Skip to main content

HYPOTHESIS AND THEORY article

Front. Psychol., 12 November 2015
Sec. Cognition
This article is part of the Research Topic Quantum Structures in Cognitive and Social Science View all 15 articles

Unitary Transformations in the Quantum Model for Conceptual Conjunctions and Its Application to Data Representation

  • 1Department of Mathematics, University of British Columbia, Kelowna, BC, Canada
  • 2Center Leo Apostel, Vrije Universiteit Brussel, Brussels, Belgium
  • 3Instituto de Filosofía y Ciencias de la Complejidad - IFICC, Ñuñoa, Chile

Quantum models of concept combinations have been successful in representing various experimental situations that cannot be accommodated by traditional models based on classical probability or fuzzy set theory. In many cases, the focus has been on producing a representation that fits experimental results to validate quantum models. However, these representations are not always consistent with the cognitive modeling principles. Moreover, some important issues related to the representation of concepts such as the dimensionality of the realization space, the uniqueness of solutions, and the compatibility of measurements, have been overlooked. In this paper, we provide a dimensional analysis of the realization space for the two-sector Fock space model for conjunction of concepts focusing on the first and second sectors separately. We then introduce various representation of concepts that arise from the use of unitary operators in the realization space. In these concrete representations, a pair of concepts and their combination are modeled by a single conceptual state, and by a collection of exemplar-dependent operators. Therefore, they are consistent with cognitive modeling principles. This framework not only provides a uniform approach to model an entire data set, but, because all measurement operators are expressed in the same basis, allows us to address the question of compatibility of measurements. In particular, we present evidence that it may be possible to predict non-commutative effects from partial measurements of conceptual combinations.

1. Introduction

1.1. Concept Combinations in Quantum Cognition

The application of quantum models to cognitive phenomena is an emergent field known as quantum cognition (Aerts, 2009; Pothos and Busemeyer, 2013). One of the areas in quantum cognition that has received much attention is the study of concepts and their combinations (Aerts and Gabora, 2005a,b; Aerts, 2007a,b; Aerts and Sozzo, 2011; Aerts et al., 2013). In a general setting, a cognitive situation might include multiple concepts forming aggregated structures (Rips, 1995; Fodor, 1998). For example, the concepts “Fruit” and “Vegetable” can be combined to form a new concept “Fruit And Vegetable” (Hampton, 1988a). This example of a concept combination is built with the connective “And,” which is also an operation mathematically defined in logic and probability. The question becomes, is it possible to apply the mathematical definition of the connective “And” to build the structure of “Fruit And Vegetable” from the structures of “Fruit” and “Vegetable”? Cognitive scientists have performed several experiments measuring various semantic estimations including typicality, membership, and similarity of concept combinations built with connectives such as “And,” and “Not” (Hampton, 1997a, 1988a,b), and adjective-noun compounds such as “Red Apple” (Medin and Shoben, 1988; Medin, 1989; Kamp and Partee, 1995). The evidence collected during two decades of research suggests that it might not be possible to represent all the experimental data for concept combinations using the mathematical structures of fuzzy logic or probability theory. Quantum cognition proposes an alternative approach.

While traditional models based on classical logic, probability, or fuzzy set theory have failed to properly account for cognitive phenomena exhibiting non-classical probabilistic features, quantum models have consistently provided a framework that easily encompasses these and other so-called cognitive biases (Gilovich et al., 2002; Busemeyer et al., 2011) or paradoxical phenomena (Aerts et al., 2011a). Quantum inspired models have been successfully developed in the areas of decision making (Aerts et al., 2011b, 2012b; Busemeyer et al., 2011; Busemeyer and Bruza, 2012), psychology of categorization (Aerts and Aerts, 1995; Blutner et al., 2013; Sozzo, 2014), human memory (Bruza and Cole, 2005; Bruza et al., 2009, 2012), and finances (Khrennikov, 2009; Haven and Khrennikov, 2013). In this paper we will focus on the phenomena of concept conjunction. However, since our analysis and methodology is based on pure mathematical notions of the quantum mechanical framework, the results presented in this paper can be extended to other concept combinations (Veloz, 2015).

Aerts (2009) formally states the conditions that characterize the existence of a classical probability model for concept conjunction:

Definition 1. Let μ(A), μ(B), and μ(AB) be the membership weights of an exemplar p with respect to a pair of concepts A and B and their conjunction AB. We say that these membership weights are classical conjunction data if there exists a Kolmogorovian probability space (Ω, σ(Ω), P), and events EA, EB ∈ σ(Ω) such that

P(EA)=μ(A),P(EB)=μ(B),P(EAEB)=μ(AB).    (1)

Classical conjunction data characterizes the membership values of the conjunction of concepts that can be modeled in a classical probabilistic framework. It is therefore important to characterize the notion of classical conjunction data in terms of the membership weights.

