HYPOTHESIS AND THEORY article

Front. Psychol., 25 April 2025

Sec. Evolutionary Psychology

Volume 16 - 2025 | https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2025.1570049

The modular mind and psychiatry: toward clinical integration with a focus on self-disorders


Gheorghe Ilie
Gheorghe Ilie*Adrian V. JaeggiAdrian V. Jaeggi
  • Institute of Evolutionary Medicine, University of Zurich, Zurich, Switzerland

One of the foundational tenets of evolutionary psychology, the modular view of the mind, offers promising applications for clinical psychiatry. This perspective conceptualizes the mind as a collection of specialized information-processing modules, shaped by natural selection to address adaptive challenges faced by our ancestors. In this paper, we propose several points of integration between the modularity framework and clinical psychiatric practice. First, we argue that the descriptive psychopathology of self-disorders provides evidence supporting the modular view, demonstrating how a dysfunctional minimal self may expose the mind's modular architecture to conscious awareness. Next, we will explore how the modular perspective can illuminate the nature of intrapsychic conflicts. Finally, we will discuss how evidence from neuropsychiatric syndromes supports the modular view of the mind and, in turn, how this perspective can provide a basis for classifying mental disorders.

1 Introduction

In this paper, we explore how the modular view of the mind informs our understanding of neuropsychiatric disorders and, in turn, how these disorders provide empirical support for modularity in the mind. Although the intersection of modularity and psychiatry was elegantly explored by Zielasek and Gaebel (2008, 2009)—laying important groundwork for applying this framework to psychiatric conditions—our approach diverges by centering on ego-pathology, a group of disorders characterized by disruptions in the sense of self. We begin by defining modularity—first in biological terms more broadly (Section 2), and then in cognition more specifically (Section 3). Our discussion focuses on Jerry Fodor's classical concept of modularity in cognition, examining why many of his criteria are unlikely to define a biologically informed modular mind based on current evidence and outlining contemporary views on modularity in evolutionary psychology. Section 4 reinforces this point, cautioning against oversimplified models of cognition. In the following three sections we present the core of our argument. In Section 5 we introduce the concept of self-disorders from classical psychopathology, recognizing both their historical significance and their validity in contemporary research. We then argue that in self-disorders, the modular architecture of the mind is revealed to conscious awareness when the sense of self fails. Using the concept of semantic tagging and the prerequisites of a minimal self, we outline the neurophenomenological link between information processing and the subjective manifestations of self-disorders. At the same time, we theorize how information may be handled by a modular mind in the context of self-disorders, a perspective not previously explored. In Section 6, we present empirical evidence supporting modularity in self-disorders and in Section 7 we propose methods for testing the claims outlined in Section 5. Section 8 then explores information encapsulation in the context of intrapsychic conflict. Finally, Section 9 broadens the scope by demonstrating how evidence from dissociation studies supports a modular architecture of the mind and how, in turn, the modular framework may serve as a valuable organizing principle for classifying neuropsychiatric diseases.

In presenting our arguments, we integrate modularity with elements of embodied cognition and network neuroscience, emphasizing that modularity complements rather than supersedes these perspectives. Modularity can strengthen network-based frameworks (Alcalá-Corona et al., 2021), as we highlight in the context of self-disorders in Section 6. It also explains how distinct neuropsychological functions can be selectively impaired while others remain intact. In contrast, a network perspective shows that disease mechanisms rarely affect a single module in isolation. Instead, disease progression follows network topology, spreading from specific functional modules through hub regions—highly connected nodes within a network—ultimately leading to widespread dysfunction (Seeley et al., 2009; Pievani et al., 2014; Fornito et al., 2015). Embodied cognition integrates with modularity, particularly in bodily ownership disruptions in self-disorders and in melancholic depression, as explored in Section 5. Furthermore, modular decomposition plays a key role in understanding pathophysiology, as identifying disease modules—clusters of functionally related, co-dysregulated genes (Lucchetta and Pellegrini, 2020)—can reveal new disease-associated pathways in various conditions, including temporal lobe epilepsy (Moreira-Filho et al., 2015), pancreatic cancer (Long et al., 2016), and coronary artery disease (Liu et al., 2016). Recognizing the modular architecture of disease can thus advance targeted therapy, while network approaches can identify vulnerable hubs (e.g., in neurodegeneration) and guide early interventions to slow disease progression (Zhou et al., 2012). Thus, modularity, embodied cognition, and network neuroscience—each operating at distinct yet complementary levels of analysis—together provide a more comprehensive framework for understanding cognitive function and dysfunction.

2 Modularity as a general concept

Modularity holds different meanings across disciplines (Zelditch and Goswami, 2021). However, in its widest scope, it refers to interacting, functionally specialized, and semi-independent units—a concept ubiquitous across the biological world at multiple scales (Hartwell et al., 1999; Huitzil and Huepe, 2024). Biological systems are decomposable into such discrete functional units, spanning levels from the molecular to the ecosystemic (Huitzil and Huepe, 2024). At the molecular level, examples include cell cycle protein complexes (John et al., 2001) and gene regulatory networks (Davidson and Erwin, 2006; Wellik, 2007). At the cellular level, metabolic networks (Jeong et al., 2000; Ravasz et al., 2002) and cellular interaction networks (Barabasi and Oltvai, 2004; Qi and Ge, 2006) provide additional instances. This principle extends to higher levels of organization, such as tissues, organs, and even ecosystems (Solé and Montoya, 2001; Montoya et al., 2006). Modularity enables systems to repurpose and recombine existing components, fostering innovation and adaptability in response to environmental shifts. It also helps contain disruptions, allowing subsystems to evolve independently while improving both the efficiency of information processing and system-wide integration. Furthermore, by structuring simple elements into more complex arrangements, modularity facilitates the emergence of new functions and supports specialization within complex systems (Huitzil and Huepe, 2024).

Within modules, elements are more interconnected with each other than with neighboring modules (Cheverud, 1996; Wagner, 1996; Hartwell et al., 1999; Von Dassow and Munro, 1999; Debat et al., 2000; Newman, 2006; Klingenberg, 2008). This principle also applies to brain organization, where clusters of neurons exhibit dense intramodular connectivity and relatively sparse connections to neighboring modules (Sporns et al., 2004, 2005; Meunier et al., 2010; Gazzaniga, 2018; Gazzaniga et al., 2019). Functional specialization is their hallmark (Passingham et al., 2002; Bullmore and Sporns, 2012; Petersen and Sporns, 2015) as evidenced by their consistent activation during specific tasks (Kanwisher, 2010), such as the fusiform face area being reliably activated during face perception tasks (Kanwisher et al., 1997; Kanwisher and Yovel, 2006).

3 Modularity in cognition

The existence of mental modules—cognitive mechanisms specialized for processing specific types of information—makes sense from an evolutionary perspective, as natural selection is expected to shape mechanisms that are well-suited to particular tasks (e.g., Burkart et al., 2017); as such the concept has been widely adopted by evolutionary psychologists (Tooby and Cosmides, 1992; Barrett and Kurzban, 2006; Carruthers, 2006) The concept of mental modularity was first introduced to cognitive science by Jerry Fodor in his 1983 book, The Modularity of Mind, where he proposed a set of a priori properties that mental modules are likely to possess. These include, among others, domain specificity (processing specific types of information, p. 47–52), automaticity and rapid information processing (p. 61–64), informational encapsulation (knowledge in other domains doesn't influence their operations, p. 64–86), shallow outputs (lacking broader contextual and interpretive depth, p. 86–97), fixed neural architecture (p. 98–99), specific breakdown patterns (damage results in localized deficits, p. 99–100) and characteristic ontogeny (developing in a uniform manner across individuals, p. 100–101) (Fodor, 1983).

Fodor's criteria have faced extensive criticism, including from evolutionary psychologists, for their biological implausibility and their inability to account for the diversity of evolved mental modules (Barrett, 2005, 2007; Pinker, 2005; Barrett and Kurzban, 2006; Barrett et al., 2006). Critics of the modular view, such as Bolhuis et al. (2011), argue that the classical criteria—particularly strict domain specificity and informational encapsulation—are inconsistent with empirical findings from neuroscience, genetics, and developmental psychology (Bolhuis et al., 2011). While certain systems, such as those involved in face recognition, are indeed domain-specific and process a single type of input (e.g., Kanwisher et al., 1997), other systems are expected to integrate inputs from multiple domains to address complex challenges. For example, threat identification likely involves the interaction of motion detection, memory, emotional processing, and motor systems. This view aligns with Bolhuis et al.'s (2011) emphasis on cognitive plasticity, extensive interconnectivity, and feedback loops in the brain, which facilitate the integration of information across multiple domains and support adaptability to novel contexts.

Moreover, informational encapsulation is not an all-or-nothing characteristic of cognitive systems, because few, if any, processes operate in complete isolation (see also Section 8). Instead, cognitive modules often interact in structured ways, promoting cognitive flexibility in solving adaptive challenges (Barrett, 2005). Even ostensibly “peripheral” processes, like visual perception, are modulated by context, personal expectations, and higher-order cognition (Goldstone and Barsalou, 1998; Pylyshyn, 1999; Ditzinger, 2021), illustrating how Fodor's concept of encapsulation applies primarily at the intentional level—reflecting subjective experience—rather than at the functional level, which concerns how cognitive systems actually operate (Pietraszewski and Wertz, 2022). Furthermore, not all cognitive systems are designed to function automatically or process information rapidly, as highlighted by the distinction between System 1 and System 2 (Kahneman, 2011). Pietraszewski and Wertz (2022) argue that automaticity is meaningful primarily at the intentional level—where cognitive processes appear effortless or reflexive—whereas at the functional level, cognitive mechanisms vary in flexibility and deliberation depending on adaptive demands, rather than being inherently automatic (Pietraszewski and Wertz, 2022). Nor do mental modules necessarily have a fixed neural architecture as they are often widely distributed across the brain (Pinker, 2015). For instance, some authors propose that Theory of Mind arises from the interaction of the 3 large-scale neural networks—default-mode network, salience network, and frontoparietal network (Ryan et al., 2017), while others argue that it emerges from the activity of 5 specific brain regions (Saxe, 2006).

The properties of mental modules, it has been argued, are a matter of empirical discovery rather than predefined assumptions (Sperber, 1994). A major source of confusion arises from the conflation of modern conceptions of modularity with classic Fodorian modularity (Pietraszewski and Wertz, 2022). Indeed, several alternative non-Fodorian models of cognition have been proposed (Barrett, 2005; Carruthers, 2008). Sperber highlighted a paradox in the title of Fodor's book, The Modularity of Mind, noting that Fodor restricted modularity to the “periphery” of the mind—sensory systems like perception—while attributing the “core” processes, such as reasoning, inference, problem-solving, judgment, and decision-making, to general-purpose mechanisms, which he considered non-modular (Sperber, 1994; Barrett, 2015, p. 265). The concept of general-purpose cognitive mechanisms has been widely criticized, particularly by the adaptationist program in evolutionary psychology, which argues that the entire mind, not just its periphery, is modular (Tooby and Cosmides, 1992). Critics invoke several key arguments against general-purpose mechanisms, including functional incompatibility (the inability of a single mechanism to simultaneously optimize behavior across conflicting adaptive challenges), combinatorial explosion (overwhelm caused by infinite possibilities for action, making decision-making infeasible), and a lack of efficacy in clueless environments (insufficient information to deduce effective actions without prior knowledge or specialized mechanisms) (Tooby and Cosmides, 1992; Ermer et al., 2007). However, Pietraszewski and Wertz (2022) caution against strictly categorizing cognitive mechanisms as domain-specific or domain-general, arguing that functional specialization exists on a continuum, with mechanisms varying in specificity and flexibility based on adaptive demands. They emphasize that domain specificity is best understood at the functional level, where mechanisms process particular input classes, rather than as an absolute distinction implying strict encapsulation or independence from other processes (Pietraszewski and Wertz, 2022). A more useful way to address this dichotomy is provided by Sperber (1994), who distinguishes between a module's proper domain—the type of information it evolved to process—and its actual domain, which includes the range of inputs it currently processes, even if they were not part of its original evolutionary function (Sperber, 1994). For example, the face recognition system evolved to process human faces (its proper domain) but can also be activated by face-like stimuli, including caricatures, objects resembling faces, and even schematic face-like patterns (its actual domain) (Johnson, 2005; Tsao and Livingstone, 2008; Hadjikhani et al., 2009; Liu et al., 2014).

According to the adaptationist framework, modules in the mind are specialized information-processing devices shaped by natural selection to solve recurrent adaptive problems encountered by our human ancestors (Tooby and Cosmides, 1992; Buss, 1995; Carruthers, 2006; Barrett, 2015; Pinker, 2015; Lewis et al., 2020). An adaptive problem—defined as a challenge affecting survival or reproduction—can be identified by applying natural selection principles to behaviors such as food acquisition, mating, kin care, cooperation, and aggression (Buss, 2019). This perspective underpins the concept of mental modularity used in this paper, emphasizing functional specialization as its core feature, akin to other evolved biological mechanisms (Tooby and Cosmides, 1992; Barrett and Kurzban, 2006; Carruthers, 2006).

In the current understanding of evolutionary psychology then, a mental module consists of three primary components: an input subsystem that receives informational cues from internal or external sources (e.g., physiological, social, or ecological signals); a processing mechanism that applies algorithms, decision rules, or other computational operations; and an output subsystem that generates behavioral responses, physiological reactions, or further inputs for other modules (Buss, 1991, 1995, 2019; Lewis et al., 2020). For the module to efficiently solve an adaptive problem, its front end must align closely with environmental features (Tooby and Cosmides, 1992). This fit between form and function is the essence of functional specialization, where “form” refers to the information-processing design features of the mechanism (Barrett, 2009). These features work by detecting specific informational cues from the environment or the organism that signal an adaptive problem, activating the system (Carruthers, 2006, p. 7) and informing the organism of the challenge it faces (Buss, 1991, 1995, 2019). Modules also address adaptive problems using inherent assumptions about the world's structure, known as intuitive ontologies, which guide behavior and organize knowledge (Cosmides and Tooby, 1997; Carey, 2009; Boyer and Barrett, 2015). The diversity of adaptive challenges faced by humans suggests a corresponding array of specialized mental modules (Buss, 1991, 1995, 2019). This proliferation of modules is sometimes referred to as the “multimodular mind” (Cosmides and Tooby, 2013) or the “Massive Modularity Hypothesis” (Carruthers, 2006).

In conclusion, although cognitive modularity remains a topic of active debate—either because its conceptual evolution has been underrecognized or because its modern iteration is still conflated with the older Fodorian model—key aspects of its modern form are particularly useful for understanding psychiatric phenomena, as explored throughout this paper. Functional specialization is especially relevant in lesion studies, while intuitive ontologies and the tight form-function fit help explain semantic deficits, which track fitness-relevant environmental elements (e.g., plants, animals, motion detection) (Section 9). Crucially, the diversity and numerosity of cognitive modules align with insights from the psychopathology of self-disorders, as explored in Section 5.

4 Words of caution

The above observations about cognitive architecture are necessarily simplified and may reflect our natural tendency to categorize reality. As Nesse cautions, it is essential to avoid the trap of tacit creationism—the implicit view of bodies as engineered machines—by recognizing their full biological complexity (Nesse, 2020, 2022). Bodies are not machines with distinct components designed to perform isolated functions; instead, their interlocked parts carry out overlapping functions, shaped by natural selection to enhance gene transmission. For instance, functions such as fighting infections are distributed across multiple components (Nesse, 2020). Similarly, caution is needed when interpreting the mind through the “mind as a computer” metaphor on which Fodor's classical modularity is based. While Marr's tripartite computational framework (inputs, computational rules, and outputs) remains central to cognitive science (Marr, 1982; Brase, 2014, 2021), and can be applied to evolved cognitive modules, extending the metaphor beyond its source domain can lead to biologically improbable conclusions (Brase, 2002). Instead, “we should be prepared to let the brain inform us about how it solves problems, rather than deciding in advance” (Barrett, 2007).

The organic complexity of brains further resists the oversimplification of mapping one module to one function or one ontological category. While modules can theoretically map onto functions in various ways—one to one, one to many, many to one, or many to many (Barrett, 2020a), their precise alignments remain ultimately empirical questions. This complexity reflects the evolutionary history of human cognitive abilities, which have emerged through hierarchical evolution driven by descent with modification, duplication, and divergence (Barrett, 2012, 2017). These processes have repurposed and specialized ancient mechanisms, creating a brain that integrates ancestral systems with novel adaptations unique to humans (Barrett, 2012, 2017). For instance, mindreading builds on older mechanisms like gaze detection to make sophisticated inferences about the mental states of others (Baron-Cohen, 1997). These cognitive abilities have also been shaped through reciprocal interactions with human-designed environments and tools, leading to further adaptive changes (Barrett, 2012, 2017). Neural sharing of components leads to overlapping and indistinct functional boundaries (Nesse, 2004, 2020, 2022; Anderson, 2010). This underscores that modules are not atomic entities parsing reality into distinct classical categories (e.g., plants, animals, and objects) (Carruthers, 2006, p. 62; Boyer and Barrett, 2015). Instead, they transcend traditional ontological boundaries, addressing fitness challenges arising from interwoven situations in the evolutionary past (Nesse, 1990a, 2022; Boyer and Barrett, 2015). For instance, the behavioral immune system, a suite of behaviors aimed at avoiding infection, activates regardless of whether the pathogenic threat originates from contaminated food, bodily products, infected animals, or humans (Schaller, 2015). This suggests that mental modules respond to specific eliciting features within a category, rather than the category as a whole (Boyer and Barrett, 2015).

Modules are not expected to develop in a fixed, predetermined manner across all individuals. Instead, they emerge in each generation as genes interact with developmental processes and environmental inputs. This process, termed “design reincarnation” (Tooby et al., 2003; Barrett, 2006), highlights the universality of our cognitive architecture (types) alongside individual variation (tokens). Types refer to universally evolved cognitive mechanisms, such as the capacity to recognize faces or acquire language, which have been shaped by natural selection to address adaptive problems. In contrast, tokens represent individual manifestations of these mechanisms, shaped by personal experiences and environmental inputs, like recognizing a familiar face or speaking a specific language (Barrett, 2006, 2012, 2017). This relationship showcases that our species-specific cognitive mechanisms generate flexible responses contingent upon their different inputs (Lewis et al., 2020).

Transcultural research, for example, reveals how environmental variability shapes diverse individual and cultural outcomes. In regions with high pathogen prevalence, for instance, individuals tend to prioritize physical attractiveness in mate selection, because visible traits can signal health and genetic fitness, which become particularly important in disease-prone environments (Gangestad and Buss, 1993). Under these conditions, women tend to prefer more masculine male faces, a relationship that persists regardless of women's specific mating strategies or economic wealth (DeBruine et al., 2010). These environments are also associated with increased collectivism, a trait that can help mitigate disease transmission (Fincher et al., 2008), and tend to foster lower average levels of extraversion and sociosexuality, likely due to the risks posed by increased interpersonal contact (Schaller and Murray, 2008). The influence of cultural and environmental factors extends beyond mating strategies and personality traits to basic senses, such as olfaction. For instance, speakers of Jahai in the Malay Peninsula exhibit remarkable precision in labeling odors using culturally specific terms, in stark contrast to the difficulty English speakers often face in describing smells (Majid and Burenhult, 2014). Similarly, the Maniq language, spoken by a group of hunter-gatherers in southern Thailand, contains numerous odor-specific words that enable detailed categorization and recognition of smells (Wnuk and Majid, 2014). These linguistic differences align with the ecological environments of these communities, as their foraging lifestyle likely necessitates heightened olfactory acuity, which their languages facilitate. This interaction between universal, species-specific mechanisms and environmental and cultural factors produces individualized outcomes, demonstrating developmental plasticity, wherein consistent cognitive types adapt flexibly to varied contexts to generate specific tokens (Barrett, 2020b).

