical evidence theorizes that specific inhibitory networks of neurons may be responsible for the intentional forgetting of memories (Ten Oever et al., 2021). Therefore, it is plausible that these networks could be key in dampening emotional responsiveness and, consequently, behavioral habituation (Barron et al., 2017; Koolschijn et al., 2019). In simple terms, modulating memory could make individuals feel and react differently than they otherwise would as their emotional responses to stimuli associated with the altered memory become distorted. As Glannon (2010) contends, memory plays a fundamental role in personal identity and moral sensibility due to the emotions it generates. As moral agents, individuals are guided by their moral emotions, and memory serves as a vital component in shaping these emotions (Liao and Sandberg, 2008; Lavazza, 2015). However, altering memory, as seen in the case of Claude, may inadvertently erode a significant portion of an individual’s moral and emotional sensitivity, potentially detaching them from their capacity to feel and respond to their own moral emotions (Erler, 2011). This complex interplay between memory and emotion inexorably raises questions of moral responsibility as, for example, the degree of ethical permissibility may vary between that of a victim or the perpetrator of a horrific act even if the act generated PTSD for both individuals (De Marco, 2019).

Neuromodulation of unpleasant memories resulting in a subsequent loss of our moral or emotional responsiveness could yield serious repercussions that will likely impair us from assessing ‘moral reasons for or against’ avenues of action as feeling our emotions contributes to such a counterfactual capacity of reasoning (Strawson, 1962; Rafetseder and Perner, 2012; Wilkinson et al., 2015; Glannon, 2019). For example, recalling Claude’s case, in which the original memory motivated his career to become philanthropic, it could be argued that his MMT prompted a radical emotional change that led him to disassociate his feeling of fulfillment toward his professional career. Let us examine why such an abrupt change is ethically troublesome.

Prior to the MMT, Claude’s self-characteristics developed in hand with his identity-constituting narrative, in which the memory in question held a building block. His self-narrative was coherent in light of his intelligible self-characteristics as Claude could provide an evaluative interpretation regarding what made him pursue philanthropy. Moreover, it could be claimed that prior to the procedure, Claude’s core value system was normative as per his identity as it constituted sufficient reasons for action (Mackenzie and Walker, 2015). Furthermore, Claude was exercising his autonomy as he was taking an active role in authoring his narrative identity––his career could be considered an authentic project of self-creation arising from his coherent self-narrative.

However, as a result of the MMT, Claude cannot provide evaluative judgment as to why he desired to support his local community. The side effects from the procedure directly impinge upon Claude’s self-narrative as the latter will now contain a significant inconsistency that will translate into a partial loss of identity (Dings and Newen, 2021). In other words, the treatment decreased Claude’s narrative coherence, and his sudden change in career could not be considered an authentic project of self-creation as such a choice would not be grounded in his long-standing values. Claude would not be able to make immediate practical sense of who he is, at least in his professional sphere. In Mackenzie and Walker’s (2015) terminology, Claude would not be able to make psychological and evaluative sense of himself: he would likely experience a degree of self-alienation—a likely scenario suggested in the literature (Leuenberger, 2021a,b)—as to why he is closing his charity and suddenly finds himself applying to more lucrative, non-local jobs. Though there could be external deposits of memory, such as diaries or social media publications, that could potentially help Claude weave together aspects of his narrative, if Claude is still unable to make practical sense of a crucial part of himself, this could be considered significant identity harm as such inability is breaching ‘the most basic of the capacities underpinned by coherent self-narratives’ as sustained by Postan (2022).

Claude’s case has both similarities and differences when compared to instances of the ‘burden of normality’ syndrome (“BoN”), particularly in cases where individuals with Parkinson’s disease decide to shift careers following motor improvement. A prominent similarity is that both generate an impact on the individual’s identity (Gilbert, 2012). However, the catalyst of Claude’s career change was the selective erasure of a specific memory, which led to a reevaluation of his core values. In contrast, BoN resulting in a career shift is a consequence of regaining physical abilities rather than a direct consequence of memory alteration. BoN is often perceived as a restoration of previous capabilities before the onset of the condition––authenticity is maintained, and a career shift is a result of returning to a more familiar state.