Corollary 1. The membership weights μ(A), μ(B), and μ(AB) of an exemplar p with respect to concepts A, B, and their conjunction AB are classical conjunction data if and only if

0μ(AB)μ(A),    (2)
0μ(AB)μ(B),    (3)
0μ(A)+μ(B)μ(AB)1.    (4)

A large body of experimental evidence and a considerable amount of data analysis indicate that the membership of exemplars with respect to concept combinations does not form classical conjunction data (Fodor and Lepore, 1996; Hampton, 1997a,b; Aerts and Gabora, 2005a,b). Namely, the membership with respect to the conjunction of concepts is generally larger than the membership of one of the former concepts, and thus violates either conditions (2) or (3). This phenomenon is called single overextension. When conditions (2) and (3) are violated simultaneously, it is called double overextension. The violation of condition (4) is called the Kolmogorovian factor violation. We refer to (Pitowsky, 1989; Aerts, 2009) for an explanation of this phenomenon.

In Supplementary Table 1, we show two cases reported in Hampton (1988b). In the first case, the membership weight μ1(AB) of the item p1 = “coffee table” with respect to the conjunction A1B1 = “Furniture And Household Appliances” is single overextended with respect to the membership weights μ1(A) and μ1(B) of concepts A1 = “Furniture,” and B1 = “Household Appliances,” respectively. In the second case, membership weight μ2(AB) of the item p2 = “tree house” with respect to the conjunction A2B2 = “Building And Dwelling” is doubly overextended with respect to the membership weigths μ2(A) and μ2(B) of the concepts A2 = “Building,” and B2 = “Dwelling,” respectively.

The phenomenon of overextension has also been demonstrated not only for membership estimations, but also in typicality (Smith and Osherson, 1981; Hampton, 1996; Storms et al., 1998), property relevance (Fodor and Lepore, 1996; Hampton, 1997a,b; Aerts and Gabora, 2005a,b), and probability estimations (Tversky and Kahneman, 1983; Moro, 2009).

1.2. The Quantum Approach to Concept Combination

The quantum approach to concepts introduces two fundamental assumptions that depart from classical approaches:

A1 Concepts are not represented by a set of instances. Instead, a concept is assumed to exist in a state. A Hilbert space H is introduced, and a unit vector |ψ〉 ∈ H represents the state of the concept.

A2 Semantic estimations are not functions over the set of instances. Instead, a semantic estimation is a measurement operator, M : HH, that projects onto a subspace of H.

Concepts A and B are represented by the states |A〉 and |B〉, respectively. When we consider the conjunction AB of these two concepts, there are two different ways to combine the concepts (Aerts, 2009). The first considers the conjunction of concepts from an intuitive perspective in the sense that the connective And does not play a logical role in the combination AB; instead the conjunction AB is viewed as an emergent entity. In particular, the quantum model assumes that the state of the combined concept |AB〉 ∈ H is given by a superposition of the states of concepts A and B as follows:

|AB=12(|A+|B).    (5)

The second way considers the conjunction of concepts from a logical perspective, in the sense that And does play a logical role in the combination AB. In particular, the quantum model assumes that the state of the combined concept |C〉 is modeled in the tensor product space HH, where each space in the product captures the representation of the concepts in the combination, while the entire space represents the conjunction. The two quantum models of concept combination are presented in Supplementary Material. These two modes can be unified in a mathematical framework developed in quantum mechanics called Fock space (Aerts, 2007a, 2009).

A Fock space is a direct sum of tensor products of Hilbert spaces, where each space in the sum represents the state space of a system having different numbers of particles (Meyer, 1995). For the case of concepts, we model the state of the combination of two concepts in the two-sector Fock space:

F=H(HH).    (6)

The first space, H, also called the first sector, represents the concept combination as an emergent entity. The second space, HH, called the second sector, represents the concept combination as a logical entity. The state of the combined concept in the two-sector Fock space is hence a superposition of the two modes of combination.

For example, when |C〉 = |A〉 ⊗ |B〉, the state |ψ〉 of the concept combination is

yes

and the membership formula is given by

μ(AB)=n2(μ(A)+μ(B)2+(A|M|B))+1n2μ(A)μ(B),    (8)

for 0 ≤ n ≤ 1.

When n = 1, the membership weight μ(AB) corresponds to the sum of the average of μ(A) and μ(B), plus an interference term ℜ(〈A|M|B〉) bounded by

μ(A)μ(B)(A|M|B)μ(A)μ(B).

In the absence of interference, i.e., when ℜ(〈A|M|B〉) = 0, the membership weight is simply the average of the former membership weights. This particular case, which has been shown to provide a good first approximation to exemplars of conceptual conjunction (Aerts et al., 2012a), is overextended, and therefore non-classical. When n = 0, the membership weight corresponds to the product μ(A)μ(B), which is equivalent to the probability of two joint classical events that are independent. When 0 < n < 1, the state of the concept is in the superposition of the two modes of combination.