5 The unitary self shattered into a thousand pieces

In the following section, we will argue that the descriptive psychopathology of self-disorders supports the multimodular view of the mind described in Section 2. When the pervasive sense of self that typically unifies mental processes breaks down, as it does in self-disorders, the modular architecture of the mind becomes internally exposed to the individual. This disruption reveals the mind's inherent multiplicity, as the lack of synchrony between its components forces the subject into a distressing awareness of their fragmented internal state.

5.1 The disordered self

Historically, the concept of “self” has been the subject of numerous philosophical interpretations (Zahavi, 2003). Berrios and Marková (2003) describe how this term entered psychiatric discourse in the 19th century, ultimately contributing to the concept of the “disordered self.” However, they argue that the very notion of the self is merely a metaphor (Berrios and Marková, 2003). By contrast, psychiatrists with a phenomenological perspective reject the notion of the self as either a metaphor or a social construct, viewing it instead as a fundamental aspect of mental life. From this perspective, the self is understood through the lens of “first-personal givenness”—a pre-reflective self-awareness that imbues all experiences with a sense of “my-ness,” “mineness,” “for-me-ness,” or Meinhaftigkeit (Sass and Parnas, 2003; Zahavi, 2003; Schneider, 2007). This perspective allows individuals to experience events from a first-personal perspective, recognizing themselves as the subjects of their experiences (Sass and Parnas, 2003; Zahavi, 2003; Parnas and Henriksen, 2014; Henriksen et al., 2019). For instance, when performing an action, having a thought or experiencing emotions, there is an unquestionable recognition that it is indeed oneself, who is acting, thinking and feeling. This implicit, pre-reflective awareness, referred to as the “minimal self” (also termed the “core self,” “basic self,” or ipseity—from ipse, the Latin word for “self”), imbues all experiences with a sense of “my-ness,” affirming that these experiences belong to the individual (Sass and Parnas, 2003; Parnas and Henriksen, 2019). The minimal self captures, in essence, the experiential sense of being a coherent, living agent—distinct from others and the environment—who maintains a continuous identity over time and is the source of their own thoughts, feelings, and actions (Jaspers, 1920; Casey and Kelly, 2019; Oyebode, 2022). Blanke and Metzinger further refine this into the concept of “minimal phenomenal selfhood,” defined as the most basic form of self-consciousness. Its key features include global identification with one's body, a first-person experiential perspective, and the spatial-temporal localization of the body (Blanke and Metzinger, 2009; Metzinger, 2013).

Self-disorders refer to disruptions in the inner experiences of individuals, particularly affecting the minimal self. Empirical evidence supports the longstanding clinical observation that schizophrenia is characterized by disturbances in the minimal self (Scharfetter, 1981, 2003, 2010; Parnas and Henriksen, 2014). These disturbances, which constitute the “clinical core” of schizophrenia (Sass and Parnas, 2003), are typically non-psychotic phenomena that often emerge in childhood or adolescence, preceding the onset of full-blown psychotic symptoms (Parnas, 2011). To address this core feature of schizophrenia, the Examination of Anomalous Self-Experience (EASE) scale was developed in 2005 as a semi-structured clinical tool designed to capture disturbances of the minimal self (Parnas et al., 2005). The EASE comprises 57 items grouped into five domains: cognition and stream of consciousness, self-awareness and presence, bodily experiences, demarcation and transitivism, and existential reorientation (Table 1). Unlike broader tools such as the Ego Pathology Inventory (Scharfetter, 2003), which addresses both psychotic and non-psychotic self-experiences, the EASE focuses specifically on near-psychotic or non-psychotic phenomena. Self-disorders exhibit a trait-like quality (Henriksen et al., 2021), are more prevalent in schizophrenia spectrum disorders than in other mental illnesses (Raballo et al., 2021; Burgin et al., 2022), demonstrate temporal stability (Nordgaard et al., 2018; Henriksen et al., 2021) and serve as predictors for the development of full-blown psychosis (Henriksen et al., 2021).

Table 1
www.frontiersin.org

Table 1. Selected Elements from the Examination of Anomalous Self-Experience (EASE) scale, adapted from Parnas et al. (2005).

5.2 Culture and the minimal self

Culture influences self-representation (Han et al., 2013). A well-documented distinction in this regard is the Independent Self-Construal, which emphasizes autonomy and personal goals (common in individualistic cultures), and the Interdependent Self-Construal, which emphasizes connectedness to others and group harmony (common in collectivist cultures) (Markus and Kitayama, 1991). In turn, the self shapes the culture that accommodates it by reinforcing or modifying norms through daily interactions (Markus and Kitayama, 2010). Culture also appears to affect self-representation at the neural level. For instance, Zhu et al. (2007) demonstrated that medial prefrontal cortex (MPFC) activation differs by culture: in Western cultures, the MPFC responds more selectively to the self, whereas in East Asian cultures, it responds similarly to both the self and close others (Zhu et al., 2007). However, these findings primarily focus on what phenomenologists call the narrative self—the dimension of selfhood involving autobiographical memory, personal identity, and social interactions, shaping how an individual perceives themselves over time (Zahavi, 2010; Horváth, 2024). The minimal self serves as a foundation for the narrative self and also appears to be permeable to cultural influences, at least in some of its dimensions. For instance, while self-other boundary disruptions in Western cultures are typically individualized, affecting internal mental space (e.g., “The government is putting thoughts in my head” or “Aliens implanted a chip in my head and now control my actions”), in Jaffna's sociocentric cultural context, boundary invasiveness is experienced as a relational disorder—one that disrupts not only the individual's sense of self but also family and community structures (Alphonsus et al., 2023).

5.3 Enzymatic computation as a framework for self-disorders

In Barrett's enzymatic model of cognition (Barrett, 2005, 2015), thinking is compared to catalysis performed by cognitive enzymes, or “cogzymes,” which process information in a manner similar to how enzymes function within a cell's cytoplasm. A cogzyme acts on a specific chunk of information (its substrate) and then releases the processed output back into a central information pool, making it available for further processing by other cogzymes. This sequential processing resembles a metabolic pathway, such as glycolysis or the Krebs cycle, where the product of one enzymatic reaction serves as the substrate for the next. Just as glycolytic enzymes preserve the energy potential of glucose, cogzymes must retain the “aboutness” of information to ensure its adaptive relevance. For instance, if incoming information signals the presence of a lion, it may be assigned a “LION” tag. Specialized cogzymes can then recognize this tag in a key-and-lock fashion, ensuring that the information is efficiently accessed by the appropriate processing pathways to address the adaptive problem (Barrett, 2005, 2015). Roser and Gazzaniga (2004) and Gazzaniga (2012)'s concept of the interpreter provides another perspective, positing a specialized cognitive process that unifies conscious experience by synthesizing the outputs of thousands of information-processing modules operating simultaneously. In this view, Gazzaniga (2012, 2018) argues that conscious experience emerges from the coordinated activity of individual modules rather than from a single, central mechanism. Even in cases of brain damage, such as stroke or dementia, consciousness persists, albeit in a constrained form, as the loss of specific modules limits its scope (Gazzaniga, 2018). Within this framework, the interpreter can be seen as another type of cogzyme, integrating and synthesizing modular outputs into a coherent conscious narrative. However, when the interpreter receives incomplete or erroneous input, the cohesion of conscious experience breaks down, following the familiar principle of “garbage in, garbage out” (Gazzaniga, 2012).

We propose that the pre-reflective sense of ipseity depends on tagging processes within the mind and is therefore vulnerable to their disruptions. Representations may indeed be assigned a “mineness” tag before entering conscious awareness, enabling the interpreter to integrate them into a cohesive product of conscious experience. In the absence of a mineness tag, the interpreter would no longer recognize and integrate these representations. As a result, conscious awareness would receive a disjointed collection of modular outputs, leading to fractured and alien experiences, as captured in the Cognition and Stream of Consciousness domain of the EASE scale (Parnas et al., 2005), where thoughts and internal representations are perceived as strange, anonymized, impersonal, and devoid of their sense of belonging. Conversely, overactive tagging may oversaturate consciousness with self-referentiality, producing solipsistic experiences in which the world feels entirely centered on the self, and the subject's perceptions dominate as the only existing reality, as described in the Existential Reorientation domain of the EASE scale (Parnas et al., 2005).

A similar tagging mechanism may also apply to bodily representations. If the “global bodily self-identification” tag is absent, the interpreter cannot integrate these representations into a coherent sense of bodily unity. Consequently, the subjective experience of the body becomes fragmented, leading to phenomena like bodily estrangement, morphological alterations, or even sensations of bodily disintegration, producing, in a sense, the sensation of a “disembodied” mind (Fuchs, 2005a). These disruptions align with the Bodily Experiences domain of the EASE scale (Parnas et al., 2005). In contrast, melancholic depression, may involve an overactive tagging mechanism that indiscriminately marks body-specific representations. This “over-tagging” results in an overwhelming bodily awareness, leading to what Fuchs (Fuchs, 2005a,b) describes as a “corporealized” mind—a state in which the individual becomes excessively absorbed by their physical body, experiencing a collapse into its spatial and material boundaries (Fuchs, 2005b). Here, the lived body—the experiential medium through which one inhabits the world (Leib, or “the body that I am”)—is reduced to an anatomical body (Körper, or “the body that I have”) (Fuchs, 2005b). Correspondingly, failure in the “spatiotemporal location” tag may impair the ability to distinguish one's body from external objects or others, leading to disturbances such as mistaking one's mirror image or another person for oneself. This aligns with the Demarcation/Transitivism domain of the EASE scale (Parnas et al., 2005). These bodily tagging mechanisms share conceptual similarities with Damasio's somatic marker hypothesis, which suggests that emotionally charged bodily states (“gut feelings”) influence decision-making by steering individuals toward beneficial or detrimental outcomes (Damasio et al., 1996; Damasio, 2000, 2006). Just as somatic markers bias which options become consciously prioritized, embodiment tags may play a crucial role in shaping self-experience by selecting and reinforcing specific bodily representations as central to the sense of self, thereby contributing to its coherence. A breakdown in multiple tagging systems—whether simultaneously or in varying combinations—can result in overlapping anomalies in self-experience, as documented in the Self-Awareness and Presence domain of the EASE scale (Parnas et al., 2005).

In conclusion, our proposed model of ego-pathology suggests that cognitive module outputs lose coherence as they enter conscious awareness, leading to the fragmented self often described in self-disorders. Fundamental dimensions of minimal phenomenal selfhood—such as first-person perspective (with its sense of mineness), global bodily self-identification, and spatiotemporal self-location (Blanke and Metzinger, 2009; Metzinger, 2013)—may act as tags that structure conscious self-experience. When these dimensions become disrupted, the individual's sense of agency and coherence erodes, contributing to self-disorders (Table 2).

Table 2
www.frontiersin.org

Table 2. Narrative accounts of patients with self-disorders.

6 Evidence for modularity in self-disorders

6.1 Split-brains

At a very broad level, evidence for modularity in the brain comes from patients with disrupted interhemispheric communication, where resulting independent cognitive and motor behaviors for each hemisphere challenge the idea of a unitary self (Gazzaniga, 1977, 2005; Gazzaniga and LeDoux, 1978; Volz and Gazzaniga, 2017). Abnormalities in interhemispheric communication have also been documented in schizophrenia (Foong et al., 2000; Kubicki et al., 2008; Patel et al., 2011; Wang et al., 2024), a phenomenon that may underlie the emergence of auditory hallucinations in the psychosis spectrum (Francis et al., 2016; McGuire, 2016). These observations align with Frith's impaired self-monitoring model, which posits that internally generated thoughts are misattributed to an external source, leading to auditory hallucinations (Frith and Done, 1988; Frith, 2014; chap. 7). Given the functional specialization of the cerebral hemispheres, this loss of interhemispheric synchronization may result in internally generated dialogue in the left hemisphere failing to be recognized as self-produced by the right hemisphere (Frith, 2014, chap. 7), mirroring the cognitive disintegration seen in split-brain patients.

6.2 Schizophrenia as dysmodularity

Although hemispheres cannot be strictly considered modules, schizophrenia provides further evidence for dysconnectivity, as it is characterized by widespread white matter abnormalities rather than isolated regional deficits (Kelly et al., 2018). Similar disruptions appear in functional connectivity, where large-scale networks fail to maintain balanced co-activation patterns across brain regions (Liang et al., 2006; Li et al., 2017). This aligns with the “disconnection hypothesis,” which posits that impaired communication between functional networks underlies core symptoms of the disorder (Friston and Frith, 1995). Martin et al. (2023) describe schizophrenic self-disorders as emerging from dysconnectivity both within and between large-scale brain networks, particularly the Salience Network (SN), Default Mode Network (DMN), and Fronto-Parietal Network (FPN), linking these disruptions to the subjective experience of affected individuals (Martin et al., 2023).

The SN, crucial for detecting relevant stimuli and signaling shifts in attention, is hyperactive, leading to excessive self-focus, and an increased awareness of previously filtered-out self-signals. The DMN, involved in self-referential thought and introspection, becomes dysregulated, contributing to disturbances in self-experience and altered self-perception. Meanwhile, the FPN, which regulates executive control, shows disrupted connectivity with the DMN, potentially impairing cognitive regulation over self-monitoring and contributing to misattributions of self-generated thoughts and actions (Martin et al., 2023). This model suggests that a hyperactive SN contributes to excessive self-focus and hyper-reflexivity, heightened SN-DMN connectivity disrupts self-boundaries and impairs the distinction between internal and external stimuli, and reduced DMN-FPN connectivity weakens self-monitoring, collectively driving self-disorders in schizophrenia (Martin et al., 2023). Notably, these alterations are detectable even in unmedicated first-episode psychotic patients, reinforcing that they are intrinsic to the disorder rather than secondary to chronicity or medication effects (Li et al., 2018; Cui et al., 2019). Given that self-disorders often precede full-blown psychosis (Nordgaard and Parnas, 2014), similar network dysfunctions likely occur in pre-psychotic individuals, highlighting their potential as biomarkers for early intervention. This triple-network model suggests that schizophrenic self-disorders involves both reduced network modularity—where specialized networks become less distinct—and the abnormal dominance of certain networks over others.

Considering these findings collectively, self-disorders can be viewed as manifestations of “dysmodularity,” to borrow a term from David (1994), thereby lending renewed attention to the classical Fodorian notion of information encapsulation. From this perspective, self-disorders may metaphorically reflect a modular mind whose encapsulation has been compromised, in which mental modules “decapsulate,” as it were, exposing their internal operations both to each other and to conscious awareness in an unfiltered and often disruptive manner (see also Section 8).

6.3 Dissolution of the ego under psychedelics

Dysmodularity and a fragmented self can also manifest in otherwise healthy brains, particularly in states such as psychedelic-induced ego dissolution. This phenomenon shares overlapping neural substrates and exhibits remarkably similar phenomenology with self-disorders (Nour and Carhart-Harris, 2017; Millière et al., 2018). For instance, both psychedelics and self-disorders involve altered information flow within the DMN and SN (Lebedev et al., 2015; Letheby and Gerrans, 2017; Millière et al., 2018; Stoliker et al., 2022). However, while both conditions involve altered large-scale connectivity, their network dynamics diverge. Self-disorders are characterized by rigid, maladaptive hyperconnectivity, whereas psychedelic states promote a more flexible, and globally integrated network architecture, potentially contributing to their therapeutic effects (Carhart-Harris et al., 2013, 2016; Tagliazucchi et al., 2016; Letheby and Gerrans, 2017; Stoliker et al., 2022).

Psychedelics temporarily relax hierarchical constraints, increasing communication between previously segregated brain regions and dissolving functional boundaries (Carhart-Harris et al., 2014; Lebedev et al., 2016; Stoliker et al., 2022). LSD, for instance, enhances global functional connectivity, reducing modularity and strengthening cross-network interactions (Tagliazucchi et al., 2016; Bedford et al., 2023). Crucially, the magnitude of these connectivity changes correlates with participants' subjective ratings of ego dissolution, underscoring the neural basis of self-boundary disintegration (Nour et al., 2016; Tagliazucchi et al., 2016). The phenomenological parallels between these states are equally striking. Individuals may experience loss of self—where personal identity dissolves—disembodiment, derealization, cognitive fragmentation, breakdown of self-other boundaries and fear of dissolution (Hovmand et al., 2024). However, while self-disorders are predominantly characterized by negative emotional connotations, psychedelic experiences can also be mystical, unitive, or even therapeutic (Nour et al., 2016; Letheby and Gerrans, 2017; Stoliker et al., 2022).

Psychedelics shift cognitive processing toward a more associative, non-linear, and emotion-driven mode, mirroring cognitive alterations observed in dreaming and psychosis (Kraehenmann, 2017; Kraehenmann et al., 2017). This cognitive mode, often referred to as primary process thinking and thought to underlie unconscious cognition, stands in contrast to secondary process thinking, which characterizes conscious thought and is inherently logical, structured, and constrained by reality (Brakel, 2004, 2018; Arminjon, 2011; Auchincloss et al., 2012; p. 199–201; Modell, 2014). Under the influence of LSD, participants exhibited hallmark features of primary process cognition, including blurred self-boundaries (“I became part of a metal plate”), surreal transformations (“A cat turned into a wooden clock”), and fluid shape-shifting (“Two people entangled and dissolved into bubbles”) (Kraehenmann et al., 2017). Notably, these effects depended on serotonin 2A receptor (5-HT2A) activation, as their reversal with ketanserin, a 5-HT2A antagonist, confirmed their transient nature (Kraehenmann et al., 2017). These collective findings strongly support the modular mind hypothesis, suggesting that psychedelics disrupt the coordination between distinct cognitive subsystems and, by facilitating the transition between primary and secondary process thinking, may allow their unsynchronized outputs to become consciously accessible. The case of transient, drug-induced ego dissolution, occurring independently of schizophrenia's chronicity, and antipsychotic effects, offers a unique lens into the modular nature of selfhood.

6.4 Conclusion of Section 6

Collectively, the phenomenological and neurobiological links between self-disorders and psychedelic-induced ego-dissolution indicate that self-consciousness emerges from the dynamic interplay of multiple components of a modular mind. These findings highlight the fluid and distributed nature of selfhood, challenging traditional views of a unified, monolithic self.

7 Empirical approaches to testing the dysmodularity model

To empirically test our model of ego-pathology, where disrupted modular tagging processes expose fragmented modular outputs to conscious awareness, we propose employing guided imagery paradigms in patients with self-disorders. Structured imagery tasks specifically designed to target “mineness,” self-identification, and spatiotemporal coherence could systematically assess subjective experiences of self-fragmentation. Additionally, integrating these paradigms with neuroimaging could reveal the neural correlates of disrupted self-coherence, offering deeper insight into the modular mechanisms underlying selfhood disturbances. A useful organizing principle for this investigation is the distinction between psychological ownership—the sense that one's thoughts and emotions are inherently one's own—and bodily ownership—the sense that one's body and its parts belong to oneself (Bermúdez, 2019).