On the other hand, MMT directly involves altering an individual’s emotional experiences––a more profound change in the realm of personal identity because it directly affects the way a person perceives and interacts with their past experiences and values. Even though memory is extended and socially constructed (Hunt, 2013), it is closely tied to one’s sense of self and moral sensibility; thus, its alteration can be regarded as a more fundamental interference than regaining physical abilities.

In addition, Claude’s identity harm also entails further repercussions from a third-person perspective. For instance, his abrupt lack of career commitment could be perceived as selfish by others as Claude’s colleagues would not comprehend his sudden decision to close the organization that he dedicated decades of effort to building. Additionally, the change could also bear repercussions on his family life; for example, Claude’s wife would not understand why he wants to move countries and might not be able to carry on a long-distance marriage. This scenario evinces the potential negative consequences of altering memory, particularly the significant harm to our personal lives and interpersonal relationships.

Claude’s case is contentious as some may argue that if he intentionally altered his memory, his decision could be considered a narrative development that he autonomously constructed (Wiley et al., 1998; Rocha, 2014). However, as put forward by Tan and Lim (2020), a forceful alteration of one’s self-narrative can also be inherently self-deceiving. In such a line of argument, Claude’s choice of memory editing could not be considered authentic as it would not exhibit a sufficient degree of intelligibility as per his pre-existing narrative (Libby et al., 2011).

5.2 Altering the emotional component of memories: social considerations

The possibility of emotional blunting brings the discussion to a larger issue that calls for ethical scrutiny in its own right. This section will examine how MMT can entail an ethically problematic collateral effect: rendering systemic change more difficult to attain. The aim of this section is two-fold. First, it is argued that societal considerations can multiply the conflicting moral views regarding whether MMT is ethically justified. Second, ethical implications stemming from MMT shall be examined in relation to concerns on an individual level and amalgamated with potential societal issues as narratives are inescapably socially embedded.

It is relevant to note that the ethical implications of MMT are contingent on distinguishing between particular memory erasure and emotional blunting. While Claude’s case primarily involved the erasure of a specific traumatic memory, MMT can encompass various forms of memory modulation, including preventing the formation of new traumatic memories and limiting the ability to recall past experiences. Thus, the implications arising from MMT depend on the specific nature of the intervention. Erasing traumatic episodes raises concerns related to authenticity and potential identity harm. In contrast, emotional blunting or preventing the formation of new traumatic memories also carries distinct ethical concerns, potentially reducing empathy and hindering an individual’s capacity to relate to the experiences of victims of trauma, impeding advocacy for social change.

The emotional component of our memories (particularly traumatic episodes) plays a crucial role in one’s narrative construction process as it constitutes an aggregate factor for providing explanatory justification for our lived experiences. However, such a component is also crucial for instituting social change. Tenenbaum and Reese (2007) sustain the latter by arguing that memories provide a foundation for systemic changes. Moreover, Gensburger (2020) contends that shared traumatic memories of, for example, violence are relevant in order to collectively aim to pacify societies, combat racial bias, and lessen discrimination rates.

In such respect, the President’s Council on Bioethics (Beyond Therapy, 2003) has argued that memories provide us with invaluable information that aids us in re-evaluating our social institutions. In virtue of this, social movements such as #MeToo or #BlackLivesMatter have demonstrated that intersubjective, collective types of traumas serve as an emotional stimulus and encourage individuals to fight systemic issues that they have experienced, such as racism, violence, or sexual abuse.

As echoed by multiple scholars (Barry et al., 2020; Forooshani et al., 2021), the capacity to feel the emotions associated with particular memories is a paramount driver for fostering social change; striving for social change demands––in Nezu et al. (2021) terminology––a cognitive openness to negative emotions. Thus, it is rational to assert that the emotional component in question serves to advocate for systemic change by acting as a catalyst for fighting social injustices. Translating this argument into our neuromodulatory context, dampening memories can also entail a significant risk of making us unable to decolonize existing systemic issues as feeling the emotions correlating to our memories is crucial for achieving the former.