Finally, the membership operator for a certain exemplar with respect to the conjunction of two concepts is given by

MF=M(MM),    (9)

where M is the operator that measures membership of the exemplar in the first sector, and MM measures the membership of the exemplar with respect to the two concepts simultaneously in the second sector.

In addition to providing a suitable mathematical framework for cognitive models, quantum cognition also offers a different perspective on cognitive phenomena: uncertainty is described by means of superposed states (Aerts et al., 2011b), non-logical coherence involves interference (Aerts, 2009), order effects are revealed by incompatible measurements (Wang and Busemeyer, 2013), and certain “verb-noun” conceptual combinations mimic the structure of physically entangled particles (Aerts and Sozzo, 2014).

1.3. The Representation of Data

One of the reasons why quantum models of concept combinations have not been widely used is that the issue of data representation has been overlooked. Scholars have studied the capacity of quantum models to fit semantic estimations of concept combinations, and have presented concrete representations of the different estimations to validate the models (Aerts, 2007a,b, 2009; Aerts et al., 2012a; Sozzo, 2014); these concrete representations, however, model the data in an exemplar-based fashion, where one operator is used for all exemplars, but the conceptual state varies with exemplars.

For example, Aerts (2009) builds a quantum model in the Hilbert space ℂ3 to consider the exemplars “filing cabinet” and “heated waterbed” with respect to concepts A = “Furniture, B = “Household Appliances,” and their conjunction AB. For the first exemplar, we have μ(A) = 0.97, μ(B) = 0.31, and μ(AB) = 0.53. This case is represented by the vectors

yes

For the second exemplar, μ(A) = 1, μ(B) = 0.49, and μ(AB) = 0.78, and the state vectors are given by

|A=(0.71,0.71,0),|B=(0.49,0.49,0.71).    (11)

In both cases M is defined by the projection operator

M(x,y,z)(x,0,0).    (12)

Such concrete representations are useful to validate models, but unwieldy if one seeks to build a model that can be used for studying and comparing large amounts of data. Because the state is independent of the exemplar, it must remain the same for all measurements. But if we require the state representing the concept to remain fixed, then the number of measurement operators is restricted by the dimension of the Hilbert space H. In fact, because the membership operator is usually represented by the identity projector restricted to a smaller subspace, and the identity operator of the entire space and the null operator entail trivial measurements, the number of projectors available to represent membership measurements is restricted to n − 1, for n = dim(H). This implies that, if we consider n or more exemplars, then some exemplars will not have a unique membership operator. These issues become crucial in real-world situations involving concepts that entail thousands of exemplars (Tenenbaum et al., 2011).

In Section 2, we take a close look at the concrete representations of quantum models on each sector of the Fock space to identify the minimal dimensionality required to reach the modeling capacity of each of the sectors. In Section 3, we introduce the notion of unitary transformation for the first and second sectors of the Fock space separately, and propose concrete representations for concepts in these two models that require a single conceptual state, and a collection of exemplar-dependent operators. In Section 4, we use these representations to advance a conjecture concerning compatibility of measurements.

2. Dimensionality Analysis of the Two-Sector Fock Space Model

In what follows we determine the dimension of H required to model concept combinations in the first and second sectors of the two-sector Fock space model. To explore this question, we assume H = ℂn equipped with the standard inner product, and analyze how n relates to the representation of concepts.

2.1. First Sector Dimension Analysis

The Hilbert space model for concept conjunction requires two vectors, |A〉, |B〉 ∈ H, and an orthogonal projector, M : HH, such that

A|A=B|B=1,    (13)
A|B=0,    (14)
A|M|A=μ(A), B|M|B=μ(B),    (15)
μ(AB)=12(μ(A)+μ(B))+(A|M|B).    (16)

The next theorem shows that n = 3 is sufficient to build a model that satisfies conditions (13–16).

Theorem 1. Let μ(A), μ(B), and μ(AB) denote the membership of an exemplar with respect to concepts A, B, and their conjunction AB. The membership weights are compatible with a complex Hilbert space model H = ℂ3 if and only if

μ(AB)[ave(AB)dev(AB),ave(AB)+dev(AB)],    (17)

where

ave(AB)=12(μ(A)+μ(B)), anddev(AB)=min(μ(A)μ(B),(1μ(A))(1μ(B)).    (18)

Proof. We derive Equation (17) by applying conditions (13–16). First, if M is a zero- or three-dimensional projector, then

μ(A)=μ(B)=μ(AB)=0, orμ(A)=μ(B)=μ(AB)=1,    (19)

respectively. Thus, Equation (17) holds, and Equations (13–16) are satisfied by choosing |A〉 and |B〉 to be any two mutually orthogonal unit vectors.