Assessing mineness or ownership for body parts is relatively straightforward, as patients often spontaneously report deficits in bodily ownership to their examiner. For example, patients with alien limb syndrome would be expected to demonstrate reduced ownership scores when asked, “On a scale from 1 to 10, where 1 represents no sense of belonging and 10 signifies complete ownership, how much does this arm feel like yours?” More severe disturbances of bodily ownership, such as those seen in Cotard Syndrome—where some patients hold the delusional belief that they lack body parts, organs, or biological functions (“I have no organs, no blood, I don't exist physically”) (Berrios and Luque, 1995; Debruyne et al., 2009; Dieguez, 2018)—can be similarly assessed using structured quantitative measures. Beyond bodily ownership, the same methodology can be applied to psychological ownership. Lower scores would be expected in ego-dystonic experiences, such as obsessive thoughts in obsessive-compulsive disorder, intrusive memories in post-traumatic stress disorder, or auditory hallucinations and thought insertion in schizophrenia, where patients perceive these thoughts as originating externally rather than being self-generated. The same quantification methods could systematically assess psychological ownership in patients with self-disorders and may help identify clinically relevant symptom clusters based on individual differences in the intensity of tagging processes.

Subpopulations of self-disordered patients, particularly those experiencing disturbances in bodily experiences as assessed by validation tools (e.g., EASE), could engage in guided motor imagery—externally directed mental simulation of movement without execution (Moran et al., 2012; Hurst and Boe, 2022)—designed to evoke the subjective sense of bodily ownership, provided they do not have aphantasia, the inability to voluntarily generate mental imagery (Zeman et al., 2015; Zeman, 2024). For example, they would be instructed to first imagine their own arm reaching for a cup, and then to imagine a robotic arm performing the same action. Their subjective feelings of mineness would then be assessed using structured quantitative measures, such as “On a scale from 1 to 10, how convinced are you that the imagined arm is yours?” or “How convinced are you that the robotic arm is yours?” The model predicts that patients with disrupted tagging processes should exhibit reduced or altered mineness scores for both conditions, reflecting pre-existing impairments in ownership for their own limb.

Mental imagery tasks, combined with neuroimaging techniques, could be further used to examine neurophenomenological correlations, specifically in the context of self-agency and external attribution, which have been shown to rely on distinct neural systems. The anterior insula, crucial for integrating interoceptive signals and self-generated actions—thereby contributing to the sense of control over one's own movements (Farrer and Frith, 2002; Ohata et al., 2020)—is expected to show atypical activation when individuals with self-disorders imagine their own arm reaching for an object. Such alterations would reflect impairments in sensory-motor integration and self-referential processing. Conversely, when imagining a robotic arm performing the same action, these individuals may exhibit abnormal or undifferentiated activation in the inferior parietal lobule (IPL), a region implicated in differentiating self-initiated from externally generated actions (Farrer and Frith, 2002; Ohata et al., 2020). Disruptions in IPL activation may underlie agency misattribution and weakened self-other boundaries, contributing to experiences of passivity, dissociation, or delusions of control in self-disorders. Notably, similar disturbances in agency processing and self-other differentiation have been experimentally induced in healthy individuals using transcranial magnetic stimulation (TMS) applied to the IPL (Uddin et al., 2006; Chambon et al., 2015), providing an opportunity to systematically investigate parallels between experimental manipulations of agency and the self-disturbances observed in clinical conditions. Moreover, these insights open new avenues for therapeutic intervention. For instance, TMS applied over the temporoparietal junction, a region encompassing parts of the parietal lobe, has led to symptomatic relief in patients with depersonalization disorder (Mantovani et al., 2011). This suggests the potential for targeted neuromodulation strategies to restore agency and self-boundaries in self-disordered patients.

8 Information encapsulation

In the classical Fodorian sense, information encapsulation refers to the idea that computations within a module (or inside its “capsule”) are isolated and unaffected by computations in other modules (Fodor, 1983, 2000). While this strict encapsulation may efficiently handle tasks like perception, it fails to account for the flexibility and interactivity required for higher-order cognition. In Barrett's model, cogzymes balance functional specialization with broader informational access. They can broadly access a shared information pool (access generality) but process only inputs matching their specific “binding sites” (processing specificity) (Barrett, 2005; Barrett and Kurzban, 2006). Barrett and Kurzban (2006) further framed encapsulation as a relative concept, arguing that modules operate based on the types or formats of information they can recognize and process. Thus, encapsulation is not absolute but varies depending on the cognitive mechanism and its inputs (Barrett and Kurzban, 2006). Similarly, Carruthers describes encapsulation as a matter of degree. While low-level perceptual systems may exhibit high encapsulation, central systems like reasoning and planning allow for interaction with and querying of other modules. Carruthers distinguishes between wide-scope encapsulation, where most stored mental information does not affect a module's operations, and narrow-scope encapsulation, where modules remain entirely isolated (Carruthers, 2006, chap. 1). This graded view emphasizes how encapsulation supports functional specialization while allowing integration and flexibility, which are essential for human cognition.

In Why Everyone (Else) Is a Hypocrite (Kurzban, 2012) and related works (Kurzban and Aktipis, 2006, 2007), Kurzban explains information encapsulation as a default feature of the modular mind, wherein specialized cognitive modules process information independently, ensuring efficiency by focusing on specific tasks without interference. This independence is evident in phenomena like split-brain patients, where distinct modules operate in relative isolation, sometimes producing inconsistencies in thought and behavior. Kurzban links encapsulation to the diversity of representational formats—the ways cognitive modules encode information. Each module processes information in formats optimized for its specific function and may include discursive (propositional, language-like) and iconic (analog, image-like) forms (Quilty-Dunn, 2020). For instance, a visual processing module may rely on iconic representations to encode sensory details, while a social reasoning module may use discursive formats to handle abstract concepts like fairness or intent. These differing representational formats often hinder direct information sharing between modules. Kurzban applies this concept to explain various psychological and behavioral phenomena rooted in the modular mind's independent processing. Cognitive dissonance, self-deception, and moral hypocrisy, for example, arise from the relative isolation of modules and their encapsulated operations, shaped by evolutionary constraints on representational formats and cognitive specialization (Kurzban, 2012). Against this backdrop of encapsulation and diverse representational formats, we will explore intrapsychic conflict in clinical psychiatry.

8.1 Clashes between mental modules

The concept of internal conflicts within the mind is far from new. In Phaedrus, Plato portrays the soul as consisting of three parts, likened to a chariot pulled by two horses. Reason, depicted as the charioteer, struggles to keep balance between a disciplined horse, representing virtue, and an impulsive one, driven by base desires, whose opposing tendencies makes it difficult to control the chariot (Plato, 2011). Freud similarly conceptualized the mind as tripartite, with the ego (the conscious self) and the superego (morality) attempting to regulate the id (repository of instinctual drives) but they are often dominated by it (Freud, 2019).

Modern theories echo these foundational ideas. Rowan describes semi-independent subpersonalities within the mind, each capable of acting autonomously (Rowan, 1989), while Elliott and Greenberg highlight the “dialogues between aspects of the self” often encountered in therapy (Elliott and Greenberg, 1997). In clinical contexts, such conflicts are vividly observed. For instance, patients with borderline personality disorder often oscillate between wanting to live and wanting to die. Linehan (1993), the founder of dialectical behavior therapy, describes this as a dialectical dilemma: one part wishes to end their life, while another part wants to survive. The therapist's role is to help reconcile these opposing desires. A similar approach is used in motivational interviewing, where therapists address ambivalence between conflicting behaviors, such as wanting to quit substance use while also wanting to continue (Rollnick and Miller, 1995). Obsessive-compulsive disorder further illustrates internal conflict through repetitive behaviors. For instance, while one part of the individual knows the car is locked, another part persistently doubts it, driving compulsive checking. Similarly, in psychosis, ambivalence may manifest as indecision, with patients vacillating for hours or days over seemingly simple choices, such as whether to remain in treatment or leave the hospital (Scharfetter, 2010; Payk, 2021). This theme of conflicting impulses extends to catatonia, where patients may exhibit “ambitendency,” a state of being “stuck” in indecisive movement (Bush et al., 1996), a symptom consistently included in most clinical rating scales for the disorder (Sienaert et al., 2011). For example, a patient might freeze midway while bringing a spoon to their mouth, unable to resolve the urge to simultaneously eat and not eat (Scharfetter, 2010).

Gilbert extends the concept of internal conflict to “social mentalities,” parts of the mind exchanging signals of dominance and submission (Gilbert, 2000). This dynamic is evident in self-criticism, where a dominant “bullying” part attacks a submissive part with thoughts like “You're useless” or “How stupid can you be?” Gilbert extends this concept to schizophrenia, suggesting that humiliating voices or thoughts originate from parts of the self perceived as powerful and dominant, while the receiving part feels powerless and submissive. He proposes therapeutic approaches to challenge the dominance of attacking mentalities by counteracting their influence, fostering moral beliefs to reduce self-criticism, or activating caregiving mentalities for support (Gilbert, 2000). These therapeutic strategies align with specific psychotherapeutic modalities employed in the treatment of dissociative identity disorder, formerly known as multiple personality disorder (International Society for the Study of Trauma and Dissociation, 2011). This condition is characterized by the presence of distinct subpersonalities or alters within the same individual, with at least two of them alternating in taking control over the person's behavior, often accompanied by amnesia for the periods during which an alter is in control (Dorahy et al., 2014; American Psychiatric Association, 2022; Khan, 2023). Some alters are considered more dominant, as illustrated in a female patient of the author G.I., where some therapeutic relief was achieved by opening a dialogue between her dominant, most destructive subpersonality and other aspects of her self, with the goal of identity integration. She shared her experiences of living with multiple personality states in the memoir, I Am Many, in the German language (Röper and Hagedorn, 2019).

People often desire incompatible outcomes, creating internal conflicts. A central concept of psychodynamic psychotherapy is that many of these internal struggles occur outside conscious awareness. The clash between different parts of the mind with opposing desires can overwhelm us (e.g., Shedler, 2022; Westen and Gabbard, 2002). To manage this stress, the mind deploys defense mechanisms—unconscious and automatic strategies that help us adapt to internal or external stress and mitigate painful affects (Freud, 1984; Vaillant, 1995; Gabbard, 2014; Cabaniss, 2017). When conflicting parts of the mind are inactive or operate at different times, stress remains low (Cabaniss, 2017). The mind may also find compromises, partially satisfying opposing desires (Collective, 2022). However, when clashing parts are active simultaneously, defense mechanisms activate to reduce internal tension (Cabaniss, 2017; Collective, 2022). These mechanisms are fueled by intrapsychic conflict—unconscious clashes between fears or desires (Cabaniss, 2017)—and their outcome is the alleviation of overstimulation or unpleasant affect.

Defense mechanisms are traditionally classified along a spectrum from less adaptive (“immature”) to more adaptive (“mature”) mechanisms (Cabaniss, 2017; Gabbard, 2014). Less adaptive defenses are based on splitting, where positive and negative aspects of people or experiences are kept separate. In contrast, more adaptive defenses rely on repression, an unconscious process that manages unpleasant thoughts and feelings. If an individual develops object constancy—the ability to recognize that people possess both positive and negative traits—they can use repression to tolerate and integrate distressing emotions. However, without this capacity, unpleasant thoughts and emotions tend to be compartmentalized and often perceived as external threats from others. Cabaniss (2017) describes this dynamic in detail. The specific defense mechanisms a person employs depend on their relative costs and benefits to them. Low-cost, high-benefit defenses can preserve functioning, whereas high-cost, low-benefit defenses may impair long-term functioning, even if they provide temporary relief from distress (Collective, 2022). Nesse (1990b) and Nesse and Lloyd (1992) argues that these trade-offs align with two opposing evolutionary strategies for maximizing fitness: short-term strategies that prioritize immediate personal gains, often at the expense of social relationships, and long-term strategies involving sacrifices that foster reciprocity and future benefits. This dichotomy mirrors Freud's classical distinction between the id, which seeks immediate gratification, and the ego/superego, which regulate behavior for long-term goals and social harmony (Nesse, 1990b; Nesse and Lloyd, 1992). Conceptually, these defenses align with fast life-history traits, which prioritize immediate benefits such as impulsivity, short-term mating strategies, and risk-taking behaviors (Del Giudice and Haltigan, 2023; Del Giudice, 2024). While direct empirical studies linking high-cost, low-benefit defenses to life-history strategies are lacking, indirect evidence suggests a plausible connection. Conditions marked by emotional dysregulation and impulsivity, such as borderline personality disorder, exhibit defense mechanisms like splitting and dissociation alongside fast life-history traits (Brüne, 2016). Although the evidence remains indirect, this conceptual overlap suggests that these defenses may extend beyond intrapsychic conflict resolution, potentially reflecting broader behavioral tendencies linked to life history strategy.

9 Clinical evidence for the modular mind and the modular framework for classifying mental disorders

In this final section, we examine how various neuropsychiatric syndromes provide evidence for the modular view and, conversely, how this perspective can serve as an organizing principle for classifying mental disorders. The first part of this section examines how dissociation studies support the decomposability of cognitive processes into distinct modular elements. It further considers how lesion studies provide evidence for specific modules proposed by evolutionary psychology, such as the animacy detector, the agency detector and cognitive mechanisms for reasoning about artifacts. In the second part, we consider the potential for organizing neuropsychiatric clinical evidence along modular lines and discuss the implications of using dysfunctional modules as a framework for classifying neuropsychiatric illness.

9.1 Supporting the modular view through clinical evidence

Clinically recognized disorders, such as those discussed in Sections 5, 6, 8, provide compelling empirical support for the existence of mental modules. Dissociation studies have historically highlighted a modular architecture of the mind, demonstrating that distinct neuropsychological functions can be selectively impaired while others remain relatively intact (Baddeley, 2003; Caramazza and Coltheart, 2006; Dunn and Kirsner, 2003; Gerlach et al., 2018; Machery, 2012; but see Plaut, 1995). For example, in melancholia and personality disorders, it is the narrative self—shaped by identity, life stories, and beliefs—that is disrupted, while the minimal self, which is affected in schizophrenia spectrum disorders, remains intact (Parnas and Henriksen, 2019). A clear dissociation between knowledge domains is evident in cases where knowledge about the functions of tools remains distinct from knowledge about how to manipulate them (Johnson-Frey, 2004; Boronat et al., 2005; Garcea and Mahon, 2012; Garcea et al., 2013). For instance, patients with apraxia—a condition characterized by an inability to perform complex learned actions (Heilman, 2010; Berkowitz, 2022)—exhibit selective impairments in manipulation knowledge while retaining the ability to recognize the function of objects (Buxbaum et al., 2000; Buxbaum and Saffran, 2002). Similarly, vision and action can be dissociated in specific deficits affecting these components (Goodale et al., 1994). Patients with optic ataxia, such as patient RV, can “see but cannot grasp”—they are unable to reach for or grasp objects despite being able to visually perceive them (Perenin and Vighetto, 1988; Goodale et al., 1994; Schindler et al., 2004; Karnath and Perenin, 2005). Conversely, cases like patient DF demonstrate the opposite dissociation—being able to “grasp but not see” (Goodale et al., 1991, 1994; Milner et al., 1991; James et al., 2003). Dissociation studies also demonstrated significant sharing in processing mechanisms, as it is rare for a module to be affected without neighboring ones also experiencing some degree of impairment. For example, in the ventral temporal cortex, representations of objects and faces overlap substantially (Haxby et al., 2001). Lesion studies reveal that focal damage in this area can result in prosopagnosia, while more extensive damage often leads to broader difficulties in object recognition (Damasio et al., 1982; Farah, 1991; Gauthier et al., 2000). By the same token, disruptions in the minimal self in schizophrenia can also lead to instability in the narrative self, as the former serves as a precondition for the latter (Scharfetter, 2010, chap. 3; Parnas and Henriksen, 2019). In summary, dissociations offer robust clinical evidence for the modularity of distinct neuropsychological systems, while simultaneously recognizing their interconnectedness.

Not only does clinical evidence from neuropsychiatric syndromes support the decomposability of cognitive processes into distinct modules, but it may also help identify new modular elements. For instance, conditions such as akinetopsia (the inability to perceive motion) (Zihl et al., 1983; Stevens et al., 2009) and kinetopsia (perceiving stationary objects as moving) (Blom, 2023), observed in various neuropsychiatric syndromes (Browne et al., 2024)—including Alice in Wonderland Syndrome, which involves distortions in visual perception, body schema, and the experience of time (Blom, 2016)—suggest the existence of an animacy detector. This mechanism classifies objects as animate or inanimate (Leslie, 1994; Scholl and Tremoulet, 2000; Barrett, 2015). While motion itself takes various forms (Park and Tadin, 2018), biological motion, characterized by self-propulsion, goal-directed behavior, and responsiveness to external events (Barrett, 2015, p. 108), is distinct from mechanical motion. These mechanisms, referred to as “life detectors” (Troje and Westhoff, 2006), are crucial for distinguishing animate from inanimate entities. Anomalies in perceiving biological motion have been documented in disorders such as schizophrenia (Kim et al., 2005, 2013) and autism spectrum disorders (Freitag et al., 2008; Todorova et al., 2019; Federici et al., 2020).

In self-disorders, disturbances in the sense of agency—the perception of oneself as the initiator and controller of thoughts, feelings, and actions—are also striking (Scharfetter, 1981, 2003; Gallagher and Trigg, 2016). Patients may phenomenologically experience their actions or thoughts as being externally produced or manipulated, a phenomenon referred to as delusions of control (American Psychiatric Association, 2022). These patients often describe having implanted devices, purportedly used for surveillance or control of their bodily functions (e.g., “They inserted a computer chip in my brain to control me”). This clinical phenomenon supports the idea of a “hypersensitive agent detection device,” an adaptive mechanism that predisposes humans to perceive agency and intentionality, even in improbable situations (Barrett, 2004). This bias likely evolved as an error-management strategy, enhancing survival by erring on the side of caution—e.g., interpreting rustling leaves as a potential predator (Barrett, 2004; Douglas, 2020). When these delusions specifically involve artifacts, they align with Dennett's concept of the “design stance,” which ascribes intention to an actual or presumed creator when interpreting an artifact (Dennett, 1990). Additionally, this reflects a universal cognitive tendency across cultures: reasoning about artifacts often focuses on the original intentions behind their creation (German and Johnson, 2002; Defeyter and German, 2003; Kelemen and Carey, 2007; Barrett et al., 2008). In delusions of control, patients may interpret the “implanted” artifacts as instruments of malicious intent.

9.2 Organizing clinical evidence through a modular lens

Several authors have advocated for using evolved cognitive mechanisms as the basis for classifying mental conditions (Wakefield, 1992, 2015; Cosmides and Tooby, 1999; Murphy and Stich, 2000; Zielasek and Gaebel, 2008, 2009; Giudice and Ellis, 2016; Del Giudice, 2018). Such a classification system holds significant promise, but the initial step in this endeavor requires a comprehensive cataloging of the human mind and a detailed analysis of how evolved mental modules may fail or become compromised. Nesse provides valuable insights into why these systems are inherently vulnerable to breakdown (Nesse, 2005, 2015; Nesse, 2019).