Hence, from a third-person standpoint, blunting memories’ emotional component carries an added ethical dilemma as such alteration can generate significant barriers to attaining justice. Let us illustrate the practical ethical impact of this contention by recalling Claude’s case. The act of closing his charity would not only constitute an inauthentic choice, but one that would hinder social change as, for example, the foundation may have played a pivotal role in tackling inequalities by providing support to abuse victims and promoting educational developments within Claude’s local community. In such a case, closing the charity would impinge upon Claude’s social context by ceasing the advocacy for valuable social change and reducing the efforts to lessen the inequities that the foundation was tackling. With this reasoning, if our ability and willingness to strive for social change––a reasonable emotional reaction after experiencing trauma––is disrupted due to MMT, then it can be argued that such a procedure could lessen our advocacy for valuable justice. Claude’s case highlights the complexity and impact between our narratives and the social world.

6 The moral divergence between individual values and societal interests

In circumstances when a memory entails psychophysical distress that severely deteriorates one’s quality of life, moral disagreements regarding the risks and benefits of MMT would undoubtedly arise. Some might argue that it could be in an agent’s best interests to modulate a traumatic episode albeit the latter might constitute a relevant building block of their identity that could lead the individual to live an inauthentic life and lose a fragment of his narrative (Liao and Sandberg, 2008). For example, a degree of identity harm may be ethically permissible on the grounds of wellbeing or a transient effect of inauthenticity might be subjectively worth the alleviation from severe mental disorders (Kostick-Quenet and Lázaro-Muñoz, 2021; Kostick-Quenet et al., 2022). However, granting ethical priority to certain values over others would not be imperative in these scenarios but would be contingent on a case-by-case basis. Certainly, the moral exercise of balancing risks and benefits will constitute a complex task due to entangled societal concerns. Thus, it is imperative to take these elements into consideration and disclose them as necessary prior to these medical procedures being undertaken. Indubitably, moral tension will subsist due to the range of moral discrepancies that these novel procedures will generate.

7 Conclusion

While this debate cannot be settled here, it is pragmatic to sift out and highlight the array of plausible moral divergences that would originate when ethically justifying MMT. As shown, the moral landscape surrounding memory modulation is multifaceted. Potential disruptions to values should not be the sole determinant to exclude the use of neuromodulatory technologies but rather complement the informed, decision-making process by systematically allowing individuals to better understand, acknowledge, and balance the diverse impacts on their personal and relational sphere associated with erasure, emotional blunting, or other forms of memory modulation. Within the frontier of neurotechnology regulation, the ongoing discourse on neurorights initiatives, advocating personal identity as a human right, can offer a valuable framework for addressing the ethical considerations of neuromodulatory technologies that may disrupt an individual’s sense of self.

Data availability statement

The original contributions presented in the study are included in the article/supplementary material, further inquiries can be directed to the corresponding author.

Author contributions

CG-M: Writing – original draft, Writing – review & editing.

Funding

The author(s) declare that no financial support was received for the research, authorship, and/or publication of this article.

Acknowledgments

The author wishes to express gratitude to the journal’s reviewers and editor for their insightful input and constructive feedback, which significantly improved the quality of the study. Special appreciation is extended to an external reviewer whose meticulous proofreading of the revised version and provision of technical insights in neuroscience greatly contributed to the refinement of this work.

Conflict of interest

The author declares that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Publisher’s note

All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article, or claim that may be made by its manufacturer, is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.

References

Adamczyk, A. K., and Zawadzki, P. (2020). The memory-modifying potential of Optogenetics and the need for Neuroethics. NanoEthics 14, 207–225. doi: 10.1007/s11569-020-00377-1

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Aplin, F. P., and Fridman, G. Y. (2019). Implantable direct current neural modulation: theory, feasibility, and efficacy. Front. Neurosci. 13, 9–14. doi: 10.3389/fnins.2019.00379

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Barron, H. C., Vogels, T. P., Behrens, T. E., and Ramaswami, M. (2017). Inhibitory engrams in perception and memory. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. 114, 6666–6674. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1701812114