Next, we consider the cases where M is either a one- or two-dimensional projector. We apply conditions (13–16) to vectors |A〉 and |B〉 in these two cases separately, and combine the results to obtain (Equation 17).

If M is a one-dimensional projector, then without loss of generality, we can choose

M(x,y,z)(x,0,0), and|A=(a1eiα1,a2eiα2,a3eiα3),|B=(b1eiβ1,b2eiβ2,b3eiβ3).    (20)

Note that conditions (13) and (15) are satisfied by choosing the coefficients in |A〉 and |B〉 as follows:

a1=μ(A); a2=λ1μ(A) ;a3=1λ1μ(A),b1=μ(B); b2=κ1μ(B) ;b3=1κ1μ(B),    (21)

with 0 ≤ λ ≤ 1, and 0 ≤ κ ≤ 1. Moreover, Equation (16) implies that μ(AB) is given by

μ(AB)=12(μ(A)+μ(B))+μ(A)μ(B)cos(α1β1).    (22)

We then apply condition (14) to obtain

μ(A)μ(B)cos(γ1)=(1μ(A))(1μ(B))F(λ,κ,cos(γ2),cos(γ3)),    (23)
μ(A)μ(B)sin(γ1)=(1μ(A))(1μ(B))F(λ,κ,sin(γ2),sin(γ3)),    (24)

where

F(λ,κ,f(x),f(y))=(λκf(x)+(1λ)(1κ)f(y)).    (25)

Since F(λ, κ, cos(γ2), cos(γ3)) is a convex combination of λκ and (1λ)(1κ), we have

F(λ,κ,cos(γ2),cos(γ3))||λκ|+|(1λ)(1κ)|.    (26)

We set

λ=cos(θ1), κ=cos(θ2),    (27)

for θ1, θ2 in [0,π2]. Then

1λ=sin(θ1),1κ=sin(θ2).    (28)

Substituting Equations (27) and (28) in Equation (26), we obtain

|F(λ,κ,cos(γ2),cos(γ3))||cos(θ1θ2)|1.    (29)

Then Equation (23) implies that

|μ(A)μ(B) cos(γ1)|(1μ(A))(1μ(B)).    (30)

Therefore, the interference term is bounded as follows:

|μ(A)μ(B) cos(γ1)|min(μ(A)μ(B),                               (1μ(A))(1μ(B)))                                =dev(AB).    (31)

Next, combining Equations (23) and (24), we obtain

μ(A)μ(B)=(1μ(A))(1μ(B))F^(λ,κ,γ2,γ3),    (32)

where

F^(λ,κ,γ2,γ3)=F2(λ,κ,cos(γ2),cos(γ3))                           +F2(λ,κ,sin(γ2),sin(γ3)).    (33)

Hence,

μ(A)+μ(B)=1+μ(A)μ(B)(11F^(λ,κ,γ2,γ3)).    (34)

We use the parametrization for λ and κ given by Equation (27), and apply Equations (29–33), to obtain

0F^(λ,κ,γ2,γ3)cos(θ1θ2)2+sin(θ1θ2)2=1.    (35)

Combining Equations (35) and (34) yields

μ(A)+μ(B)1.    (36)

Therefore, when M is a one-dimensional projector, conditions (13–16) imply

μ(AB)[ave(AB)dev(AB),ave(AB)+dev(AB)], andμ(A)+μ(B)1.    (37)

Next, consider the case in which M is a two dimensional projector. Without loss of generality, we can assume

M(x,y,z)(x,y,0).

The requirements Equations (13) and (15) are satisfied by choosing the coefficients in |A〉, |B〉 as follows

a1=λμ(A); a2=1λμ(A) ;a3=1μ(A),b1=κμ(B); b2=1κμ(B) ;b3=1μ(B),    (38)

with 0 ≤ λ ≤ 1, and 0 ≤ κ ≤ 1. Moreover, Equation (16) implies that μ(AB) is given by

μ(AB)=12(μ(A)+μ(B))+μ(A)μ(B)F(λ,κ,cos(γ1),cos(γ2)).    (39)

We apply condition (14) to obtain

μ(A)μ(B)F(λ,κ,cos(γ1),cos(γ2))=(1μ(A))(1μ(B))cos(γ3).    (40)

Since F(λ, κ, cos(γ1), cos(γ2)) ≤ 1, Equation (40) implies that

|μ(A)μ(B)F(λ,κ,cos(γ1),cos(γ2))| min(μ(A)μ(B),                                                      (1μ(A))(1μ(B)))                                                        =dev(AB).    (41)

We repeat the procedure used in the one-dimensional case to obtain

μ(A)μ(B)F^(λ,κ,γ1,γ2)=(1μ(A))(1μ(B)).    (42)

Since 0F^(λ,κ,γ1,γ2)1, Equation (42) yields

1μ(A)+μ(B).    (43)

Therefore, when M is a two-dimensional projector, conditions (13–16) imply

μ(AB)[ave(AB)dev(AB),ave(AB)+dev(AB)], and1μ(A)+μ(B).    (44)

We complete the proof by merging Equations (37) and (44).