Efforts to identify evolved mental modules are already ongoing, though debates persist about what constitutes an evolved mental module and how best to “carve the mind at its joints.” A central challenge is the “grain problem,” which concerns defining the number and scope of distinct adaptive problems and their corresponding mental modules (Atkinson and Wheeler, 2003). Addressing this issue and the broader lack of consensus across behavioral science may require a cross-disciplinary approach (Brase, 2014). Such an approach could provide converging evidence from independent sources, fostering a more unified understanding of the mind's modular nature—an aim long championed by evolutionary psychology (e.g., Al-Shawaf et al., 2020; Buss, 2019; Lewis et al., 2017; Tooby and Cosmides, 1992). Schmitt and Pilcher (2004) propose a heuristic framework for integrating and evaluating evidence of psychological adaptations across disciplines. Their model assesses psychological features from eight evidentiary sources: theoretical, psychological, medical, physiological, genetic, phylogenetic, hunter-gatherer, and cross-cultural data. Evidence is then evaluated based on evidentiary breadth (the number of supporting disciplines) and evidentiary depth (the rigor of the research) (Schmitt and Pilcher, 2004). Building on this framework, Balachandran and Glass developed PsychTable (https://app.psychtable.org/), “a collaborative web-based project aimed at classifying and evaluating evolved psychological adaptations (EPAs).” PsychTable systematically organizes EPAs, serving as a classification system akin to the Periodic Table of Elements or Gray's Anatomy (Balachandran, 2011; Balachandran and Glass, 2012; Glass and Balachandran, 2020).

Aligning with this framework, each module in such a classificatory system would ideally include a detailed description of its functions and subcomponents, developmental trajectory, evolutionary homologies with other species, and cultural variations. For example, in the case of Mindreading, humans appear uniquely capable of consistently passing the false-belief task (Call and Tomasello, 2008), an ability that typically develops around the age of four (Wellman et al., 2001) and is universal across cultures (Onishi and Baillargeon, 2005; Barrett et al., 2013). However, the ability to track other types of mental states is not exclusive to humans. It is also observed in non-human primates (Call and Tomasello, 2008), canids (Hare et al., 2002), and corvids (Clayton et al., 2007) (reviewed in Barrett, 2020a, 2015). Beyond false-belief tasks, mindreading also involves shared intentionality and triadic representations (Barrett, 2020a)—where two individuals simultaneously focus on an external entity (Tomasello et al., 2005; Saxe, 2006; Tomasello, 2019)—as well as unique forms of empathy (Decety and Jackson, 2004; Saxe, 2006; Decety and Svetlova, 2012).

The folkbiological system (FBS) (Medin and Atran, 2004) reflects a universal human tendency, observed across cultures, to classify the living world into ranked, species-like taxonomies while attributing an “essence” to organisms—intrinsic, immutable properties inherited from their parents that determine their observable characteristics (Atran, 1998, 1999, 2002; Medin and Atran, 2004). The FBS shows notable differences between modern industrialized societies and non-WEIRD societies. For instance, children in industrialized societies often categorize humans as separate from animals earlier in life, while children in non-WEIRD societies are more likely to see humans as another type of animal at a similar developmental stage (Medin et al., 2010). Additionally, both children and adults in non-industrialized societies are more inclined to emphasize ecological relationships between living beings compared to their counterparts in majority-culture societies (Ross et al., 2003; Medin et al., 2006; Bang et al., 2007). A compelling example of evolved cognitive strategies within FBS is the Plant Learning and Avoidance of Natural Toxins (PLANT) system, which comprises behavioral strategies and social learning rules for reasoning about plants (Wertz, 2019). Infants exhibit a clear avoidance response, demonstrating reluctance to touch plants compared to other objects (Wertz and Wynn, 2014). Toxic plant avoidance is also observed in non-human animals, demonstrating evolved strategies to mitigate the risks associated with plant defenses. For instance, herbivores employ mechanisms like post-ingestive feedback, as seen in sheep, which learn to avoid harmful plants through negative physiological experiences (Provenza, 1995; Karban and Agrawal, 2002). In humans, this response manifests as food neophobia, the reluctance or fear of trying new foods (Pliner and Hobden, 1992; Pliner and Salvy, 2006). This tendency is particularly pronounced for plant-based foods, likely as an adaptive mechanism to protect infants from ingesting plant toxins once they become mobile and capable of independently selecting food (Cashdan, 1998; Wertz and Wynn, 2014, 2019; Włodarczyk et al., 2018). Evidence for this mechanism comes from the inverse relationship between food neophobia and vegetable consumption in both children (Johnson et al., 2015; Xi et al., 2022; Estay et al., 2023) and adults (Jaeger et al., 2017; Costa et al., 2020) and from the observation that neophobia scores increase between ages 1 and 2 across different cultural backgrounds, coinciding with the period when infants begin to gain mobility (Estay et al., 2023).

Building on the concept of dissociation, it is possible to map modules and their subcomponents onto the corresponding disruptions observed in various neuropsychiatric disorders. In some cases, clinically relevant dysfunctions align closely with specific modular failures, occasionally in a one-to-one correspondence. For instance, within the intuitive mechanics module, deficits often align along the what/where distinction (Putcha et al., 2021). Impairments in tracking the identity of objects manifest as an inability to recognize objects (Farah, 2004), familiar places (Landis et al., 1986), faces (Kanwisher et al., 1997; Kanwisher and Yovel, 2006), or text (Cohen et al., 2000). Spatiotemporal tracking deficits include topographical disorientation, where patients struggle to use landmarks for visuospatial navigation (Aguirre and D'Esposito, 1999; Erkkinen et al., 2021), and difficulty perceiving the motion of objects (Zihl et al., 1983; Stevens et al., 2009). Some lesions affect entire modular subcomponents, as seen in the case of patient RS. Following an ischemic stroke affecting the left posterior cerebral artery, patient RS exhibited a disproportionate semantic impairment specifically for fruits and vegetables, while knowledge of animals and artifacts remained relatively preserved (Samson and Pillon, 2003). Dyscalculia offers another example, resulting from impairment to the “number sense,” defined as the “ability to quickly understand, approximate, and manipulate numerical quantities” (Dehaene, 2001). Additionally, lesions can affect distinctions between animate and inanimate entities. Brain injuries frequently result in disproportionately severe impairments in recognizing and reasoning about living things compared to inanimate objects (Caramazza and Shelton, 1998; Forde, 1999; Humphreys and Forde, 2001; Tyler and Moss, 2001; Capitani et al., 2003; Mahon and Caramazza, 2009). This distinction is fundamental, present from early development in humans (Greif et al., 2006), and observed even in blind individuals (Mahon et al., 2009). Knowledge about animals and plants holds a privileged status in the brain due to its critical role in human survival—animals as predators or sources of food, plants as food or toxin-producers—with their specialized yet vulnerable neural representation reflected in the disproportionate impairment of these biological categories in semantic deficits (Caramazza and Shelton, 1998; Capitani et al., 2003).

Classical nosologic syndromes also exhibit disruptions in shared modular components. For example, studies of autistic children consistently show significant impairments in passing the false-belief task, despite intact capacities in non-mentalistic tasks (Baron-Cohen et al., 1985; Baron-Cohen, 1995, 1997). However, mindreading involves more than false-belief reasoning as already seen. It includes components like shared attention mechanisms (Baron-Cohen, 1997; Tomasello et al., 2005; Tomasello, 2019) and gaze detection mechanisms (Baron-Cohen, 1995, 1997). Autistic children often exhibit deficits in shared attention (Rogers and Pennington, 1991; Carpenter et al., 2001; Mundy and Newell, 2007), struggle to follow others' gaze in social contexts (Leekam et al., 1997; Nation and Penny, 2008), fail to direct their gaze toward social stimuli (Dawson et al., 1998), and show impairments in initiating joint attention, which involves using eye contact to direct others' attention to an object or event (Mundy, 2003). In schizophrenia, dysfunction spans multiple modules. It has been suggested that schizophrenia represents “the price that Homo sapiens pays for language” (Crow, 1997, 2000, 2008). Indeed, schizophrenia patients exhibit significant language deficits, including difficulties in comprehension (Kuperberg, 2010a; Perlini et al., 2012), higher-order language processing (Kuperberg, 2010b), decreased production of syntactically complex sentences (DeLisi, 2001; Kircher et al., 2005), and impairments in semantics (Goldberg and Weinberger, 2000; Salavera et al., 2013) and pragmatics (Kuperberg et al., 1998; Covington et al., 2005; Perlini et al., 2012; Salavera et al., 2013). Furthermore, they demonstrate significant deficits in mindreading tasks (Brüne, 2005) and struggle to comprehend conceptual metaphors, a phenomenon referred to as concretism (Rossetti et al., 2018). For instance, when asked to interpret the figurative expression “A rolling stone gathers no moss,” patients with schizophrenia might provide a literal interpretation such as “Because the stone is rolling, there's no time for the moss to attach to it.”

The breakdown of a modular system extends beyond semantic impairments, impacting developmental changes and the causal mechanisms underlying biological concepts (Zaitchik and Solomon, 2001). For example, the development of the FBS progresses from an early behavioral theory—focused on motion—to a mature biological theory encompassing life cycles and bodily processes such as respiration, birth, growth, disease, and death (Carey, 1985). Early in development, children exhibit animistic tendencies, categorizing independently moving objects, including inanimate ones like the sun, fire, or cars, as “alive” (Carey, 1985; but also see Barrett and Behne, 2005). During this stage, essentialist thinking—wherein an organism's intrinsic “essence” is seen as immutable—is absent, leading children to believe that an animal's identity could change based on superficial appearance (reviewed in Solomon and Zaitchik, 2012). These developmental phenomena re-emerge in conditions like Alzheimer's disease (AD). Zaitchik and Solomon (2008) documented that AD patients often attribute life to inanimate objects capable of self-generated activity, such as cars or fire, reflecting a regression to animistic thinking (Zaitchik and Solomon, 2008). Furthermore, AD patients demonstrate impaired essentialism, as shown in their performance on Keil's Species Transformation Task (Zaitchik and Solomon, 2009). In this task, about half of the AD patients believed that superficial changes, like painting stripes on a horse to resemble a zebra or dressing a chicken in a turkey costume, could cause the animal to cross species boundaries. These findings underscore how classification along modular lines offers a deeper understanding of the causal principles within a conceptual domain, surpassing simplistic interpretations of semantic impairments.

In some classical psychiatric phenomena, modular elements manifest clinically at the interfaces between different cognitive and perceptual domains. For instance, animals, as a component of the FBS, are implicated in a range of disorders. Examples include animal phobias (Norberg et al., 2024), animal hallucinations (Platz et al., 1995; Fénelon et al., 2000; Ffytche, 2005), and lycanthropy, the delusional belief of transforming into a wolf (Keck et al., 1988; Khalil et al., 2012; Blom, 2014; Guessoum et al., 2021). Other phenomena related to this modular system include zooanthroprosopmetamorphopsia, where individuals perceive human faces morphing into animal faces (Blom et al., 2021; Blom, 2023), Noah's Syndrome (animal hoarding) (Patronek, 1999; Ferreira et al., 2017; Abreu and Marques, 2022; Nadal et al., 2022; Stumpf et al., 2023), delusional parasitosis, characterized by the belief of infestation with crawling pathogens (Trabert, 1995; Freudenmann and Lepping, 2009), and the Dolittle phenomenon, where individuals experience animals speaking (Dening and West, 1990; Hirsch, 2023). In the context of musicality, the cognitive processes underlying music perception and behavior (Honing and Ploeger, 2012; Honing, 2018), examples include musical anhedonia, characterized by an inability to derive pleasure from music despite experiencing normal enjoyment in other areas of life (Mas-Herrero et al., 2014), musical hallucinations, where individuals perceive music that is not externally present (Blom, 2023), and musical obsessions, which involve involuntary and intrusive musical thoughts or tunes that align with the criteria for obsessions (Taylor et al., 2014).

A modular framework can also provide insights into comorbidity between psychiatric disorders. Disorders affecting overlapping modules often share clinical features. Theoretically, if Disorder 1 involves dysfunctions in modules A, B, and C, and Disorder 2 involves dysfunctions in modules C, D, and E, their symptomatology would overlap due to the shared impairment in module C. For example, dysfunctions in mindreading modules are commonly observed in autism spectrum disorders (Baron-Cohen et al., 1985; Baron-Cohen, 1995, 1997, 2000), schizophrenia (Abu-Akel, 1999; Abu-Akel and Bailey, 2000; Brüne, 2005), bipolar disorder, major depressive disorder, social anxiety disorder, eating disorders, and borderline personality disorder (reviewed in de la Higuera-González et al., 2023). These shared dysfunctions help explain overlapping symptoms, such as difficulties in social cognition, across these conditions.

10 Discussion

The mind conceived as an assemblage of evolved information-processing modules offers a powerful organizing principle for understanding many phenomena of psychiatric interest, including selfhood disorders, intrapersonal conflict, and even the classification of mental conditions along modular lines. In self-disorders, a dysfunctional minimal self may expose the mind's underlying modular architecture to conscious awareness, prompting a sudden and unsettling recognition of its internal multiplicity. A relaxed interpretation of information encapsulation, combined with the varied ways information is stored across different parts of the mind, could illuminate the inconsistencies in thought and behavior that underpin intrapsychic conflict. Well-defined clinical disorders could help bolster support for proposed mental modules or suggest novel ones. Conversely, mapping the modular framework onto neuropsychiatric syndromes can enhance our parsing of clinical reality and refine our conceptualization of psychiatric illness, enabling a more nuanced recognition of patients' lived experiences and, in turn, deepening our empathic understanding of their suffering. In conclusion, should cognitive modularity persist as a biologically plausible and empirically validated framework, it would resonate profoundly with the core phenomena that psychiatry has grappled with for over two centuries.

Data availability statement

The original contributions presented in the study are included in the article/supplementary material, further inquiries can be directed to the corresponding author.

Author contributions

GI: Conceptualization, Writing – original draft, Writing – review & editing. AJ: Supervision, Writing – review & editing.

Funding

The author(s) declare that no financial support was received for the research and/or publication of this article.

Conflict of interest

The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Generative AI statement

The author(s) declare that no Gen AI was used in the creation of this manuscript.

Publisher's note

All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article, or claim that may be made by its manufacturer, is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.

References

Abreu, L. M., and Marques, J. G. (2022). Noah syndrome: a review regarding animal hoarding with squalor. Innov. Clin. Neurosci. 19:48.

PubMed Abstract | Google Scholar

Abu-Akel, A. (1999). Impaired theory of mind in schizophrenia. PandC 7, 247–282. doi: 10.1075/pc.7.2.02abu

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Abu-Akel, A., and Bailey, A. (2000). The possibility of different forms of theory of mind impairment in psychiatric and developmental disorders. Psychol. Med. 30, 735–738. doi: 10.1017/S0033291799002123

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Aguirre, G. K., and D'Esposito, M. (1999). Topographical disorientation: a synthesis and taxonomy. Brain 122, 1613–1628. doi: 10.1093/brain/122.9.1613

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Alcalá-Corona, S. A., Sandoval-Motta, S., Espinal-Enríquez, J., and Hernández-Lemus, E. (2021). Modularity in biological networks. Front. Genet. 12:701331. doi: 10.3389/fgene.2021.701331

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Alphonsus, E., Fellin, L. C., Thoma, S., and Galbusera, L. (2023). They have taken out my spinal cord: an interpretative phenomenological analysis of self-boundary in psychotic experience within a sociocentric culture. Front. Psychiatry 14:1215412. doi: 10.3389/fpsyt.2023.1215412

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Al-Shawaf, L., Lewis, D. M. G., Barbaro, N., and Wehbe, Y. S. (2020). “The products of evolution: Conceptual distinctions, evidentiary criteria, and empirical examples,” in The SAGE handbook of evolutionary psychology: Foundations of evolutionary psychology (Sage Reference), 70–95. doi: 10.4135/9781529739442.n5

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

American Psychiatric Association (2022). Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders: DSM-5-TR. New York: American Psychiatric Association Publishing. doi: 10.1176/appi.books.9780890425787

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Anderson, M. L. (2010). Neural reuse: A fundamental organizational principle of the brain. Behav. Brain Sci. 33, 245–266. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X10000853

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Arminjon, M. (2011). The four postulates of freudian unconscious neurocognitive convergences. Front. Psychol. 2:125. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2011.00125

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Atkinson, A. P., and Wheeler, M. (2003). “Evolutionary psychology's grain problem and the cognitive neuroscience of reasoning,” in Evolution and the Psychology of Thinking: The Debate, ed. D. E. Over (London: Psychology Press), 61–99.

Google Scholar

Atran, S. (1998). Folk biology and the anthropology of science: cognitive universals and cultural particulars. Behav. Brain Sci. 21, 547–569. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X98001277

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Atran, S. (1999). “Itzaj maya folkbiological taxonomy: cognitive universals and cultural particulars,” in Folkbiology, eds. D. L. Medin and S. Atran (Cambridge: MIT Press), 119–213. doi: 10.7551/mitpress/3042.003.0007

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Atran, S. (2002). “Modular and cultural factors in biological understanding: an experimental approach to the cognitive basis of science,” in The Cognitive Basis of Science, eds. P. Carruthers, S. Stich, and M. Siegal (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 41–72. doi: 10.1017/CBO9780511613517.004

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Auchincloss, E. L., Samberg, E., and Association, A. P. (2012). Psychoanalytic Terms and Concepts. Yale University Press.

Google Scholar

Baddeley, A. (2003). Double dissociations: not magic, but still useful. Cortex 39, 129–131. doi: 10.1016/S0010-9452(08)70082-0

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Balachandran, N. (2011). A proposed taxonomy of human evolved psychological adaptations. J. Soc. Evolut. Cult. Psychol. 5, 194–207. doi: 10.1037/h0099264

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Balachandran, N., and Glass, D. J. (2012). Psychtable.org: the taxonomy of human evolved psychological adaptations. Evo. Edu. Outreach 5, 312–320. doi: 10.1007/s12052-012-0428-8

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Bang, M., Medin, D. L., and Atran, S. (2007). Cultural mosaics and mental models of nature. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 104, 13868–13874. doi: 10.1073/pnas.0706627104

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Barabasi, A.-L., and Oltvai, Z. N. (2004). Network biology: understanding the cell's functional organization. Nat. Rev. Genet. 5, 101–113. doi: 10.1038/nrg1272

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Baron-Cohen, S. (1995). Mindblindness: An Essay on Autism and Theory of Mind., First MIT Press paperback edition. Cambridge London: MIT Press. doi: 10.7551/mitpress/4635.001.0001

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Baron-Cohen, S. (1997). “How to build a baby that can read minds: cognitive mechanisms in mindreading,” in The Maladapted Mind (London: Psychology Press).

Google Scholar

Baron-Cohen, S. (2000). Autism and ‘theory of mind.' Appl. Psychol. 2, 1–20.

Google Scholar

Baron-Cohen, S., Leslie, A. M., and Frith, U. (1985). Does the autistic child have a “theory of mind”? Cognition 21, 37–46. doi: 10.1016/0010-0277(85)90022-8

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Barrett, H. C. (2005). Enzymatic computation and cognitive modularity. Mind Lang. 20, 259–287. doi: 10.1111/j.0268-1064.2005.00285.x

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Barrett, H. C. (2006). “Modularity and design reincarnation,” in The innate mind: culture and cognition, eds. P. Carruthers, S. Laurence and S. Stich (Oxford: Oxford Academic), 199–217. doi: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195310139.003.0013

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Barrett, H. C. (2007). “Modules in the flesh,” in The Evolution of Mind: Fundamental Questions and Controversies, 161–168.