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Barry, T. J., Hallford, D. J., Del Rey, F., and Ricarte, J. J. (2020). Differential associations between impaired autobiographical memory recall and future thinking in people with and without schizophrenia. Br. J. Clin. Psychol. 59, 154–168. doi: 10.1111/bjc.12236

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bazaka, K., and Jacob, M. V. (2013). Implantable devices: issues and challenges. Electronics 2, 1–34. doi: 10.3390/electronics2010001

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Beyond Therapy. Biotechnology and the pursuit of happiness: A report of the President’s council on bioethics, chapter 6, ‘beyond Terapy: General reflections’. (2003). Washington, D.C. Available at: https://biotech.law.lsu.edu/research/pbc/reports/beyondtherapy/chapter6.html.

Google Scholar

Blagov, P. S., Singer, J. A., Oost, K. M., and Goodman, J. A. (2022). Self-defining memories—narrative features in relation to adaptive and maladaptive personality traits (replication and extension of Blagov & Singer, 2004). J. Pers. 90, 457–475. doi: 10.1111/jopy.12677

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Blitz, M. J., and Barfield, W. (2023). “Memory enhancement and brain–computer Interface devices: technological possibilities and constitutional challenges” in Policy, identity, and Neurotechnology: The Neuroethics of brain-computer interfaces. eds. V. Dubljević and A. Coin (Cham: Springer International Publishing), 207–231.

Google Scholar

Carter, A., Ambermoon, P., and Hall, W. D. (2011). Drug-induced impulse control disorders: a prospectus for Neuroethical analysis. Neuroethics 4, 91–102. doi: 10.1007/s12152-010-9071-7

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Costanzi, M., Cianfanelli, B., Santirocchi, A., Lasaponara, S., Spataro, P., Rossi-Arnaud, C., et al. (2021). Forgetting unwanted memories: active forgetting and implications for the development of psychological disorders. J. Personalized Med. 11:241. doi: 10.3390/jpm11040241

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Cutsuridis, V. (2019). Memory prosthesis: is it time for a deep Neuromimetic computing approach? Front. Neurosci. 13:667. doi: 10.3389/fnins.2019.00667

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Dings, R., and Newen, A. (2021). Constructing the past: the relevance of the narrative self in modulating episodic memory. Rev. Philos. Psychol. 14, 87–112. doi: 10.1007/s13164-021-00581-2

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

El-Shamayleh, Y., and Horwitz, G. D. (2019). Primate Optogenetics: Progress and prognosis. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. 116, 26195–26203. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1902284116

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Erler, A. (2011). Does memory modification threaten our authenticity? Neuroethics 4, 235–249. doi: 10.1007/s12152-010-9090-4

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Erler, A. (2021). Optogenetic memory modification and the many facets of authenticity. AJOB Neurosci. 12, 40–42. doi: 10.1080/21507740.2020.1866108

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Forooshani, S. A., Murray, K., Khawaja, N., and Izadikhah, Z. (2021). Identifying the links between trauma and social adjustment: implications for more effective psychotherapy with traumatized youth. Front. Psychol. 12, 1–2. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2021.666807

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gensburger, Sarah. (2020). ‘Can the past change the future? A Sociological Reflection about What Memory Public Policies Actually Do’. The European Observatory on Memories (EUROM), 2020. Available at: https://europeanmemories.net/magazine/can-the-past-change-the-future-a-sociological-reflection-about-what-memory-public-policies-actually-do/.

Google Scholar

Gilbert, F. (2012). ‘The Burden of Normality: From “Chronically Ill” to “Symptom Free”. New Ethical Challenges for Deep Brain Stimulation Postoperative Treatment’. Journal of Medical Ethics 38: 408–12. doi: 10.1136/medethics-2011-100044

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gilbert, F., Goddard, E., John, N. M., Viaña, A. C., and Horne, M. (2017). I miss being me: phenomenological effects of deep brain stimulation. AJOB Neurosci. 8, 96–109. doi: 10.1080/21507740.2017.1320319

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gilbert, F., Harris, A. R., and Kidd, M. (2021a). Burnt in your memory or burnt memory? Ethical issues with Optogenetics for memory modification. AJOB Neurosci. 12, 22–24. doi: 10.1080/21507740.2020.1866104

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gilbert, F., and Viaña, J. N. (2018). ‘A Personal Narrative on Living and Dealing with Psychiatric Symptoms after DBS Surgery’. Narrative Inquiry in Bioethics 8: 67–77.