The general case, H = ℂn for n > 3, doesn't provide additional modeling power since the condition given by Equation (17) remains. Also, the case H = ℂ2 is more restrictive than the H = ℂ3 case. In fact, membership data compatible with conditions (13–16) for H = ℂ2 must satisfy μ(A) + μ(B) = 1 (Veloz, 2015).

2.2. Second Sector Dimension Analysis

The second sector of the two-sector Fock space requires a concept combination state |C〉 ∈ ℂn ⊗ ℂn and an operator M : ℂn → ℂn, such that |C〉 restricted to the first sector represents the concept A, and |C〉 restricted to the second sector represents the concept B. However, |C〉 cannot in general be decomposed as a tensor product of the type |CA〉 ⊗ |CB〉, for |CA,|CB n. Therefore, |C〉 is usually a non-separable state.

To recover the probabilistic structure of the former concepts in the combination, the operators M1 and 1M are applied to |C〉 to obtain μ(A) and μ(B), respectively. Moreover, since |C〉 as a whole represents the concept combination AB, then the operator MM is applied to |C〉 to obtain μ(AB).

The following definition summarizes how data is represented in the second sector.

Definition 2. Let μ = {μ(A), μ(B), μ(AB)} be a triplet denoting the membership of concepts A, B, and their conjunction AB. We say that the triplet μ admits a representation inn ⊗ ℂn if there exists a unit vector |C〉 ∈ ℂn ⊗ ℂn, and an operator M:ℂn → ℂn such that

C|MA|C=C|M1|C=μ(A),    (45)
C|MB|C=C|1M|C=μ(B),    (46)
C|M|C=C|MM|C=μ(AB).    (47)

Let {|i}i=1 be the canonical basis of ℂn. Without loss of generality, we can take M to be an orthogonal projector on the subspace of ℂn spanned by the basis elements |1〉, …, |r〉, with r < n. Hence,

M(x1,,xn)(x1,,xr,0,,0).

Next, let |C〉 be a unit vector in ℂn ⊗ ℂn. That is,

yes

and

yes

We now prove that the operator M and the vector |C〉 above satisfy Equations (45–47) if and only if μ(A), μ(B), and μ(AB) are classical conjunction data.

Theorem 2. Let μ = {μ(A), μ(B), μ(AB)} be a triplet denoting the membership of concepts A, B, and their conjunction AB. The triplet μ is classical conjunction data if and only if it admits a representation inn ⊗ ℂn with n = 2.

Proof. If μ admits a representation in ℂ2 ⊗ ℂ2, there exists a unit vector |C〉 ∈ ℂ2 ⊗ ℂ2 and an operator M such that Equations (45–47) are satisfied. If μ(A) = μ(B) = μ(AB) = 0 or 1, we can choose |C〉 to be any unit vector in ℂ2 ⊗ ℂ2, and M to be a zero- or two-dimensional projector, respectively. Otherwise, let {|1〉, |2〉} be the canonical basis for ℂ2. Without loss of generality, we can define |C〉 by

yes

and M by the one-dimensional projector into the subspace determined by |1〉. Note that

   μ(A)=C|M1|C=c112+c122,   μ(B)=C|1M|C=c112+c212,μ(AB)=C|MM|C=c112.    (51)

Then, clearly μ(AB) ≤ μ(A), μ(AB) ≤ μ(B), and since |C〉 is a unit vector,

μ(A)+μ(B)μ(AB)=c112+c122+c2121.    (52)

Therefore, μ is classical conjunction data. The other implication is proven by taking M to be the same one-dimensional projector, and |C〉 such that

c11=μ(AB),c12=μ(A)μ(AB),c21=μ(B)μ(AB),c22=1μ(A)μ(B)+μ(AB),

and γij = 0, for i, j = 1, 2.

Theorem 2 proves the strict equivalence between classical conjunction data and the model of conjunction built in ℂ2 ⊗ ℂ2.

3. Unitary Transformations and Data Representation

We now investigate how multiple exemplars can be concretely represented using a single concept state. To do so, we use unitary transformations to identify a basis of the realization space where multiple exemplars can be represented simultaneously. In this new framework, concrete representations are consistent with the cognitive principles of the quantum model of concepts. Namely, a concept exists in a single state for all exemplars, and the measurement of membership of an exemplar depends on the exemplar to be measured rather than on the concept state.

3.1. Data Representation in the First Sector

The following definition and theorem introduce the notion of data representation in the first sector that is consistent with the cognitive principles of the quantum model of concepts in ℂ3.