Google Scholar

Barrett, H. C. (2009). “Where there is an adaptation, there is a domain: the form-function fit in information processing,” in Foundations in Evolutionary Cognitive Neuroscience, 97–116. doi: 10.1017/CBO9780511626586.004

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Barrett, H. C. (2012). A hierarchical model of the evolution of human brain specializations. Proc. Nat. Acad. Sci. 109, 10733–10740. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1201898109

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Barrett, H. C. (2015). The Shape of Thought: How Mental Adaptations Evolve. New York: Oxford University Press. doi: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199348305.001.0001

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Barrett, H. C. (2017). “Diversity and hierarchy in the evolution of mental mechanisms,” in On human nature (Elsevier), 467–474. doi: 10.1016/B978-0-12-420190-3.00028-4

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Barrett, H. C. (2020a). “The search for human cognitive specializations,” in Evolutionary Neuroscience (Elsevier), 917–929. doi: 10.1016/B978-0-12-820584-6.00039-8

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Barrett, H. C. (2020b). Towards a cognitive science of the human: cross-cultural approaches and their urgency. Trends Cogn. Sci. 24, 620–638. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2020.05.007

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Barrett, H. C., and Behne, T. (2005). Children's understanding of death as the cessation of agency: a test using sleep versus death. Cognition 96, 93–108. doi: 10.1016/j.cognition.2004.05.004

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Barrett, H. C., Broesch, T., Scott, R. M., He, Z., Baillargeon, R., Wu, D., et al. (2013). Early false-belief understanding in traditional non-Western societies. Proc. R. Soc. B. 280:20122654. doi: 10.1098/rspb.2012.2654

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Barrett, H. C., Frederick, D. A., Haselton, M. G., and Kurzban, R. (2006). Can manipulations of cognitive load be used to test evolutionary hypotheses? J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 91, 513–518. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.91.3.513

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Barrett, H. C., and Kurzban, R. (2006). Modularity in cognition: framing the debate. Psychol. Rev. 113, 628–647. doi: 10.1037/0033-295X.113.3.628

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Barrett, H. C., Laurence, S., and Margolis, E. (2008). Artifacts and original intent: a cross-cultural perspective on the design stance. J. Cogn. Cult. 8, 1–22. doi: 10.1163/156770908X289189

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Barrett, J. L. (2004). “Finding agents everywhere,” in Why Would Anyone Believe in God? (AltaMira Press).

Google Scholar

Bedford, P., Hauke, D. J., Wang, Z., Roth, V., Nagy-Huber, M., Holze, F., et al. (2023). The effect of lysergic acid diethylamide (LSD) on whole-brain functional and effective connectivity. Neuropsychopharmacology 48, 1175–1183. doi: 10.1038/s41386-023-01574-8

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Berkowitz, A. L. (2022). Clinical Neurology and Neuroanatomy: A Localization-Based Approach, Second Edition. New York: McGraw Hill Professional.

Google Scholar

Bermúdez, J. L. (2019). Bodily ownership, psychological ownership, and psychopathology. Rev.Phil.Psych. 10, 263–280. doi: 10.1007/s13164-018-0406-3

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Berrios, G. E., and Luque, R. (1995). Cotard's syndrome: analysis of 100 cases. Acta Psychiatr. Scand. 91, 185–188. doi: 10.1111/j.1600-0447.1995.tb09764.x

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Berrios, G. E., and Marková, I. S. (2003). “The self and psychiatry: a conceptual history,” in The Self in Neuroscience and Psychiatry, eds. A. David and T. Kircher (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 9–39. doi: 10.1017/CBO9780511543708.002

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Blanke, O., and Metzinger, T. (2009). Full-body illusions and minimal phenomenal selfhood. Trends Cogn. Sci. 13, 7–13. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2008.10.003

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Blom, J. D. (2014). When doctors cry wolf: a systematic review of the literature on clinical lycanthropy. Hist. Psychiatry 25, 87–102. doi: 10.1177/0957154X13512192

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Blom, J. D. (2016). Alice in Wonderland syndrome: a systematic review. Neur. Clin. Pract. 6, 259–270. doi: 10.1212/CPJ.0000000000000251

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Blom, J. D. (2023). A Dictionary of Hallucinations. Cham: Springer International Publishing. doi: 10.1007/978-3-031-25248-8

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Blom, J. D., Ter Meulen, B. C., and Dool, J. (2021). A century of prosopometamorphopsia studies. Cortex 139, 298–308. doi: 10.1016/j.cortex.2021.03.001

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Bolhuis, J. J., Brown, G. R., Richardson, R. C., and Laland, K. N. (2011). Darwin in mind: new opportunities for evolutionary psychology. PLoS Biol. 9:e1001109. doi: 10.1371/journal.pbio.1001109

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Boronat, C. B., Buxbaum, L. J., Coslett, H. B., Tang, K., Saffran, E. M., Kimberg, D. Y., et al. (2005). Distinctions between manipulation and function knowledge of objects: evidence from functional magnetic resonance imaging. Cogn. Brain Res. 23, 361–373. doi: 10.1016/j.cogbrainres.2004.11.001

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Boyer, P., and Barrett, H. C. (2015). “Intuitive ontologies and domain specificity,” in The Handbook of Evolutionary Psychology, (John Wiley and Sons. Ltd), 1–19. doi: 10.1002/9781119125563.evpsych105

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Brakel, L. A. W. (2004). The psychoanalytic assumption of the primary process: extrapsychoanalytic evidence and findings. J. Am. Psychoanal. Assoc. 52, 1131–1161. doi: 10.1177/00030651040520040201

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Brakel, L. A. W. (2018). The primary process: bridges to interdisciplinary studies of mind. Psychoanalytic Inquiry 38, 177–185. doi: 10.1080/07351690.2018.1430964

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Brase, G. L. (2002). Mental modularity, metaphors, and the marriage of evolutionary and cognitive sciences. Cogn. Proc. 3, 3–17.

Google Scholar

Brase, G. L. (2014). Behavioral science integration: a practical framework of multi-level converging evidence for behavioral science theories. New Ideas Psychol. 33, 8–20. doi: 10.1016/j.newideapsych.2013.11.001

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Brase, G. L. (2021). “Adaptive problems,” in The SAGE handbook of evolutionary psychology: Foundations of evolutionary psychology (Sage Reference), 34–55. doi: 10.4135/9781529739442.n3

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Browne, J. L., Krabbendam, L., and Blom, J. D. (2024). Akinetopsia: a systematic review on visual motion blindness. Front. Neurol. 15:1510807. doi: 10.3389/fneur.2024.1510807

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Brüne, M. (2005). “Theory of mind” in schizophrenia: a review of the literature. Schizophr. Bull. 31, 21–42. doi: 10.1093/schbul/sbi002

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Brüne, M. (2016). Borderline Personality Disorder: Why “fast and furious”? Evol. Med. Public Health 2016, 52–66. doi: 10.1093/emph/eow002

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Bullmore, E., and Sporns, O. (2012). The economy of brain network organization. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 13, 336–349. doi: 10.1038/nrn3214

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Burgin, S., Reniers, R., and Humpston, C. (2022). Prevalence and assessment of self-disorders in the schizophrenia spectrum: a systematic review and meta-analysis. Sci. Rep. 12:1165. doi: 10.1038/s41598-022-05232-9

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Burkart, J. M., Schubiger, M. N., and van Schaik, C. P. (2017). The evolution of general intelligence. Behav. Brain Sci. 40:e195. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X17000024

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Bush, G., Fink, M., Petrides, G., Dowling, F., and Francis, A. (1996). Catatonia. I. Rating scale and standardized examination. Acta Psychiatr. Scand. 93, 129–136. doi: 10.1111/j.1600-0447.1996.tb09814.x

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Buss, D. (1991). Evolutionary personality psychology. Annu. Rev. Psychol. 42, 459–491. doi: 10.1146/annurev.ps.42.020191.002331

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Buss, D. (1995). Evolutionary psychology: a new paradigm for psychological science. Psychol. Inq. 6, 1–30. doi: 10.1207/s15327965pli0601_1

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Buss, D. (2019). Evolutionary Psychology: The New Science of the Mind. London: Routledge. doi: 10.4324/9780429061417

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Buxbaum, L. J., and Saffran, E. M. (2002). Knowledge of object manipulation and object function: dissociations in apraxic and nonapraxic subjects. Brain Lang. 82, 179–99. doi: 10.1016/S0093-934X(02)00014-7

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Buxbaum, L. J., Veramontil, T., and Schwartz, M. F. (2000). Function and manipulation tool knowledge in apraxia: knowing ‘what for' but not ‘how.' Neurocase 6, 83–97. doi: 10.1080/13554790008402763

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Cabaniss, D. L. (2017). Psychodynamic Psychotherapy: A Clinical Manual. Second Edition. New York: John Wiley and Sons. doi: 10.1002/9781119142010

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Call, J., and Tomasello, M. (2008). Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? 30 years later. Trends Cogn. Sci. 12, 187–192. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2008.02.010

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Capitani, E., Laiacona, M., Mahon, B., and Caramazza, A. (2003). What are the facts of semantic category-specific deficits? A critical review of the clinical evidence. Cogn. Neuropsychol. 20, 213–261. doi: 10.1080/02643290244000266

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Caramazza, A., and Coltheart, M. (2006). Cognitive neuropsychology twenty years on. Cogn. Neuropsychol. 23, 3–12. doi: 10.1080/02643290500443250

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Caramazza, A., and Shelton, J. R. (1998). Domain-specific knowledge systems in the brain: the animate-inanimate distinction. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 10, 1–34. doi: 10.1162/089892998563752

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Carey, S. (1985). Conceptual Change in Childhood. Cambridge: MIT Press.

Google Scholar

Carey, S. (2009). The Origin of Concepts. Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195367638.001.0001

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Carhart-Harris, R. L., Leech, R., Erritzoe, D., Williams, T. M., Stone, J. M., Evans, J., et al. (2013). Functional connectivity measures after psilocybin inform a novel hypothesis of early psychosis. Schizophr. Bull. 39, 1343–1351. doi: 10.1093/schbul/sbs117

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Carhart-Harris, R. L., Leech, R., Hellyer, P. J., Shanahan, M., Feilding, A., Tagliazucchi, E., et al. (2014). The entropic brain: a theory of conscious states informed by neuroimaging research with psychedelic drugs. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 8:20. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2014.00020

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Carhart-Harris, R. L., Muthukumaraswamy, S., Roseman, L., Kaelen, M., Droog, W., Murphy, K., et al. (2016). Neural correlates of the LSD experience revealed by multimodal neuroimaging. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA. 113, 4853–4858. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1518377113

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Carpenter, M., Pennington, B. F., and Rogers, S. J. (2001). Understanding of others' intentions in children with autism and children with developmental delays. J. Autism Dev. Disord. 31, 589–599. doi: 10.1023/A:1013251112392

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Carruthers, P. (2006). The Architecture of the Mind: Massive Modularity and the Flexibility of Thought. Oxford: Clarendon Press; Oxford University Press. doi: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199207077.001.0001

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Carruthers, P. (2008). On fodor-fixation, flexibility, and human uniqueness: a reply to cowie, machery, and wilson. Mind Lang. 23, 293–303. doi: 10.1111/j.1468-0017.2008.00344.x

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Casey, P., and Kelly, B. (2019). Fish's Clinical Psychopathology: Signs and Symptoms in Psychiatry., 4th Edn. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi: 10.1017/9781108578264

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Cashdan, E. (1998). Adaptiveness of food learning and food aversions in children. Soc. Sci. Inf. 37, 613–632. doi: 10.1177/053901898037004003

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Chambon, V., Moore, J. W., and Haggard, P. (2015). TMS stimulation over the inferior parietal cortex disrupts prospective sense of agency. Brain Struct. Funct. 220, 3627–3639. doi: 10.1007/s00429-014-0878-6

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Cheverud, J. M. (1996). Developmental integration and the evolution of pleiotropy. Am. Zool. 36, 44–50. doi: 10.1093/icb/36.1.44

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Clayton, N. S., Dally, J. M., and Emery, N. J. (2007). Social cognition by food-caching corvids. The western scrub-jay as a natural psychologist. Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B 362, 507–522. doi: 10.1098/rstb.2006.1992

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Cohen, L., Dehaene, S., Naccache, L., Lehéricy, S., Dehaene-Lambertz, G., Hénaff, M.-A., et al. (2000). The visual word form area: spatial and temporal characterization of an initial stage of reading in normal subjects and posterior split-brain patients. Brain 123, 291–307. doi: 10.1093/brain/123.2.291

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Collective, T. P. F. (2022). Psychodynamic Formulation: An Expanded Approach., 2. edition. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley and Sons.

Google Scholar

Cosmides, L., and Tooby, J. (1997). Evolutionary psychology: A primer. Center for Evolutionary Psychology, Santa Barbara. Available at: https://www.cep.ucsb.edu/wp-content/uploads/2023/06/Evolutionary-Psychology-A-Primer-CosmidesTooby1993.pdf (accessed June 10, 2024).

Google Scholar

Cosmides, L., and Tooby, J. (1999). Toward an evolutionary taxonomy of treatable conditions. J. Abnorm. Psychol. 108, 453–464. doi: 10.1037/0021-843X.108.3.453

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Cosmides, L., and Tooby, J. (2013). “Unraveling the enigma of human intelligence: evolutionary psychology and the multimodular mind,” in The Evolution of Intelligence (New York: Psychology Press), 145–198.

Google Scholar

Costa, A., Silva, C., and Oliveira, A. (2020). Food neophobia and its association with food preferences and dietary intake of adults. Nutr. Dietet. 77, 542–549. doi: 10.1111/1747-0080.12587

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Covington, M. A., He, C., Brown, C., Naçi, L., McClain, J. T., Fjordbak, B. S., et al. (2005). Schizophrenia and the structure of language: the linguist's view. Schizophr. Res. 77, 85–98. doi: 10.1016/j.schres.2005.01.016

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Crow, T. J. (1997). Is schizophrenia the price that Homo sapiens pays for language? Schizophr. Res. 28, 127–141. doi: 10.1016/S0920-9964(97)00110-2

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Crow, T. J. (2000). Schizophrenia as the price that Homo sapiens pays for language: a resolution of the central paradox in the origin of the species. Brain Res. Rev. 31, 118–129. doi: 10.1016/S0165-0173(99)00029-6

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Crow, T. J. (2008). The ‘big bang' theory of the origin of psychosis and the faculty of language. Schizophr. Res. 102, 31–52. doi: 10.1016/j.schres.2008.03.010

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Cui, L.-B., Wei, Y., Xi, Y.-B., Griffa, A., De Lange, S. C., Kahn, R. S., et al. (2019). Connectome-based patterns of first-episode medication-naïve patients with schizophrenia. Schizophr. Bull. 45, 1291–1299. doi: 10.1093/schbul/sbz014

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Damasio, A. (2000). The Feeling of What Happens: Body, Emotion and the Making of Consciousness. Vintage.

Google Scholar

Damasio, A. (2006). Descartes' Error: Emotion, Reason and the Human Brain. New York: Vintage.

Google Scholar

Damasio, A. R., Damasio, H., and Van Hoesen, G. W. (1982). Prosopagnosia: anatomic basis and behavioral mechanisms. Neurology 32, 331–331. doi: 10.1212/WNL.32.4.331

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Damasio, A. R., Everitt, B. J., and Bishop, D. (1996). The somatic marker hypothesis and the possible functions of the prefrontal cortex [and discussion]. Philos. Trans. 351, 1413–1420. doi: 10.1098/rstb.1996.0125

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

David, A. S. (1994). Dysmodularity: a neurocognitive model for schizophrenia. Schizophr. Bull. 20, 249–255. doi: 10.1093/schbul/20.2.249

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Davidson, E. H., and Erwin, D. H. (2006). Gene regulatory networks and the evolution of animal body plans. Science 311, 796–800. doi: 10.1126/science.1113832

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Dawson, G., Meltzoff, A. N., Osterling, J., Rinaldi, J., and Brown, E. (1998). Children with autism fail to orient to naturally occurring social stimuli. J. Autism Dev. Disord. 28, 479–485. doi: 10.1023/A:1026043926488

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

de la Higuera-González, P., Galvez-Merlin, A., Rodríguez-Toscano, E., Andreo-Jover, J., and de la Torre-Luque, A. (2023). “Theory of mind and psychopathology: a comprehensive assessment and an overview of impairments in neuropsychiatric disorders,” in The Theory of Mind Under Scrutiny: Psychopathology, Neuroscience, Philosophy of Mind and Artificial Intelligence, eds. T. Lopez-Soto, A. Garcia-Lopez, and F. J. Salguero-Lamillar (Cham: Springer Nature Switzerland), 103–160. doi: 10.1007/978-3-031-46742-4_5

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Debat, V., Alibert, P., David, P., Paradis, E., and Auffray, J.-C. (2000). Independence between developmental stability and canalization in the skull of the house mouse. Proc. R. Soc. Lond. B 267, 423–430. doi: 10.1098/rspb.2000.1017

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

DeBruine, L. M., Jones, B. C., Crawford, J. R., Welling, L. L. M., and Little, A. C. (2010). The health of a nation predicts their mate preferences: cross-cultural variation in women's preferences for masculinized male faces. Proc. R. Soc. B. 277, 2405–2410. doi: 10.1098/rspb.2009.2184

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Debruyne, H., Portzky, M., Van Den Eynde, F., and Audenaert, K. (2009). Cotard's syndrome: a review. Curr. Psychiatry Rep. 11, 197–202. doi: 10.1007/s11920-009-0031-z

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Decety, J., and Jackson, P. L. (2004). The functional architecture of human empathy. Behav. Cogn. Neurosci. Rev. 3, 71–100. doi: 10.1177/1534582304267187

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Decety, J., and Svetlova, M. (2012). Putting together phylogenetic and ontogenetic perspectives on empathy. Dev. Cogn. Neurosci. 2, 1–24. doi: 10.1016/j.dcn.2011.05.003

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Defeyter, M. A., and German, T. P. (2003). Acquiring an understanding of design: evidence from children's insight problem solving. Cognition 89, 133–155. doi: 10.1016/S0010-0277(03)00098-2

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Dehaene, S. (2001). Précis of the number sense. Mind Lang. 16, 16–36. doi: 10.1111/1468-0017.00154

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Del Giudice, M. (2018). Evolutionary Psychopathology: A Unified Approach. Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi: 10.1093/med-psych/9780190246846.001.0001

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Del Giudice, M. (2024). A Turning Point for the Life History Approach to Individual Differences. Available at: https://marcodg.net/wp-content/uploads/2024/05/delgiudice_life-history-approach_chapter_pre_v1.pdf (accessed March 15, 2025).

Google Scholar

Del Giudice, M., and Haltigan, J. D. (2023). An integrative evolutionary framework for psychopathology. Dev. Psychopathol. 35, 1–11. doi: 10.1017/S0954579421000870

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

DeLisi, L. E. (2001). Speech disorder in schizophrenia: review of the literature and exploration of its relation to the uniquely human capacity for language. Schizophr. Bull. 27, 481–496. doi: 10.1093/oxfordjournals.schbul.a006889

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Dening, T. R., and West, A. (1990). The dolittle phenomenon: hallucinatory voices from animals. Psychopathology 23, 40–45. doi: 10.1159/000284636

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Dennett, D. C. (1990). The interpretation of texts, people and other artifacts. Philos. Phenomenol. Res. 50, 177–194. doi: 10.2307/2108038

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Dieguez, S. (2018). Cotard syndrome. Front. Neurol. Neurosci. 42, 23–34. doi: 10.1159/000475679

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Ditzinger, T. (2021). “Fourth journey: ambiguous perception,” in Illusions of Seeing: Exploring the World of Visual Perception, ed. T. Ditzinger (Cham: Springer International Publishing), 67–94. doi: 10.1007/978-3-030-63635-7_4

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Dorahy, M. J., Brand, B. L., Sar, V., Krüger, C., Stavropoulos, P., Martínez-Taboas, A., et al. (2014). Dissociative identity disorder: an empirical overview. Aust. N. Z. J. Psychiatry 48, 402–417. doi: 10.1177/0004867414527523

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Douglas, K. M. (2020). “Hypersensitive Agency Detection,” in Encyclopedia of Personality and Individual Differences, eds. V. Zeigler-Hill and T. K. Shackelford (Cham: Springer International Publishing), 2097–2098. doi: 10.1007/978-3-319-24612-3_2273

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Dunn, J. C., and Kirsner, K. (2003). What can we infer from double dissociations? Cortex 39, 1–8. doi: 10.1016/S0010-9452(08)70070-4

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Elliott, R., and Greenberg, L. S. (1997). Multiple voices in process-experiential therapy: dialogues between aspects of the self. J. Psychother. Integr. 7:225. doi: 10.1037/h0101127

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Erkkinen, M., Putcha, D., and Daffner, K. R. (2021). “Focal Neurobehavioral Syndromes,” in Neuropsychiatry and Behavioral Neurology: Principles and Practice, eds. D. A. Silbersweig, L. T. Safar, and K. R. Daffner (New York, NY: McGraw Hill).