Google Scholar

Gilbert, F., Viaña, J. N. M., and Ineichen, C. (2021b). Deflating the “DBS causes personality changes” bubble. Neuroethics 14, 1–17. doi: 10.1007/s12152-018-9373-8

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Glannon, W. (2017). Brain implants to erase memories. Front. Neurosci. 11, 1–3. doi: 10.3389/fnins.2017.00584

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Glannon, Walter. (2010). Chapter 11, ‘the Neuroethics of memory’. In The Memory process: Neuroscientific and humanistic perspectives. Available at: https://academic.oup.com/mit-press-scholarship-online/book/19044/chapter/177444597.

Google Scholar

Glannon, Walter. (2019). The Neuroethics of memory: from total recall to oblivion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. i–ii.

Google Scholar

Goering, S., Klein, E., Specker Sullivan, L., Wexler, A., Agüera y Arcas, B., Bi, G., et al. (2021). Recommendations for responsible development and application of Neurotechnologies. Neuroethics 14, 365–386. doi: 10.1007/s12152-021-09468-6

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Goshen, I., Brodsky, M., Prakash, R., Wallace, J., Gradinaru, V., Ramakrishnan, C., et al. (2011). Dynamics of retrieval strategies for remote memories. Cells 147, 678–689. doi: 10.1016/j.cell.2011.09.033

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gulino, M., Kim, D., Pané, S., Santos, S. D., and Pêgo, A. P. (2019). Tissue response to neural implants: the use of model systems toward new design solutions of implantable microelectrodes. Front. Neurosci. 13, 1–2. doi: 10.3389/fnins.2019.00689

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Han, J.-H., Kushner, S. A., Yiu, A. P., Hsiang, H.-L. (L.)., Buch, T., Waisman, A., et al. (2009). Selective erasure of a fear memory. Science 323, 1492–1496. doi: 10.1126/science.1164139

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Howell, B., and McIntyre, C. C. (2021). ‘Feasibility of Interferential and Pulsed Transcranial Electrical Stimulation for Neuromodulation at the Human Scale’. Neuromodulation 24: 843–53. doi: 10.1111/ner.13137

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Huff, M. L., Miller, R. L., Deisseroth, K., Moorman, D. E., and LaLumiere, R. T. (2013). Posttraining Optogenetic manipulations of basolateral amygdala activity modulate consolidation of inhibitory avoidance memory in rats. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. 110, 3597–3602. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1219593110

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hui, K., and Fisher, C. E. (2015). The ethics of molecular memory modification. J. Med. Ethics 41, 515–520. doi: 10.1136/medethics-2013-101891

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hu, J., Wang, W., Homan, P., Wang, P., Zheng, X., and Schiller, D. (2018). Reminder duration determines threat memory modification in humans. Sci. Rep. 8:8848. doi: 10.1038/s41598-018-27252-0

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hunt, N. (2013). “Chapter 4, ‘memory and social meaning: the impact of society and culture on traumatic memories’” in Hurting memories and beneficial forgetting. eds. M. Linden and K. Rutkowski (Oxford: Elsevier), 49–57.