Definition 3. Let μ={μi(A),μi(B),μi(AB)}i=1k be a set of experimental data, where μi(x) is the semantic estimation of an exemplar pi with respect to concepts A, B, and their conjunction AB. A representation of μ in3 is defined as a pair of unit vectors |A〉, |B〉 ∈3, and a collection of orthogonal projectors Mi:33 such that conditions (13–16) are satisfied for i = 1, …, k. We say (|A,|B,{Mi}i=1k) is a representation of μ in3.

Theorem 3. Let μ={μi(A),μi(B),μi(AB)}i=1k be a set of experimental data, where μi(x) is the semantic estimation of exemplar pi with respect to concepts A, B, and their conjunction AB. The set of data μ has a representation in3 if and only if for all i = 1, …, k

μi(AB)[avei(AB)devi(AB),avei(AB)+devi(AB)].    (53)

Proof. Let |A〉 = (1, 0, 0), |B〉 = (0, 1, 0), and |C〉 = (0, 0, 1) be the canonical basis for ℂ3. We prove that, if Equation (53) is satisfied for each i = 1, …, k then there exists an orthogonal projector Mi such that conditions (13–16) are satisfied for |A〉, |B〉, and Mi.

Since μi(A), μi(B) and μi(AB) satisfy (Equation 53), by Theorem 1 for each i ∈ {1, …, k} there exist two vectors,

yes

and an orthogonal projector M^i such that Equations (13–16) are satisfied. Thus, the pair of vectors |Ai〉 and |Bi〉, as constructed in the proof of Theorem 1, are orthonormal. We set |Ci〉 = |Ai〉 × |Bi〉 so that the set {|Ai〉, |Bi〉, |Ci〉} forms an orthonormal basis for ℂ3 for any i ∈ {1, …, k}. Next, we define the operator Ui by

Ui=(Ai|AAi|BAi|CBi|ABi|BBi|CCi|ACi|BCi|C).    (55)

Ui is a unitary matrix whose action induces a change from the basis {|Ai〉, |Bi〉, |Ci〉} to the basis {|A〉, |B〉, |C〉}. Note that Ui|Ai〉 = |A〉, Ui|Bi〉 = |B〉, and Ui|Ci〉 = |C〉.

We can also use the operator Ui to represent M^i in the canonical basis {|A〉, |B〉, |C〉} as follows:

Mi=UiM^iUi1.    (56)

We use the fact that I=Ui1Ui=UiUi1 to show that the remaining conditions are satisfied. That is, for each i = 1, …, k,

μi(A)=Ai|M^i|Ai=AiUi1|UiM^iUi1|UiAi=A|Mi|A,μi(B)=Bi|M^i|Bi=BiUi1|UiM^iUi1|UiBi=B|Mi|B,    (57)

and

μi(AB)=12(μ(A)+μ(B))+(Ai|M^i|Bi)            =12(μ(A)+μ(B))+(AiUi1|UiM^iUi1|UiAi)            =12(μ(A)+μ(B))+(A|Mi|B).    (58)

Theorem 3 provides a data representation in terms of a single pair of vectors |A〉 and |B〉, and a set of projectors Mi, for i = 1, …, k, corresponding to the membership operator for each exemplar. Since the unitary transformations preserve the inner product between vectors and operators, the values of the membership estimations μi(A), μi(B), and μi(AB) are preserved.

Consider for example the exemplars p =“filing cabinet” and q =“heated waterbed” mentioned in Section 1.3. These can now be represented by the states |A〉 = (1, 0, 0), |B〉 = (0, 1, 0) and the following measurement operators

yes

From a geometric perspective, the operators Mp and Mq correspond to rotations of the one-dimensional projector M(x, y, z) → (x, 0, 0) in ℂ3.

3.2. Data Representation in the Second Sector

We now apply unitary transformations in the concrete representations of the tensor product model in ℂn ⊗ ℂn. We first define different types of representations for multiple exemplars, and then provide explicit representation theorems for the cases n = 2 and 3.

Definition 4. A zero-type representation of μi=1k on the tensor product space ℂnn is a unit vector |C〉 ∈n ⊗ ℂn, and a collection of orthogonal projectors {MiA,MiB}i=1k fromn ⊗ ℂn ton ⊗ ℂn, such that conditions (47)–(49) are satisfied with Mi=MiAMiB, for i = 1, …, k. We say (|C,|{MiA,MiB}i=1k) is a zero-type representation of μi=1k inn ⊗ ℂn.

The zero-type representation is, mathematically speaking, the most general representation in the tensor product model that is consistent with the modeling principles of quantum cognition because it assumes a single concept state |C〉, and a collection of measurements that represent the membership weight estimations. However, this representation cannot be appropriately interpreted because MiA and MiB can be entangled measurements, for i = 1, …, k.