Google Scholar

Ermer, E., Cosmides, L., and Tooby, J. (2007). “Functional specialization and the adaptationist program,” in The evolution of mind: Fundamental questions and controversies, 153–160.

Google Scholar

Estay, K., Zhong, F., and Guinard, J.-X. (2023). Food neophobia in early childhood: a cross cultural study. Food Qual. Prefer. 111:105001. doi: 10.1016/j.foodqual.2023.105001

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Farah, M. J. (1991). Cognitive neuropsychology: patterns of co-occurrence among the associative agnosias: implications for visual object representation. Cogn. Neuropsychol. 8, 1–19. doi: 10.1080/02643299108253364

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Farah, M. J. (2004). Visual Agnosia. Cambridge: MIT Press. doi: 10.7551/mitpress/7122.001.0001

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Farrer, C., and Frith, C. D. (2002). Experiencing oneself vs another person as being the cause of an action: the neural correlates of the experience of agency. Neuroimage 15, 596–603. doi: 10.1006/nimg.2001.1009

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Federici, A., Parma, V., Vicovaro, M., Radassao, L., Casartelli, L., and Ronconi, L. (2020). Anomalous perception of biological motion in autism: a conceptual review and meta-analysis. Sci. Rep. 10:4576. doi: 10.1038/s41598-020-61252-3

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Fénelon, G., Mahieux, F., Huon, R., and Ziégler, M. (2000). Hallucinations in Parkinson's disease: prevalence, phenomenology and risk factors. Brain 123, 733–745. doi: 10.1093/brain/123.4.733

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Ferreira, E. A., Paloski, L. H., Costa, D. B., Fiametti, V. S., De Oliveira, C. R., de Lima Argimon, I. I., et al. (2017). Animal hoarding disorder: a new psychopathology? Psychiatry Res. 258, 221–225. doi: 10.1016/j.psychres.2017.08.030

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Ffytche, D. H. (2005). Visual hallucinations and the charles bonnet syndrome. Curr. Psychiatry Rep. 7, 168–179. doi: 10.1007/s11920-005-0050-3

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Fincher, C. L., Thornhill, R., Murray, D. R., and Schaller, M. (2008). Pathogen prevalence predicts human cross-cultural variability in individualism/collectivism. Proc. R. Soc. B. 275, 1279–1285. doi: 10.1098/rspb.2008.0094

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Fodor, J. A. (1983). The Modularity of Mind. Cambridge: MIT Press. doi: 10.7551/mitpress/4737.001.0001

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Fodor, J. A. (2000). The Mind Doesn't Work That Way: The Scope and Limits of Computational Psychology. Cambridge: MIT Press. doi: 10.7551/mitpress/4627.001.0001

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Foong, J., Maier, M., Clark, C. A., Barker, G. J., Miller, D. H., and Ron, M. A. (2000). Neuropathological abnormalities of the corpus callosum in schizophrenia: a diffusion tensor imaging study. J. Neurol. Neurosur. Psychiat. 68, 242–244. doi: 10.1136/jnnp.68.2.242

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Forde, E. (1999). Category specific recognition impairments: a review of important case studies and influential theories. Aphasiology 13, 169–193. doi: 10.1080/026870399402172

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Fornito, A., Zalesky, A., and Breakspear, M. (2015). The connectomics of brain disorders. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 16, 159–172. doi: 10.1038/nrn3901

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Francis, A. N., Mothi, S. S., Mathew, I. T., Tandon, N., Clementz, B., Pearlson, G. D., et al. (2016). Callosal abnormalities across the psychosis dimension: bipolar schizophrenia network on intermediate phenotypes. Biol. Psychiatry 80, 627–635. doi: 10.1016/j.biopsych.2015.12.026

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Freitag, C. M., Konrad, C., Häberlen, M., Kleser, C., von Gontard, A., Reith, W., et al. (2008). Perception of biological motion in autism spectrum disorders. Neuropsychologia 46, 1480–1494. doi: 10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2007.12.025

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Freud, A. (1984). Das Ich und die Abwehrmechanismen., 26. FISCHER Taschenbuch.

Google Scholar

Freud, S. (2019). Das Ich und das Es (1923) in Sigmund Freud: Sämtliche Werke und Briefe. Pandora Verlag.

Google Scholar

Freudenmann, R. W., and Lepping, P. (2009). Delusional Infestation. Clin. Microbiol. Rev. 22, 690–732. doi: 10.1128/CMR.00018-09

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Friston, K. J., and Frith, C. D. (1995). Schizophrenia: a disconnection syndrome. Clin. Neurosci. 3, 89–97.

Google Scholar

Frith, C. D. (2014). The Cognitive Neuropsychology of Schizophrenia. New York: Psychology press. doi: 10.4324/9781315785011

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Frith, C. D., and Done, D. J. (1988). Towards a neuropsychology of schizophrenia. Br J. Psychiat. 153, 437–443. doi: 10.1192/bjp.153.4.437

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Fuchs, T. (2005a). Corporealized and disembodied minds: a phenomenological view of the body in melancholia and schizophrenia. Philos. Psychiat. Psychol. 12, 95–107.

Google Scholar

Fuchs, T. (2005b). The phenomenology of body, space and time in depression. Comprendre 15, 108–121.

Google Scholar

Gabbard, G. O. (2014). Psychodynamic Psychiatry in Clinical Practice. New York: American Psychiatric Pub. doi: 10.1176/appi.books.9781615378395

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Gallagher, S., and Trigg, D. (2016). Agency and anxiety: delusions of control and loss of control in schizophrenia and agoraphobia. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 10:459. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2016.00459

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Gangestad, S. W., and Buss, D. M. (1993). Pathogen prevalence and human mate preferences. Ethol. Sociobiol. 14, 89–96. doi: 10.1016/0162-3095(93)90009-7

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Garcea, F. E., Dombovy, M., and Mahon, B. Z. (2013). Preserved tool knowledge in the context of impaired action knowledge: implications for models of semantic memory. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 7. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2013.00120

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Garcea, F. E., and Mahon, B. Z. (2012). What is in a tool concept? Dissociating manipulation knowledge from function knowledge. Mem. Cogn. 40, 1303–1313. doi: 10.3758/s13421-012-0236-y

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Gauthier, I., Skudlarski, P., Gore, J. C., and Anderson, A. W. (2000). Expertise for cars and birds recruits brain areas involved in face recognition. Nat. Neurosci. 3, 191–197. doi: 10.1038/72140

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Gazzaniga, M. (2012). Who's in Charge? Free Will and the Science of the Brain. Hachette UK: Ecco.

Google Scholar

Gazzaniga, M. S. (1977). On dividing the self: speculations from brain research. Excerpta Medica 434, 233–244.

PubMed Abstract | Google Scholar

Gazzaniga, M. S. (2005). Forty-five years of split-brain research and still going strong. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 6, 653–659. doi: 10.1038/nrn1723

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Gazzaniga, M. S. (2018). The Consciousness Instinct: Unraveling the Mystery of How the Brain Makes the Mind. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.

Google Scholar

Gazzaniga, M. S., Ivry, R., and Mangun, G. R. (2019). Cognitive Neuroscience: The Biology of the Mind. Fifth Edition. New York London: W.W. Norton and Company.

Google Scholar

Gazzaniga, M. S., and LeDoux, J. E. (1978). The Integrated Mind. Boston, MA: Springer. doi: 10.1007/978-1-4899-2206-9

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Gerlach, C., Lissau, C. H., and Hildebrandt, N. K. (2018). On defining and interpreting dissociations. Cogn. Neuropsychol. 35, 66–69. doi: 10.1080/02643294.2017.1414692

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

German, T. P., and Johnson, S. C. (2002). Function and the origins of the design stance. J. Cogn. Dev. 3, 279–300. doi: 10.1207/S15327647JCD0303_2

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Gilbert, P. (2000). “Social mentalities: internal ‘social' conflict and the role of inner warmth and compassion in cognitive therapy,” in Genes on the couch (Routledge), 118–150.

Google Scholar

Giudice, M. D., and Ellis, B. J. (2016). “Evolutionary foundations of developmental psychopathology,” in Developmental Psychopathology, ed. D. Cicchetti (Hoboken, NJ, USA: John Wiley and Sons, Inc.), 1–58. doi: 10.1002/9781119125556.devpsy201

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Glass, D., and Balachandran, N. (2020). PsychTable.org: a tool for biopolitical researchers, policymakers, and citizens. Polit. Life Sci. 39, 1–6. doi: 10.1017/pls.2020.10

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Goldberg, T. E., and Weinberger, D. R. (2000). Thought disorder in schizophrenia: a reappraisal of older formulations and an overview of some recent studies. Cogn. Neuropsychiatry 5, 1–19. doi: 10.1080/135468000395790

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Goldstone, R. L., and Barsalou, L. W. (1998). Reuniting perception and conception. Cognition 65, 231–262. doi: 10.1016/S0010-0277(97)00047-4

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Goodale, M. A., Meenan, J. P., Bülthoff, H. H., Nicolle, D. A., Murphy, K. J., and Racicot, C. I. (1994). Separate neural pathways for the visual analysis of object shape in perception and prehension. Curr. Biol. 4, 604–610. doi: 10.1016/S0960-9822(00)00132-9

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Goodale, M. A., Milner, A. D., Jakobson, L. S., and Carey, D. P. (1991). A neurological dissociation between perceiving objects and grasping them. Nature 349, 154–156. doi: 10.1038/349154a0

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Greif, M. L., Kemler Nelson, D. G., Keil, F. C., and Gutierrez, F. (2006). What do children want to know about animals and artifacts? Domain-specific requests for information. Psychol. Sci. 17, 455–459. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9280.2006.01727.x

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Guessoum, S. B., Benoit, L., Minassian, S., Mallet, J., and Moro, M. R. (2021). Clinical lycanthropy, neurobiology, culture: a systematic review. Front. Psychiatry 12:718101. doi: 10.3389/fpsyt.2021.718101

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Hadjikhani, N., Kveraga, K., Naik, P., and Ahlfors, S. P. (2009). Early (M170) activation of face-specific cortex by face-like objects. Neuroreport 20, 403–407. doi: 10.1097/WNR.0b013e328325a8e1

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Han, S., Northoff, G., Vogeley, K., Wexler, B. E., Kitayama, S., and Varnum, M. E. W. (2013). A cultural neuroscience approach to the biosocial nature of the human Brain. Annu. Rev. Psychol. 64, 335–359. doi: 10.1146/annurev-psych-071112-054629

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Hare, B., Brown, M., Williamson, C., and Tomasello, M. (2002). The domestication of social cognition in dogs. Science 298, 1634–1636. doi: 10.1126/science.1072702

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Hartwell, L. H., Hopfield, J. J., Leibler, S., and Murray, A. W. (1999). From molecular to modular cell biology. Nature 402, C47–C52. doi: 10.1038/35011540

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Haxby, J. V., Gobbini, M. I., Furey, M. L., Ishai, A., Schouten, J. L., and Pietrini, P. (2001). Distributed and overlapping representations of faces and objects in ventral temporal cortex. Science 293, 2425–2430. doi: 10.1126/science.1063736

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Heilman, K. M. (2010). Apraxia. Continuum 16, 86–108. doi: 10.1212/01.CON.0000368262.53662.08

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Henriksen, M. G., and Nordgaard, J. (2016). “Self-disorders in schizophrenia,” in An Experiential Approach to Psychopathology: What is it like to Suffer from Mental Disorders?, eds. G. Stanghellini and M. Aragona (Cham: Springer International Publishing), 265–280. doi: 10.1007/978-3-319-29945-7_14

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Henriksen, M. G., Parnas, J., and Zahavi, D. (2019). Thought insertion and disturbed for-me-ness (minimal selfhood) in schizophrenia. Conscious. Cogn. 74:102770. doi: 10.1016/j.concog.2019.102770

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Henriksen, M. G., Raballo, A., and Nordgaard, J. (2021). Self-disorders and psychopathology: a systematic review. Lancet Psychiat. 8, 1001–1012. doi: 10.1016/S2215-0366(21)00097-3

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Hirsch, J. W. (2023). Opioid-induced doctor dolittle phenomenon. CNS Spectr. 28, 233–234. doi: 10.1017/S1092852923001608

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Honing, H. (2018). The Origins of Musicality. Cambridge: MIT Press. doi: 10.7551/mitpress/10636.001.0001

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Honing, H., and Ploeger, A. (2012). Cognition and the evolution of music: pitfalls and prospects. Top. Cogn. Sci. 4, 513–524. doi: 10.1111/j.1756-8765.2012.01210.x

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Horváth, L. (2024). “The narrative self and the minimal self,” in The Affective Core Self: The Role of the Unconscious and Retroactivity in Self-Constitution, ed. L. Horváth (Cham: Springer Nature Switzerland), 37–86. doi: 10.1007/978-3-031-56920-3_2

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Hovmand, O. R., Poulsen, E. D., and Arnfred, S. (2024). Assessment of the acute subjective psychedelic experience: a review of patient-reported outcome measures in clinical research on classical psychedelics. J. Psychopharmacol. 38, 19–32. doi: 10.1177/02698811231200019

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Huitzil, S., and Huepe, C. (2024). Life's building blocks: the modular path to multiscale complexity. Front. Syst. Biol. 4:1417800. doi: 10.3389/fsysb.2024.1417800

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Humphreys, G. W., and Forde, E. M. E. (2001). Hierarchies, similarity, and interactivity in object recognition: “Category-specific” neuropsychological deficits. Behav. Brain Sci. 24, 453–476. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X01004150

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Hurst, A. J., and Boe, S. G. (2022). Imagining the way forward: a review of contemporary motor imagery theory. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 16:1033493. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2022.1033493

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

International Society for the Study of Trauma and Dissociation (2011). Guidelines for treating dissociative identity disorder in adults, third revision. J. Trauma Dissoc. 12, 115–187. doi: 10.1080/15299732.2011.537247

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Jaeger, S. R., Rasmussen, M. A., and Prescott, J. (2017). Relationships between food neophobia and food intake and preferences: findings from a sample of New Zealand adults. Appetite 116, 410–422. doi: 10.1016/j.appet.2017.05.030

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

James, T. W., Culham, J., Humphrey, G. K., Milner, A. D., and Goodale, M. A. (2003). Ventral occipital lesions impair object recognition but not object-directed grasping: an fMRI study. Brain 126, 2463–2475. doi: 10.1093/brain/awg248

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Jaspers, K. (1920). Allgemeine Psychopathologie für Studierende, Ärzte und Psychologen. Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer Berlin Heidelberg. doi: 10.1007/978-3-662-26726-4

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Jeong, H., Tombor, B., Albert, R., Oltvai, Z. N., and Barabási, A.-L. (2000). The large-scale organization of metabolic networks. Nature 407, 651–654. doi: 10.1038/35036627

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

John, P. C. L., Mews, M., and Moore, R. (2001). Cyclin/cdk complexes: Their involvement in cell cycle progression and mitotic division. Protoplasma 216, 119–142. doi: 10.1007/BF02673865

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Johnson, M. H. (2005). Subcortical face processing. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 6, 766–774. doi: 10.1038/nrn1766

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Johnson, S. L., Davies, P. L., Boles, R. E., Gavin, W. J., and Bellows, L. L. (2015). Young children's food neophobia characteristics and sensory behaviors are related to their food intake1,2. J. Nutr. 145, 2610–2616. doi: 10.3945/jn.115.217299

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Johnson-Frey, S. H. (2004). The neural bases of complex tool use in humans. Trends Cogn. Sci. 8, 71–78. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2003.12.002

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, Fast and Slow. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.

Google Scholar

Kanwisher, N. (2010). Functional specificity in the human brain: A window into the functional architecture of the mind. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 107, 11163–11170. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1005062107

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Kanwisher, N., McDermott, J., and Chun, M. M. (1997). The fusiform face area: a module in human extrastriate cortex specialized for face perception. J. Neurosci. 17, 4302–4311. doi: 10.1523/JNEUROSCI.17-11-04302.1997

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Kanwisher, N., and Yovel, G. (2006). The fusiform face area: a cortical region specialized for the perception of faces. Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B 361, 2109–2128. doi: 10.1098/rstb.2006.1934

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Karban, R., and Agrawal, A. A. (2002). Herbivore offense. Annu. Rev. Ecol. Syst. 33, 641–664. doi: 10.1146/annurev.ecolsys.33.010802.150443

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Karnath, H.-O., and Perenin, M.-T. (2005). Cortical control of visually guided reaching: evidence from patients with optic ataxia. Cerebral cortex 15, 1561–1569. doi: 10.1093/cercor/bhi034

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Keck, P. E., Pope, H. G., Hudson, J. I., McElroy, S. L., and Kulick, A. R. (1988). Lycanthropy: alive and well in the twentieth century. Psychol. Med. 18, 113–120. doi: 10.1017/S003329170000194X

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Kelemen, D., and Carey, S. (2007). “The essence of artifacts: developing the design stance,” in Creations of the Mind: Theories of Artifacts and Their Representation 212. doi: 10.1093/oso/9780199250981.003.0012

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Kelly, S., Jahanshad, N., Zalesky, A., Kochunov, P., Agartz, I., Alloza, C., et al. (2018). Widespread white matter microstructural differences in schizophrenia across 4322 individuals: results from the ENIGMA Schizophrenia DTI Working Group. Mol. Psychiatry 23, 1261–1269. doi: 10.1038/mp.2017.170

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Khalil, R. B., Dahdah, P., Richa, S., and Kahn, D. A. (2012). Lycanthropy as a culture-bound syndrome: a case report and review of the literature. J. Psychiatric Practice® 18, 51–54. doi: 10.1097/01.pra.0000410988.38723.a3

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Khan, S. (2023). “Dissociative identity disorder: theory vs. facts,” in Dissociative Identity Disorder: Treatment and Management, eds. H. Tohid and I. H. Rutkofsky (Cham: Springer International Publishing), 15–19. doi: 10.1007/978-3-031-39854-4_3

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Kim, J., Doop, M. L., Blake, R., and Park, S. (2005). Impaired visual recognition of biological motion in schizophrenia. Schizophr. Res. 77, 299–307. doi: 10.1016/j.schres.2005.04.006

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Kim, J., Norton, D., McBain, R., Ongur, D., and Chen, Y. (2013). Deficient biological motion perception in schizophrenia: results from a motion noise paradigm. Front. Psychol. 4:391. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00391

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Kircher, T. T., Oh, T. M., Brammer, M. J., and McGuire, P. K. (2005). Neural correlates of syntax production in schizophrenia. Br J. Psychiat. 186, 209–214. doi: 10.1192/bjp.186.3.209

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Klingenberg, C. P. (2008). Morphological integration and developmental modularity. Annu. Rev. Ecol. Evol. Syst. 39, 115–132. doi: 10.1146/annurev.ecolsys.37.091305.110054

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Kraehenmann, R. (2017). Dreams and Psychedelics: Neurophenomenological Comparison and Therapeutic Implications. Curr. Neuropharmacol. 15, 1032–1042. doi: 10.2174/1573413713666170619092629

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Kraehenmann, R., Pokorny, D., Aicher, H., Preller, K. H., Pokorny, T., Bosch, O. G., et al. (2017). LSD increases primary process thinking via serotonin 2A receptor activation. Front. Pharmacol. 8:814. doi: 10.3389/fphar.2017.00814

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Kubicki, M., Styner, M., Bouix, S., Gerig, G., Markant, D., Smith, K., et al. (2008). Reduced interhemispheric connectivity in schizophrenia-tractography based segmentation of the corpus callosum. Schizophr. Res. 106, 125–131. doi: 10.1016/j.schres.2008.08.027

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Kuperberg, G. R. (2010a). Language in schizophrenia part 1: an introduction. Lang. Linguist. Compass 4, 576–589. doi: 10.1111/j.1749-818X.2010.00216.x

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Kuperberg, G. R. (2010b). Language in schizophrenia part 2: what can psycholinguistics bring to the study of schizophrenia…and vice versa? Lang. Linguist. Compass 4, 590–604. doi: 10.1111/j.1749-818X.2010.00217.x

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Kuperberg, G. R., McGuire, P. K., and David, A. S. (1998). Reduced sensitivity to linguistic context in schizophrenic thought disorder: evidence from on-line monitoring for words in linguistically anomalous sentences. J. Abnorm. Psychol. 107:423. doi: 10.1037//0021-843X.107.3.423

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Kurzban, R. (2012). Why Everyone (Else) Is a Hypocrite: Evolution and the Modular Mind. Princeton: Princeton University Press. doi: 10.1515/9781400835997

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Kurzban, R., and Aktipis, C. A. (2006). “Modular minds, multiple motives,” in Evolution and Social Psychology (Psychology Press).