Google Scholar

Kindt, M., Soeter, M., and Vervliet, B. (2009). Beyond extinction: erasing human fear responses and preventing the return of fear. Nat. Neurosci. 12, 256–258. doi: 10.1038/nn.2271

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Klein, E., Kinsella, M., Stevens, I., and Fried-Oken, M. (2022). Ethical issues raised by incorporating personalized language models into brain-computer Interface communication technologies: a qualitative study of individuals with neurological disease. Disabil. Rehabil. Assist. Technol., 17, 1–11. doi: 10.1080/17483107.2022.2146217

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kolber, A. (2008). Freedom of memory today. Neuroethics 1, 145–148. doi: 10.1007/s12152-008-9011-y

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Koolschijn, R. S., Emir, U. E., Pantelides, A. C., Nili, H., Behrens, T. E. J., and Barron, H. C. (2019). The Hippocampus and neocortical inhibitory engrams protect against memory interference. Neuron 101, 528–541.e6. doi: 10.1016/j.neuron.2018.11.042

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kostick-Quenet, K., Kalwani, L., Koenig, B., Torgerson, L., Sanchez, C., Munoz, K., et al. (2022). Researchers’ ethical concerns about using adaptive deep brain stimulation for enhancement. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 16:813922. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2022.813922

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kostick-Quenet, K., and Lázaro-Muñoz, G. (2021). Neural safeguards against global impacts of memory modification on identity: ethical and practical considerations. AJOB Neurosci. 12, 45–48. doi: 10.1080/21507740.2020.1866111

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kozai, T. D. Y., Jaquins-Gerstl, A. S., Vazquez, A. L., Michael, A. C., and Tracy Cui, X. (2014). Brain tissue responses to neural implants impact signal sensitivity and intervention strategies. ACS Chem. Neurosci. 6, 48–67. doi: 10.1021/cn500256e

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kraemer, F. (2013). Me, myself and my brain implant: deep brain stimulation raises questions of personal authenticity and alienation. Neuroethics 6, 483–497. doi: 10.1007/s12152-011-9115-7

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Lavallee, A., Saloppé, X., Gandolphe, M.-C., Ott, L., Pham, T., and Nandrino, J.-L. (2019). What effort is required in retrieving self-defining memories? Specific autonomic responses for integrative and non-integrative memories. PLoS One 14:e0226009. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0226009

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Lavazza, A. (2015). Erasing traumatic memories: when context and social interests can outweigh personal autonomy. Philos. Ethics Humanit. Med. 10:3. doi: 10.1186/s13010-014-0021-6

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Lavazza, A. (2018). Memory-modulation: self-improvement or self-depletion? Front. Psychol. 9:469. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2018.00469

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Lavazza, A. (2019). Moral bioenhancement through memory-editing: a risk for identity and authenticity? Topoi 38, 15–27. doi: 10.1007/s11245-017-9465-9

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Leuenberger, M. (2021a). Why authenticity hinges on narrative identity. AJOB Neurosci. 12, 43–45. doi: 10.1080/21507740.2020.1866109

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Leuenberger, M. (2021b). Losing meaning: philosophical reflections on neural interventions and their influence on narrative identity. Neuroethics 14, 491–505. doi: 10.1007/s12152-021-09469-5

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Leuenberger, M. (2022). Memory modification and authenticity: a narrative approach. Neuroethics 15:10. doi: 10.1007/s12152-022-09489-9

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Liao, S. M., and Sandberg, A. (2008). The normativity of memory modification. Neuroethics 1, 85–99. doi: 10.1007/s12152-008-9009-5

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Libby, L. K., Valenti, G., Pfent, A., and Eibach, R. P. (2011). Seeing failure in your life: imagery perspective determines whether self-esteem shapes reactions to recalled and imagined failure. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 101, 1157–1173. doi: 10.1037/a0026105

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Li, H., Namburi, P., Olson, J. M., Borio, M., Lemieux, M. E., Beyeler, A., et al. (2022). Neurotensin orchestrates valence assignment in the amygdala. Nature 608, 586–592. doi: 10.1038/s41586-022-04964-y

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Mackenzie, C., and Walker, M. (2015). “Neurotechnologies, personal identity, and the ethics of authenticity” in Handbook of Neuroethics. eds. J. Clausen and N. Levy (Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands), 373–392.