A more reasonable representation of data assumes that yes, and yes, for i = 1, …, k. Therefore, these operators are not entangled because they act on different sides of ℂ3 ⊗ ℂ3.

Definition 5. A first-type representation of μi=1k on the tensor product spacen ⊗ ℂn is a unit vector |C〉 ∈n ⊗ ℂn, and a collection of orthogonal projectors Mi fromn ton, for i = 1, …, k, such that yes is a zero-type representation of μi=1k inn ⊗ ℂn.

The first-type representation is a direct extension of the representation of individual exemplars in Definition 2, and thus it is interpreted according to such representation: The state |C〉 describes the situation of having two concepts and their combination, and Mi represents the semantic estimation of exemplar pi, i = 1, …, k.

The zero- and first-type representations require different conditions to model a collection of exemplars for a pair of concepts and their conjunction. While the first-type corresponds to the natural way to represent a pair of systems in quantum physics, and thus is the natural way to define a representation in the tensor product model for concepts, the zero-type provides a more general way to build concrete representations because it does not impose a product structure on the concept state or on the membership operators for the exemplars.

In fact, from Definitions 4–5 it is trivial to deduce that a first-type representation is also a zero-type representation.

The following theorem characterizes the cases when a set of data has a zero-type representation in ℂ2 ⊗ ℂ2.

Theorem 4. The set of data μi=1k has a zero-type representation in2 ⊗ ℂ2 if and only if μi is classical conjunction data for i = 1, …, k.

Proof. For each i = 1, …, k, we use the construction in the proof of Theorem 2 to obtain a tensor |Ci˜ and a one-dimensional projector M~ such that yes, and M~i=M~M~. This gives the tensor product representation of μi. Next, we use unitary transformations to change this representation so that |Ci˜ is a vector in the canonical basis of ℂ2 ⊗ ℂ2. To facilitate the notation, we will make use of the isomorphism yes between ℂ2 ⊗ ℂ2 and ℂ4. Let

(1,0,0,0)=|e1,(0,1,0,0)=|e2,(0,0,1,0)=|e3,(0,0,0,1)=|e4.    (60)

We define

yes

The isomorphism allows us to represent |Ci˜ by a vector |Ci〉 in ℂ4.

We can prove the theorem by building a unitary transformation that takes |Ci〉 to one of the canonical basis vectors of ℂ4, and use this transformation to represent the operators M~A, M~B, and M~ by the operators MA,MB, and M in ℂ4. Next, we apply the the inverse isomorphism −1 to map these new representations to ℂ2 ⊗ ℂ2.

Let |Di〉, |Ei〉, |Fi〉 be three vectors in ℂ4 such that

Di|Di=Ei|Ei=Fi|Fi=1,Ci|Di=Ci|Ei=Ci|Fi=0,Di|Ei=Di|Fi=Ei|Fi=0.    (62)

The vectors |Ci〉, |Di〉, |Ei〉, and |Fi〉 form an orthonormal basis for ℂ4.

Let

Ui=(Ci|e1Ci|e2Ci|e3Ci|e4Di|e1Di|e2Di|e3Di|e4Ei|e1Ei|e2Ei|e3Ei|e4Fi|e1Fi|e2Fi|e3Fi|e4).    (63)

Note that Ui is a unitary matrix whose action induces a change from the basis {|Ci〉, |Di〉, |Ei〉, |Fi〉} to the basis {|ej}j=14. In fact,

Ui|Ci=|e1, Ui|Di=|e2, Ui|Ei=|e3, and Ui|Fi=|e4.

The operator Ui can now be used to change the basis in which MiA,MiB, and Mi are represented, to the basis {|ej}j=14:

 M¯iA=UiMiAUi1, M¯iB=UiMiBUi1,M¯i=UiMiUi1.    (64)

Since yes, we obtain

   μi(A)=Ci|MiA|Ci=CiUi1|UiMiAUi1|UiCi=e1|M¯iA|e1,   μi(B)=Ci|MiB|Ci=CiUi1|UiMiBUi1|UiCi=e1|M¯iB|e1,μi(AB)=Ci|Mi|Ci=CiUi1|UiMiUi1|UiCi=e1|M¯i|e1.    (65)

We then use the inverse isomorphism yes−1 to obtain a zero-type representation in ℂ2 ⊗ ℂ2:

yes

We have constructed a zero-type representation (|1|1{MiA,MiB}i=1k) from a collection of representations (|Ci〉, M) for the exemplars pi with M(x, y) → (x, 0) obtained from Theorem 2.

In the construction of Theorem 4, note that when Equation (66) entails operators MiA and MiB that are of the form yes and yes, then the representation is also of the first-type.