Google Scholar

Kurzban, R., and Aktipis, C. A. (2007). Modularity and the social mind: are psychologists too self-ish? Pers. Soc. Psychol. Rev. 11, 131–149. doi: 10.1177/1088868306294906

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Landis, T., Cummings, J. L., Benson, D. F., and Palmer, E. P. (1986). Loss of topographic familiarity: an environmental agnosia. Arch. Neurol. 43, 132–136. doi: 10.1001/archneur.1986.00520020026011

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Lebedev, A. V., Kaelen, M., Lövdén, M., Nilsson, J., Feilding, A., Nutt, D. J., et al. (2016). LSD-induced entropic brain activity predicts subsequent personality change. Hum. Brain Mapp. 37, 3203–3213. doi: 10.1002/hbm.23234

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Lebedev, A. V., Lövdén, M., Rosenthal, G., Feilding, A., Nutt, D. J., and Carhart-Harris, R. L. (2015). Finding the self by losing the self: neural correlates of ego-dissolution under psilocybin: finding the self by losing the self. Hum. Brain Mapp. 36, 3137–3153. doi: 10.1002/hbm.22833

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Leekam, S., Baron-Cohen, S., Perrett, D., Milders, M., and Brown, S. (1997). Eye-direction detection: a dissociation between geometric and joint attention skills in autism. Br. J. Dev. Psycho 15, 77–95. doi: 10.1111/j.2044-835X.1997.tb00726.x

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Leslie, A. M. (1994). ToMM, ToBy, and agency: core architecture and domain specificity. Mapping Mind 29, 119–148. doi: 10.1017/CBO9780511752902.006

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Letheby, C., and Gerrans, P. (2017). Self unbound: ego dissolution in psychedelic experience. Neurosci. Conscious. 2017:nix016. doi: 10.1093/nc/nix016

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Lewis, D. M., Al-Shawaf, L., Thompson, M. B., and Buss, D. M. (2020). “Evolved psychological mechanisms,” in SAGE Handbook of Evolutionary Psychology, 96–119. doi: 10.4135/9781529739442.n6

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Lewis, D. M. G., Al-Shawaf, L., Conroy-Beam, D., Asao, K., and Buss, D. M. (2017). Evolutionary psychology: a how-to guide. Am. Psychol. 72, 353–373. doi: 10.1037/a0040409

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Li, F., Lui, S., Yao, L., Ji, G.-J., Liao, W., Sweeney, J. A., et al. (2018). Altered white matter connectivity within and between networks in antipsychotic-naive first-episode schizophrenia. Schizophr. Bull. 44, 409–418. doi: 10.1093/schbul/sbx048

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Li, T., Wang, Q., Zhang, J., Rolls, E. T., Yang, W., Palaniyappan, L., et al. (2017). Brain-wide analysis of functional connectivity in first-episode and chronic stages of schizophrenia. Schizophr. Bull. 43, 436–448. doi: 10.1093/schbul/sbw099

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Liang, M., Zhou, Y., Jiang, T., Liu, Z., Tian, L., Liu, H., et al. (2006). Widespread functional disconnectivity in schizophrenia with resting-state functional magnetic resonance imaging: Neuroreport 17, 209–213. doi: 10.1097/01.wnr.0000198434.06518.b8

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Linehan, M. (1993). Cognitive-Behavioral Treatment of Borderline Personality Disorder. London: Guilford press.

Google Scholar

Liu, J., Jing, L., and Tu, X. (2016). Weighted gene co-expression network analysis identifies specific modules and hub genes related to coronary artery disease. BMC Cardiovasc. Disord. 16:54. doi: 10.1186/s12872-016-0217-3

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Liu, J., Li, J., Feng, L., Li, L., Tian, J., and Lee, K. (2014). Seeing Jesus in toast: neural and behavioral correlates of face pareidolia. Cortex 53, 60–77. doi: 10.1016/j.cortex.2014.01.013

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Long, J., Liu, Z., Wu, X., Xu, Y., and Ge, C. (2016). Screening for genes and subnetworks associated with pancreatic cancer based on the gene expression profile. Mol. Med. Rep. 13, 3779–3786. doi: 10.3892/mmr.2016.5007

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Lucchetta, M., and Pellegrini, M. (2020). Finding disease modules for cancer and COVID-19 in gene co-expression networks with the CoreandPeel method. Sci. Rep. 10:17628. doi: 10.1038/s41598-020-74705-6

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Machery, E. (2012). Dissociations in neuropsychology and cognitive neuroscience. Philos. Sci. 79, 490–518. doi: 10.1086/668002

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Mahon, B. Z., Anzellotti, S., Schwarzbach, J., Zampini, M., and Caramazza, A. (2009). Category-specific organization in the human brain does not require visual experience. Neuron 63, 397–405. doi: 10.1016/j.neuron.2009.07.012

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Mahon, B. Z., and Caramazza, A. (2009). Concepts and categories: a cognitive neuropsychological perspective. Annu. Rev. Psychol. 60, 27–51. doi: 10.1146/annurev.psych.60.110707.163532

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Majid, A., and Burenhult, N. (2014). Odors are expressible in language, as long as you speak the right language. Cognition 130, 266–270. doi: 10.1016/j.cognition.2013.11.004

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Mantovani, A., Simeon, D., Urban, N., Bulow, P., Allart, A., and Lisanby, S. (2011). Temporo-parietal junction stimulation in the treatment of depersonalization disorder. Psychiatry Res. 186, 138–140. doi: 10.1016/j.psychres.2010.08.022

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Markus, H. R., and Kitayama, S. (1991). Culture and the self: Implications for cognition, emotion, and motivation. Psychol. Rev. 98, 224–253. doi: 10.1037/0033-295X.98.2.224

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Markus, H. R., and Kitayama, S. (2010). Cultures and selves: a cycle of mutual constitution. Perspect. Psychol. Sci. 5, 420–430. doi: 10.1177/1745691610375557

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Marr, D. (1982). Vision: A Computational Investigation into the Human Representation and Processing of Visual Information. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Google Scholar

Martin, J. C., Clark, S. R., and Schubert, K. O. (2023). Towards a neurophenomenological understanding of self-disorder in schizophrenia spectrum disorders: a systematic review and synthesis of anatomical, physiological, and neurocognitive findings. Brain Sci. 13:845. doi: 10.3390/brainsci13060845

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Mas-Herrero, E., Zatorre, R. J., Rodriguez-Fornells, A., and Marco-Pallarés, J. (2014). Dissociation between musical and monetary reward responses in specific musical anhedonia. Curr. Biol. 24, 699–704. doi: 10.1016/j.cub.2014.01.068

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

McGuire, P. (2016). The role of the corpus callosum in psychosis. Biol. Psychiatry 80, 579–580. doi: 10.1016/j.biopsych.2016.08.021

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Medin, D., Waxman, S., Woodring, J., and Washinawatok, K. (2010). Human-centeredness is not a universal feature of young children's reasoning: culture and experience matter when reasoning about biological entities. Cogn. Dev. 25, 197–207. doi: 10.1016/j.cogdev.2010.02.001

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Medin, D. L., and Atran, S. (2004). The native mind: biological categorization and reasoning in development and across cultures. Psychol. Rev. 111:960. doi: 10.1037/0033-295X.111.4.960

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Medin, D. L., Ross, N. O., Atran, S., Cox, D., Coley, J., Proffitt, J. B., et al. (2006). Folkbiology of freshwater fish. Cognition 99, 237–273. doi: 10.1016/j.cognition.2003.12.005

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Metzinger, T. K. (2013). Why are dreams interesting for philosophers? The example of minimal phenomenal selfhood, plus an agenda for future research1. Front. Psychol. 4:746. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00746

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Meunier, D., Lambiotte, R., and Bullmore, E. T. (2010). Modular and hierarchically modular organization of brain networks. Front. Neurosci. 4:200. doi: 10.3389/fnins.2010.00200

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Millière, R., Carhart-Harris, R. L., Roseman, L., Trautwein, F.-M., and Berkovich-Ohana, A. (2018). Psychedelics, meditation, and self-consciousness. Front. Psychol. 9:1475. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2018.01475

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Milner, A. D., Perrett, D. I., Johnston, R. S., Benson, P. J., Jordan, T. R., Heeley, D. W., et al. (1991). Perception and action in ‘visual form agnosia.' Brain 114, 405–428. doi: 10.1093/brain/114.1.405

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Modell, A. H. (2014). The evolutionary significance of the primary process—the freudian concept and its revision. Psychoanalytic Inquiry 34, 810–816. doi: 10.1080/07351690.2014.968023

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Montoya, J. M., Pimm, S. L., and Solé, R. V. (2006). Ecological networks and their fragility. Nature 442, 259–264. doi: 10.1038/nature04927

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Moran, A., Guillot, A., MacIntyre, T., and Collet, C. (2012). Re-imagining motor imagery: Building bridges between cognitive neuroscience and sport psychology. Br. J. Psychol. 103, 224–247. doi: 10.1111/j.2044-8295.2011.02068.x

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Moreira-Filho, C. A., Bando, S. Y., Bertonha, F. B., Iamashita, P., Silva, F. N., Costa, L., et al. (2015). Community structure analysis of transcriptional networks reveals distinct molecular pathways for early-and late-onset temporal lobe epilepsy with childhood febrile seizures. PLoS ONE 10:e0128174. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0128174

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Mundy, P. (2003). Annotation: The neural basis of social impairments in autism: the role of the dorsal medial-frontal cortex and anterior cingulate system. Child Psychol. Psychiat. 44, 793–809. doi: 10.1111/1469-7610.00165

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Mundy, P., and Newell, L. (2007). Attention, joint attention, and social cognition. Curr. Dir. Psychol. Sci. 16, 269–274. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-8721.2007.00518.x

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Murphy, D., and Stich, S. (2000). “Darwin in the madhouse: evolutionary psychology and the classification of mental disorders,” in Evolution and the human mind: Modularity, language and meta-cognition 62. doi: 10.1017/CBO9780511611926.005

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Nadal, Z., Ferrari, M., Lora, J., Revollo, A., Nicolas, F., Astegiano, S., et al. (2022). Noah's syndrome: systematic review of animal hoarding disorder. Hum.-Animal Inter. Bull. 10, 1–20. doi: 10.1079/hai.2022.0003

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Nation, K., and Penny, S. (2008). Sensitivity to eye gaze in autism: is it normal? Is it automatic? Is it social? Dev. Psychopathol. 20, 79–97. doi: 10.1017/S0954579408000047

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Nesse, R. (2005). Maladaptation and Natural Selection. Q. Rev. Biol. 80, 62–70. doi: 10.1086/431026

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Nesse, R. M. (1990a). Evolutionary explanations of emotions. Hum. Nat. 1, 261–289. doi: 10.1007/BF02733986

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Nesse, R. M. (1990b). The evolutionary functions of repression and the ego defenses. J. Am. Acad. Psychoanal. 18, 260–285. doi: 10.1521/jaap.1.1990.18.2.260

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Nesse, R. M. (2004). Natural selection and the elusiveness of happiness. Phil. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B 359, 1333–1347. doi: 10.1098/rstb.2004.1511

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Nesse, R. M. (2015). “Evolutionary psychology and mental health,” in The Handbook of Evolutionary Psychology, ed. D. M. Buss (New York: Wiley), 903–927. doi: 10.1002/9780470939376.ch32

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Nesse, R. M. (2019). Good Reasons for Bad Feelings: Insights from the Frontier of Evolutionary Psychiatry. New York: Penguin.

Google Scholar

Nesse, R. M. (2020). Tacit creationism in emotions research. Emotion Researcher, ISRE's Sourcebook for Research on Emotion and Affect. Available online at: http://emotionresearcher.com/tacit-creationism-in-emotion-research/ (accessed June 10, 2024).

Google Scholar

Nesse, R. M. (2022). Social situations shape social emotions that benefit genes. Evolut. Stud. Imagin. Cult. 6, 39–42. doi: 10.26613/esic.6.1.268

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Nesse, R. M., and Lloyd, A. T. (1992). “The evolution of psychodynamic mechanisms,” in The Adapted Mind: Evolutionary Psychology and the Generation of Culture, 601–624. doi: 10.1093/oso/9780195060232.003.0018

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Newman, M. E. J. (2006). Modularity and community structure in networks. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 103, 8577–8582. doi: 10.1073/pnas.0601602103

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Norberg, M. M., Visvalingam, S., Stevenson, R. J., and Saluja, S. (2024). A review of the phenomenology, aetiology and treatment of animal phobia and insights for biophobia. People Nat. 6, 932–944. doi: 10.1002/pan3.10514

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Nordgaard, J., Nilsson, L. S., Sæbye, D., and Parnas, J. (2018). Self-disorders in schizophrenia-spectrum disorders: a 5-year follow-up study. Eur. Arch. Psychiatry Clin. Neurosci. 268, 713–718. doi: 10.1007/s00406-017-0837-3

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Nordgaard, J., and Parnas, J. (2014). Self-disorders and the schizophrenia spectrum: a study of 100 first hospital admissions. Schizophr. Bull. 40, 1300–1307. doi: 10.1093/schbul/sbt239

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Nour, M. M., and Carhart-Harris, R. L. (2017). Psychedelics and the science of self-experience. Br J. Psychiat. 210, 177–179. doi: 10.1192/bjp.bp.116.194738

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Nour, M. M., Evans, L., Nutt, D., and Carhart-Harris, R. L. (2016). Ego-dissolution and psychedelics: validation of the ego-dissolution inventory (EDI). Front. Hum. Neurosci. 10:269. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2016.00269

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Ohata, R., Asai, T., Kadota, H., Shigemasu, H., Ogawa, K., and Imamizu, H. (2020). Sense of agency beyond sensorimotor process: decoding self-other action attribution in the human brain. Cerebral Cortex 30, 4076–4091. doi: 10.1093/cercor/bhaa028

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Onishi, K. H., and Baillargeon, R. (2005). Do 15-month-old infants understand false beliefs? Science 308, 255–258. doi: 10.1126/science.1107621

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Oyebode, F. (2022). Sims' Symptoms in the Mind: Textbook of Descriptive Psychopathology E-Book: Sims' Symptoms in the Mind: Textbook of Descriptive Psychopathology E-Book. New York: Elsevier Health Sciences.

Google Scholar

Park, W. J., and Tadin, D. (2018). “Motion perception,” in Stevens' Handbook of Experimental Psychology and Cognitive Neuroscience (John Wiley and Sons Ltd), 1–73. doi: 10.1002/9781119170174.epcn210

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Parnas, J. (2011). A disappearing heritage: the clinical core of schizophrenia. Schizophr. Bull. 37, 1121–1130. doi: 10.1093/schbul/sbr081

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Parnas, J., and Handest, P. (2003). Phenomenology of anomalous self-experience in early schizophrenia. Compr. Psychiatry 44, 121–134. doi: 10.1053/comp.2003.50017

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Parnas, J., and Henriksen, M. G. (2014). Disordered self in the schizophrenia spectrum: a clinical and research perspective. Harv. Rev. Psychiatry 22, 251–265. doi: 10.1097/HRP.0000000000000040

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Parnas, J., and Henriksen, M. G. (2019). “Selfhood and its disorders,” in The Oxford Handbook of Phenomenological Psychopathology, eds. G. Stanghellini, M. Broome, A. Raballo, A. V. Fernandez, P. Fusar-Poli, and R. Rosfort (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 464–474. doi: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780198803157.013.52

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Parnas, J., Møller, P., Kircher, T., Thalbitzer, J., Jansson, L., Handest, P., et al. (2005). EASE: examination of anomalous self-experience. Psychopathology 38, 236–258. doi: 10.1159/000088441

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Passingham, R. E., Stephan, K. E., and Kötter, R. (2002). The anatomical basis of functional localization in the cortex. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 3, 606–616. doi: 10.1038/nrn893

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Patel, S., Mahon, K., Wellington, R., Zhang, J., Chaplin, W., and Szeszko, P. R. (2011). A meta-analysis of diffusion tensor imaging studies of the corpus callosum in schizophrenia. Schizophr. Res. 129, 149–155. doi: 10.1016/j.schres.2011.03.014

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Patronek, G. J. (1999). Hoarding of animals: an under-recognized public health problem in a difficult-to-study population. Public Health Rep. 114:81. doi: 10.1093/phr/114.1.81

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Payk, T. R. (2021). Psychopathologie: Vom Symptom zur Diagnose., 5. vollst. überarb. Aufl. 2021 edition. Berlin: Springer. doi: 10.1007/978-3-662-63574-2

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Perenin, M.-T., and Vighetto, A. (1988). Optic ataxia: a specific disruption in visuomotor mechanisms: I. Different aspects of the deficit in reaching for objects. Brain 111, 643–674. doi: 10.1093/brain/111.3.643

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Perlini, C., Marini, A., Garzitto, M., Isola, M., Cerruti, S., Marinelli, V., et al. (2012). Linguistic production and syntactic comprehension in schizophrenia and bipolar disorder. Acta Psychiatr. Scand. 126, 363–376. doi: 10.1111/j.1600-0447.2012.01864.x

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Petersen, S. E., and Sporns, O. (2015). Brain networks and cognitive architectures. Neuron 88, 207–219. doi: 10.1016/j.neuron.2015.09.027

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Pietraszewski, D., and Wertz, A. E. (2022). Why evolutionary psychology should abandon modularity. Perspect. Psychol. Sci. 17, 465–490. doi: 10.1177/1745691621997113

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Pievani, M., Filippini, N., Van Den Heuvel, M. P., Cappa, S. F., and Frisoni, G. B. (2014). Brain connectivity in neurodegenerative diseases—from phenotype to proteinopathy. Nat. Rev. Neurol. 10, 620–633. doi: 10.1038/nrneurol.2014.178

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Pinker, S. (2005). So how does the mind work? Mind Lang. 20, 1–24. doi: 10.1111/j.0268-1064.2005.00274.x

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Pinker, S. (2015). How the Mind Works. New York, NY: W. W. Norton & Company.