Google Scholar

Marco, GabrielDe. (2019). ‘Brain interventions, moral responsibility, and control over One’s mental life’. Neuroethics 12: 221–229. doi: 10.1007/s12152-019-09414-7

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Meyer, A.-K., and Benoit, R. G. (2022). Suppression weakens unwanted memories via a sustained reduction of neural reactivation. elife 11:e71309. doi: 10.7554/eLife.71309

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Mihailov, E., Zorila, A., and Iftode, C. (2021). Taking relational authenticity seriously: Neurotechnologies, narrative identity, and co-authorship of the self. AJOB Neurosci. 12, 35–37. doi: 10.1080/21507740.2020.1866105

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Nezu, Arthur M., Nezu, Christine Maguth, and D’Zurilla, Thomas J.. (2021). Problem-solving Therapy. New York: Springer Publishing Company.

Google Scholar

Oever, SanneTen, Sack, Alexander T., Oehrn, Carina R., and Axmacher, Nikolai. (2021). ‘An engram of intentionally forgotten information’. Nat. Commun. 12::6443. doi: 10.1038/s41467-021-26713-x

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Opris, I. (2017). “Electrical stimulation for modification of memory and cognition” in Electroceuticals: Advances in electrostimulation therapies. ed. A. Majid (Cham: Springer International Publishing), 283–316.

Google Scholar

Ponce, F. A. (2014). “Electrostimulation” in Encyclopedia of the neurological sciences. eds. M. J. Aminoff and R. B. Daroff. Second ed (Oxford: Academic Press), 1110–1111.

Google Scholar

Postan, E. (2022). “Chapter 3, ‘narrative self-constitution’” in In embodied narratives: Protecting identity interests through ethical governance of bioinformation, G. Laurie and R. Ashcroft eds. 61–88 (Cambridge Bioethics and Law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)

Google Scholar

Postan, E. (2021). Narrative devices: Neurotechnologies, information, and self-constitution. Neuroethics eds. L. Graeme and A. Richard. 14, 231–251. doi: 10.1007/s12152-020-09449-1

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Racine, E., and Affleck, W. (2016). Changing memories: between ethics and speculation. AMA J. Ethics 18, 1241–1248. doi: 10.1001/journalofethics.2016.18.12.sect1-1612

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Rafetseder, E., and Perner, J. (2012). When the alternative would have been better: counterfactual reasoning and the emergence of regret. Cognit. Emot. 26, 800–819. doi: 10.1080/02699931.2011.619744

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ramirez, S., Liu, X., Lin, P.-A., Suh, J., Pignatelli, M., Redondo, R. L., et al. (2013). Creating a false memory in the Hippocampus. Science 341, 387–391. doi: 10.1126/science.1239073

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Redondo, R. L., Kim, J., Arons, A. L., Steve Ramirez, X. L., and Tonegawa, S. (2014). Bidirectional switch of the valence associated with a hippocampal contextual memory engram. Nature 513, 426–430. doi: 10.1038/nature13725

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Riva, E. R., and Micera, S. (2021). Progress and challenges of implantable neural interfaces based on nature-derived materials. Bioelectronic Medicine 7:6. doi: 10.1186/s42234-021-00067-7

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Rocha, A. C. D. (2014). Narrative autonomy: three literary models of healthcare in the end of life. Camb. Q. Healthc. Ethics 23, 200–208. doi: 10.1017/S096318011300073X

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Schechtman, M. (2011). Memory and identity. Philos. Stud. 153, 65–79. doi: 10.1007/s11098-010-9645-6

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Siegel, A. M., Barrett, M. S., and Bhati, M. T. (2017). Deep brain stimulation for Alzheimer’s disease: ethical challenges for clinical research. J. Alzheimers Dis. 56, 429–439. doi: 10.3233/JAD-160356

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Singer, J. A., Blagov, P., Berry, M., and Oost, K. M. (2013). Self-defining memories, scripts, and the life story: narrative identity in personality and psychotherapy. J. Pers. 81, 569–582. doi: 10.1111/jopy.12005

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Soekadar, S. R., Vermehren, M., Colucci, A., Haslacher, D., Bublitz, C., Marcello, I., et al. (2023). Future Developments in Brain/Neural–Computer Interface Technology’. In Policy, Identity, and Neurotechnology: The Neuroethics of Brain-Computer Interfaces, edited by Veljko Dubljević and Allen Coin, Advances in Neuroethics. Cham: Springer International Publishing. 65–85.