Google Scholar

Plato (2011). Plato: Phaedrus. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi: 10.1017/CBO9780511977237

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Platz, W. E., Oberlaender, F. A., and Seidel, M. L. (1995). The phenomenology of perceptual hallucinations in alcohol-induced delirium tremens. Psychopathology 28, 247–255. doi: 10.1159/000284935

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Plaut, D. C. (1995). Double dissociation without modularity: evidence from connectionist neuropsychology. J. Clin. Exp. Neuropsychol. 17, 291–321. doi: 10.1080/01688639508405124

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Pliner, P., and Hobden, K. (1992). Development of a scale to measure the trait of food neophobia in humans. Appetite 19, 105–120. doi: 10.1016/0195-6663(92)90014-W

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Pliner, P., and Salvy, S. J. (2006). “Food neophobia in humans,” in The psychology of food choice, eds. R. Shepherd and M. Raats (UK: CABI), 75–92. doi: 10.1079/9780851990323.0075

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Provenza, F. D. (1995). Postingestive feedback as an elementary determinant of food preference and intake in ruminants. J. Range Manag. 48:2. doi: 10.2307/4002498

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Putcha, D., Erkkinen, M., and Daffner, K. R. (2021). “Functional Neurocircuitry of Cognition and Cognitive Syndromes,” in Neuropsychiatry and Behavioral Neurology: Principles and Practice, eds. D. A. Silbersweig, L. T. Safar, and K. R. Daffner (New York, NY: McGraw Hill).

Google Scholar

Pylyshyn, Z. (1999). Is vision continuous with cognition? The case for cognitive impenetrability of visual perception. Behav. Brain Sci. 22, 341–365. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X99002022

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Qi, Y., and Ge, H. (2006). Modularity and dynamics of cellular networks. PLoS Comput. Biol. 2:e174. doi: 10.1371/journal.pcbi.0020174

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Quilty-Dunn, J. (2020). Perceptual pluralism. Nous 54, 807–838. doi: 10.1111/nous.12285

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Raballo, A., Poletti, M., Preti, A., and Parnas, J. (2021). The self in the spectrum: a meta-analysis of the evidence linking basic self-disorders and schizophrenia. Schizophr. Bull. 47, 1007–1017. doi: 10.1093/schbul/sbaa201

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Ravasz, E., Somera, A. L., Mongru, D. A., Oltvai, Z. N., and Barabási, A.-L. (2002). Hierarchical organization of modularity in metabolic networks. Science 297, 1551–1555. doi: 10.1126/science.1073374

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Rogers, S. J., and Pennington, B. F. (1991). A theoretical approach to the deficits in infantile autism. Dev. Psychopathol. 3, 137–162. doi: 10.1017/S0954579400000043

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Rollnick, S., and Miller, W. R. (1995). What is motivational interviewing? Behav. Cogn. Psychother. 23, 325–334. doi: 10.1017/S135246580001643X

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Röper, L., and Hagedorn, T. (2019). Ich bin viele: Mein Leben mit multipler Persönlichkeitsstörung. 1st edition. Norderstedt: BoD – Books on Demand.

Google Scholar

Roser, M., and Gazzaniga, M. S. (2004). Automatic brains—interpretive minds. Curr. Dir. Psychol. Sci. 13, 56–59. doi: 10.1111/j.0963-7214.2004.00274.x

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Ross, N., Medin, D., Coley, J. D., and Atran, S. (2003). Cultural and experiential differences in the development of folkbiological induction. Cogn. Dev. 18, 25–47. doi: 10.1016/S0885-2014(02)00142-9

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Rossetti, I., Brambilla, P., and Papagno, C. (2018). Metaphor comprehension in schizophrenic patients. Front. Psychol. 9:670. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2018.00670

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Rowan, J. (1989). Subpersonalities: The People Inside Us. London: Routledge.

Google Scholar

Ryan, N. P., Catroppa, C., Beare, R., Silk, T. J., Hearps, S. J., Beauchamp, M. H., et al. (2017). Uncovering the neuroanatomical correlates of cognitive, affective and conative theory of mind in paediatric traumatic brain injury: a neural systems perspective. Soc. Cogn. Affect. Neurosci. 12, 1414–1427. doi: 10.1093/scan/nsx066

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Salavera, C., Puyuelo, M., Antoñanzas, J. L., and Teruel, P. (2013). Semantics, pragmatics, and formal thought disorders in people with schizophrenia. Neuropsychiatr. Dis. Treat. 9, 177–183. doi: 10.2147/NDT.S38676

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Samson, D., and Pillon, A. (2003). A case of impaired knwoledge for fruit and vegetables. Cogn. Neuropsychol. 20, 373–400. doi: 10.1080/02643290244000329

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Sass, L. A., and Parnas, J. (2003). Schizophrenia, consciousness, and the self. Schizophr. Bull. 29, 427–444. doi: 10.1093/oxfordjournals.schbul.a007017

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Saxe, R. (2006). Uniquely human social cognition. Curr. Opin. Neurobiol. 16, 235–239. doi: 10.1016/j.conb.2006.03.001

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Schaller, M. (2015). “The behavioral immune system,” in The Handbook of Evolutionary Psychology (John Wiley and Sons Ltd), 1–19. doi: 10.1002/9781119125563.evpsych107

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Schaller, M., and Murray, D. R. (2008). Pathogens, personality, and culture: disease prevalence predicts worldwide variability in sociosexuality, extraversion, and openness to experience. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 95:212. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.95.1.212

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Scharfetter, C. (1981). Ego-psychopathology: the concept and its empirical evaluation. Psychol. Med. 11, 273–280. doi: 10.1017/S0033291700052090

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Scharfetter, C. (2003). “The self-experience of schizophrenics,” in The Self in Neuroscience and Psychiatry, eds. A. David and T. Kircher (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 272–290. doi: 10.1017/CBO9780511543708.014

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Scharfetter, C. (2010). Allgemeine Psychopathologie: Eine Einführung., 6., überarb. Aufl. Stuttgart: Thieme. doi: 10.1055/b-0034-47669

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Schindler, I., Rice, N. J., McIntosh, R. D., Rossetti, Y., Vighetto, A., and Milner, A. D. (2004). Automatic avoidance of obstacles is a dorsal stream function: evidence from optic ataxia. Nat. Neurosci. 7, 779–784. doi: 10.1038/nn1273

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Schmitt, D. P., and Pilcher, J. J. (2004). Evaluating evidence of psychological adaptation: how do we know one when we see one? Psychol. Sci. 15, 643–649. doi: 10.1111/j.0956-7976.2004.00734.x

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Schneider, K. (2007). Klinische Psychopathologie. Georg Thieme Verlag. doi: 10.1055/b-002-44928

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Scholl, B. J., and Tremoulet, P. D. (2000). Perceptual causality and animacy. Trends Cogn. Sci. 4, 299–309. doi: 10.1016/S1364-6613(00)01506-0

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Seeley, W. W., Crawford, R. K., Zhou, J., Miller, B. L., and Greicius, M. D. (2009). Neurodegenerative diseases target large-scale human brain networks. Neuron 62, 42–52. doi: 10.1016/j.neuron.2009.03.024

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Shedler, J. (2022). That was then, this is now: psychoanalytic psychotherapy for the rest of us. Contemp. Psychoanal. 58, 405–437. doi: 10.1080/00107530.2022.2149038

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Sienaert, P., Rooseleer, J., and De Fruyt, J. (2011). Measuring catatonia: A systematic review of rating scales. J. Affect. Disord. 135, 1–9. doi: 10.1016/j.jad.2011.02.012

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Solé, R. V., and Montoya, M. (2001). Complexity and fragility in ecological networks. Proc. R. Soc. Lond. B 268, 2039–2045. doi: 10.1098/rspb.2001.1767

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Solomon, G. E. A., and Zaitchik, D. (2012). Folkbiology. WIRES Cogn. Sci. 3, 105–115. doi: 10.1002/wcs.150

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Sperber, D. (1994). “The modularity of thought and the epidemiology of representations,” in Mapping the Mind, eds. L. A. Hirschfeld and S. A. Gelman (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 39–67. doi: 10.1017/CBO9780511752902.003

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Sporns, O., Chialvo, D. R., Kaiser, M., and Hilgetag, C. C. (2004). Organization, development and function of complex brain networks. Trends Cogn. Sci. 8, 418–425. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2004.07.008

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Sporns, O., Tononi, G., and Kötter, R. (2005). The human connectome: a structural description of the human brain. PLoS Comput. Biol. 1:e42. doi: 10.1371/journal.pcbi.0010042

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Stevens, L. K., McGraw, P. V., Ledgeway, T., and Schluppeck, D. (2009). Temporal characteristics of global motion processing revealed by transcranial magnetic stimulation. Eur. J. Neurosci. 30, 2415–2426. doi: 10.1111/j.1460-9568.2009.07034.x

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Stoliker, D., Egan, G. F., Friston, K. J., and Razi, A. (2022). Neural mechanisms and psychology of psychedelic ego dissolution. Pharmacol. Rev. 74, 876–917. doi: 10.1124/pharmrev.121.000508

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Stumpf, B. P., Calácio, B., Branco, B. C., Wilnes, B., Soier, G., Soares, L., et al. (2023). Animal hoarding: a systematic review. Braz. J. Psychiat. 45, 356–365. doi: 10.47626/1516-4446-2022-3003

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Tagliazucchi, E., Roseman, L., Kaelen, M., Orban, C., Muthukumaraswamy, S. D., Murphy, K., et al. (2016). Increased global functional connectivity correlates with LSD-induced ego dissolution. Curr. Biol. 26, 1043–1050. doi: 10.1016/j.cub.2016.02.010

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Taylor, S., McKay, D., Miguel, E. C., De Mathis, M. A., Andrade, C., Ahuja, N., et al. (2014). Musical obsessions: a comprehensive review of neglected clinical phenomena. J. Anxiety Disord. 28, 580–589. doi: 10.1016/j.janxdis.2014.06.003

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Todorova, G. K., Hatton, R. E. M., and Pollick, F. E. (2019). Biological motion perception in autism spectrum disorder: a meta-analysis. Mol. Autism 10:49. doi: 10.1186/s13229-019-0299-8

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Tomasello, M. (2019). Becoming Human: A Theory of Ontogeny. Cambridge, Massachusetts: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. doi: 10.4159/9780674988651

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Tomasello, M., Carpenter, M., Call, J., Behne, T., and Moll, H. (2005). Understanding and sharing intentions: the origins of cultural cognition. Behav. Brain Sci. 28, 675–691. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X05000129

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Tooby, J., and Cosmides, L. (1992). “The psychological foundations of culture,” in The adapted mind: Evolutionary psychology and the generation of culture (New York, NY, US: Oxford University Press), 19–136. doi: 10.1093/oso/9780195060232.003.0002

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Tooby, J., Cosmides, L., and Barrett, H. C. (2003). The second law of thermodynamics is the first law of psychology: evolutionary developmental psychology and the theory of tandem, coordinated inheritances: comment on Lickliter and Honeycutt (2003). Psychol. Bull. 129, 858–865. doi: 10.1037/0033-2909.129.6.858

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Trabert, W. (1995). 100 years of delusional parasitosis. Psychopathology 28, 238–246. doi: 10.1159/000284934

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Troje, N. F., and Westhoff, C. (2006). The inversion effect in biological motion perception: evidence for a “life detector”? Curr. Biol. 16, 821–824. doi: 10.1016/j.cub.2006.03.022

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Tsao, D. Y., and Livingstone, M. S. (2008). Mechanisms of face perception. Annu. Rev. Neurosci. 31, 411–437. doi: 10.1146/annurev.neuro.30.051606.094238

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Tyler, L. K., and Moss, H. E. (2001). Towards a distributed account of conceptual knowledge. Trends Cogn. Sci. 5, 244–252. doi: 10.1016/S1364-6613(00)01651-X

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Uddin, L. Q., Molnar-Szakacs, I., Zaidel, E., and Iacoboni, M. (2006). rTMS to the right inferior parietal lobule disrupts self–other discrimination. Soc. Cogn. Affect. Neurosci. 1, 65–71. doi: 10.1093/scan/nsl003

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Vaillant, G. E. (1995). Adaptation to Life. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Google Scholar

Volz, L. J., and Gazzaniga, M. S. (2017). Interaction in isolation: 50 years of insights from splitbrain research. Brain 140, 2051–2060. doi: 10.1093/brain/awx139

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Von Dassow, G., and Munro, E. (1999). Modularity in animal development and evolution: elements of a conceptual framework for EvoDevo. J. Exp. Zool. 285, 307–325. doi: 10.1002/(SICI)1097-010X(19991215)285:4<307::AID-JEZ2>3.0.CO;2-V

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Wagner, G. P. (1996). Homologues, natural kinds and the evolution of modularity. Am. Zool. 36, 36–43. doi: 10.1093/icb/36.1.36

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Wakefield, J. C. (1992). The Concept of Mental Disorder. New York: American Psychologist.

Google Scholar

Wakefield, J. C. (2015). “Biological function and dysfunction,” in The Handbook of Evolutionary Psychology, ed. D. M. Buss (London: Wiley), 878–902. doi: 10.1002/9780470939376.ch31

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Wang, P., Jiang, Y., and Biswal, B. B. (2024). Aberrant interhemispheric structural and functional connectivity within whole brain in schizophrenia. Schizophr. Res. 264, 336–344. doi: 10.1016/j.schres.2023.12.033

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Wellik, D. M. (2007). Hox patterning of the vertebrate axial skeleton. Dev. Dyn. 236, 2454–2463. doi: 10.1002/dvdy.21286

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Wellman, H. M., Cross, D., and Watson, J. (2001). Meta-analysis of theory-of-mind development: the truth about false belief. Child Dev. 72, 655–684. doi: 10.1111/1467-8624.00304

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Wertz, A. E. (2019). How plants shape the mind. Trends Cogn. Sci. 23, 528–531. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2019.04.009

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Wertz, A. E., and Wynn, K. (2014). Thyme to touch: Infants possess strategies that protect them from dangers posed by plants. Cognition 130, 44–49. doi: 10.1016/j.cognition.2013.09.002

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Wertz, A. E., and Wynn, K. (2019). Can I eat that too? 18-month-olds generalize social information about edibility to similar looking plants. Appetite 138, 127–135. doi: 10.1016/j.appet.2019.02.013

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Westen, D., and Gabbard, G. O. (2002). Developments in cognitive neuroscience: I. Conflict, compromise, and connectionism. J. Am. Psychoanal. Assoc. 50, 53–98. doi: 10.1177/00030651020500011501

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Włodarczyk, A., Elsner, C., Schmitterer, A., and Wertz, A. E. (2018). Every rose has its thorn: Infants' responses to pointed shapes in naturalistic contexts. Evol. Hum. Behav. 39, 583–593. doi: 10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2018.06.001

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Wnuk, E., and Majid, A. (2014). Revisiting the limits of language: the odor lexicon of Maniq. Cognition 131, 125–138. doi: 10.1016/j.cognition.2013.12.008

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Xi, Y., Liu, Y., Yang, Q., Liu, H., Luo, J., Ouyang, Y., et al. (2022). Food neophobia and its association with vegetable, fruit and snack intake among 12- to 36-month toddlers in China: a cross-sectional study. Food Qual. Prefer. 98:104513. doi: 10.1016/j.foodqual.2021.104513

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Zahavi, D. (2003). “Phenomenology of self,” in The Self in Neuroscience and Psychiatry, eds. T. Kircher and A. David (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 56–75. doi: 10.1017/CBO9780511543708.004

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Zahavi, D. (2010). “Minimal self and narrative self. a distinction in need of refinement,” in The Embodied Self: Dimensions, Coherence, and Disorders, eds. T. Fuchs, H. Sattel, and P. Heningnsen (Heningnsen), 3–11.

Google Scholar

Zaitchik, D., and Solomon, G. E. (2009). Conservation of species, volume, and belief in patients with Alzheimer's disease: the issue of domain specificity and... Cogn. Neuropsychol. 26, 511–526. doi: 10.1080/02643290903478549

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Zaitchik, D., and Solomon, G. E. A. (2001). Putting semantics back into the semantic representation of living things. Behav. Brain Sci. 24, 496–497. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X01414154

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Zaitchik, D., and Solomon, G. E. A. (2008). Animist thinking in the elderly and in patients with Alzheimer's disease. Cogn. Neuropsychol. 25, 27–37. doi: 10.1080/02643290801904059

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Zelditch, M. L., and Goswami, A. (2021). What does modularity mean? Evolut. Dev. 23, 377–403. doi: 10.1111/ede.12390

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Zeman, A. (2024). Aphantasia and hyperphantasia: exploring imagery vividness extremes. Trends Cogn. Sci. 28, 467–480. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2024.02.007

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Zeman, A., Dewar, M., and Della Sala, S. (2015). Lives without imagery–Congenital aphantasia. Cortex 73, 378–380. doi: 10.1016/j.cortex.2015.05.019

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Zhou, J., Gennatas, E. D., Kramer, J. H., Miller, B. L., and Seeley, W. W. (2012). Predicting regional neurodegeneration from the healthy brain functional connectome. Neuron 73, 1216–1227. doi: 10.1016/j.neuron.2012.03.004

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Zhu, Y., Zhang, L., Fan, J., and Han, S. (2007). Neural basis of cultural influence on self-representation. Neuroimage 34, 1310–1316. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2006.08.047

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Zielasek, J., and Gaebel, W. (2008). Modern modularity and the road towards a modular psychiatry. Eur. Arch. Psychiatry Clin. Neurosci. 258, 60–65. doi: 10.1007/s00406-008-5015-1

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Zielasek, J., and Gaebel, W. (2009). Modularity in philosophy, the neurosciences, and psychiatry. Poiesis Prax. 6, 93–108. doi: 10.1007/s10202-008-0065-z

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Zihl, J., Von Cramon, D., and Mai, N. (1983). Selective disturbance of movement vision after bilateral brain damage. Brain 106, 313–340. doi: 10.1093/brain/106.2.313

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Keywords: cognitive modularity, psychiatry, self-disorders, enzymatic computation, information encapsulation, modular conflict, classification of mental disorders, evolutionary psychology

Citation: Ilie G and Jaeggi AV (2025) The modular mind and psychiatry: toward clinical integration with a focus on self-disorders. Front. Psychol. 16:1570049. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2025.1570049

Received: 02 February 2025; Accepted: 07 April 2025;
Published: 25 April 2025.

Edited by:

Geoff Kushnick, Australian National University, Australia

Reviewed by:

Tara DeLecce, Oakland University, United States
Soheil Shapouri, Lehigh University, United States

Copyright © 2025 Ilie and Jaeggi. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Gheorghe Ilie, Z2hlb3JnaGUuaWxpZUB1emguY2g=

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.