Google Scholar

Strawson, Peter F. (1962). Freedom and resentment. Vol. 48. Methuen: Proceedings of the British Academy, pp. 187–211.

Google Scholar

Sutin, A. R., and Stockdale, G. D. (2011). Trait dissociation and the subjective affective, motivational, and phenomenological experience of self-defining memories. J. Pers. 79, 939–964. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-6494.2010.00708.x

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Tan, S. Z., and Lim, L. W. (2020). A practical approach to the ethical use of memory modulating technologies. BMC Med. Ethics 21:89. doi: 10.1186/s12910-020-00532-z

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Tenenbaum, E. M., and Reese, B. (2007). Memory-altering drugs: shifting the paradigm of informed consent. Am. J. Bioeth. 7, 40–42. doi: 10.1080/15265160701518649

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Trimper, John B., and Colgin, Laura Lee. (2018). ‘Spike Time Synchrony in the Absence of Continuous Oscillations’. Neuron 100: 527–29. doi: 10.1016/j.neuron.2018.10.036

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

van Duuren, E., Nieto, Francisco A., Escámez, Ruud N. J. M. A., Joosten, Rein Visser, Mulder, Antonius B., and Pennartz, Cyriel M. A. (2007). ‘Neural Coding of Reward Magnitude in the Orbitofrontal Cortex of the Rat during a Five-Odor Olfactory Discrimination Task’. Learning & Memory 14: 446–56. doi: 10.1101/lm.546207

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Wiley, A. R., Rose, A. J., Burger, L. K., and Miller, P. J. (1998). Constructing autonomous selves through narrative practices: a comparative study of working-class and middle-class families. Child Dev. 69, 833–847. doi: 10.2307/1132207

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Wilkinson, M. R., Ball, L. J., and Alford, D. (2015). Counterfactual reasoning for regretted situations involving controllable versus uncontrollable events: the modulating role of contingent self-esteem. Adv. Cogn. Psychol. 11, 22–30. doi: 10.5709/acp-0168-4

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Won, S. M., Song, E., Reeder, J. T., and Rogers, J. A. (2020). Emerging modalities and implantable Technologies for Neuromodulation. Cells 181, 115–135. doi: 10.1016/j.cell.2020.02.054

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Zawadzki, P. (2023). The ethics of memory modification: personal narratives, relational selves and autonomy. Neuroethics 16:6. doi: 10.1007/s12152-022-09512-z

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Zawadzki, P., and Adamczyk, A. K. (2021a). To remember, or not to remember? Potential impact of memory modification on narrative identity, personal agency, mental health, and well-being. Bioethics 35, 891–899. doi: 10.1111/bioe.12926

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Zawadzki, P., and Adamczyk, A. K. (2021b). Personality and authenticity in light of the memory-modifying potential of Optogenetics. AJOB Neurosci. 12, 3–21. doi: 10.1080/21507740.2020.1866097

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Zuk, P., Torgerson, L., Sierra-Mercado, D., and Lázaro-Muñoz, G. (2018). Neuroethics of neuromodulation: an update. Current Opinion in Biomedical Engineering, Neural Engineering/ Novel Biomed. Technol.: Neuromodulation 8, 45–50. doi: 10.1016/j.cobme.2018.10.003

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Keywords: neuroethics, brain-computer interfaces, memory, neuromodulation, neurotechnology, justice, neuroscience

Citation: González-Márquez C (2023) Neuromodulation and memory: exploring ethical ramifications in memory modification treatment via implantable neurotechnologies. Front. Psychol. 14:1282634. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2023.1282634

Received: 24 August 2023; Accepted: 17 November 2023;
Published: 21 December 2023.

Edited by:

Eric García-López, Instituto Nacional de Ciencias Penales, Mexico

Reviewed by:

John Noel Montaño Viaña, Australian National University, Australia
Jesse Rissman, University of California, Los Angeles, United States
José M. Muñoz, University of California, Berkeley, United States

Copyright © 2023 González-Márquez. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Claudia González-Márquez, c.gonzalezmarquez@ed.ac.uk

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.