Stating the necessary and sufficient conditions required for a set of data to have first-type representation is out of the scope of this paper. However, we now introduce another type of representation that is mathematically simpler, and can be used to obtain sufficient conditions for a first-type representation.

Definition 6. A second-type representation of μi=1k on the tensor product spacen ⊗ ℂn is a pair of unit vectors |A〉, B〉 ∈n, and a collection of orthogonal projectors Mi fromn ton, for i = 1, …, k, such that yes is a zero-type representation of μi=1k inn ⊗ ℂn.

The second-type is a mathematical simplification of the first-type representation that assumes |C〉 to be a product state.

Lemma 1. The set of data μi=1k has a second-type representation in2 ⊗ ℂ2 if and only if for each i = 1, …, k there exist |Ai,|Bi,MˇiA, and MˇiB such that Equations (45–47) are satisfied.

Proof. Let Ui(A),Ui(B):22 be the unitary transformations that map |Ai〉 to |1〉 and |Bi〉 to |1〉 respectively, for i = 1, …, k. Then, it is straightforward to show thatyes is a second-type representation of μi=1k with

MiA=Ui(A)1MˇiAUi(A),MiB=Ui(B)1MˇiBUi(B).    (67)

Theorem 4 and Lemma 1 characterize the sets of data that have a zero- and second-type representations. Since the first-type representation is less general than the zero-type representation, but more general than the second-type representation, these results can be applied to obtain an upper and lower bound for the number of exemplars that have a first-type representation in a given set of data.

Note that Theorem 4 is built in ℂ2 ⊗ ℂ2. We now extend our results to ℂ3 ⊗ ℂ3 so they become compatible with the representation analysis developed in Section 3.1 for a Hilbert space model in ℂ3. The next corollary extends the proof of Theorem 4 to the space ℂ3 ⊗ ℂ3.

Corollary 2. If the set of data μi=1k has a zero-type representation in2 ⊗ ℂ2, then μi=1k has a zero-type representation in3 ⊗ ℂ3.

Proof. Let (|C,{MiA,MiB}i=1k) be a zero-type representation of μi=1k in2 ⊗ ℂ2. We can create a vector

|C*=i,j=13cij*|i |j    (68)

such that it is the trivial embedding of

|C=i,j=12cij|i|j    (69)

in ℂ3 ⊗ ℂ3 by choosing

cij*={ciji,j{1,2}0else.    (70)

Similarly, we can also create operators MiA* and MiB* by using the trivial embedding in such a way that the actions of the operators MiA and MiB on ℂ2 ⊗ ℂ2 are preserved. This completes the proof.

Since second-type representations are also first- and zero-type representations, we can apply Corollary 3.2 to obtain a first- and second-type representation in ℂ3 ⊗ ℂ3.

4. A Conjecture About Compatibility of Exemplars

In quantum theory, measurement operators can be incompatible. That is, when we consider two different observables, the result of their sequential application can depend on the order in which they are applied. The fact that quantum measurements can be incompatible is related to fundamental differences between the quantum and classical realms, such as the observer phenomena, and the Heisenberg uncertainty principle (Heisenberg, 1927; Isham, 2001).

Definition 7. Given two operators M1 and M2 represented in the same basis. We say that M1 and M2 represent compatible observables if and only if the commutator operator

[M1,M2] = M1M2M2M1 = 0.    (71)

Otherwise, the operators represent incompatible observables.

In terms of cognitive phenomena, sequential measurements could be interpreted as consecutive cognitive actions where the previous action serves as a context for the next action (Busemeyer and Wang, 2007; Wang and Busemeyer, 2013). Since in our concrete representations membership operators are represented in the same basis for all exemplars pi = 1, …, k, it is now possible to test whether or not these measurement operators commute. If we find exemplars whose operators are non-commutative, then we can conjecture the existence of a fundamental limit to the precision with which the membership of these exemplars can be known simultaneously.

Note that we would expect that classical probabilistic models should be compatible, and because the classical probabilistic model and the tensor product model are equivalent, tensor product operators obtained from the data should also be compatible for the vector representing the conceptual situation. However, Hilbert space models could exhibit incompatible measurements for certain data on concept combination, as the Hilbert space model represents non-classical measurements.

We introduce the following definitions to characterize the compatibility of exemplars in ℂ3 and in ℂ3 ⊗ ℂ3:

Definition 8. Let |A〉 = (1, 0, 0), |B〉 = (0, 1, 0), and {M1, M2} be a representation in3 of {(μi(A),μi(B),μi(AB))}i=12, and set

cA=A|[M1,M2]|A,cB=B|M1,M2]|B,cAB=12(A|+B|)[M1,M2](|A + |B).    (72)

We say p1 and p2 are compatible with respect to the concepts A, B, and AB if and only if cA = 0, cB = 0, and cAB = 0, respectively.

For simplicity, we will study compatibility for zero-type representations in ℂ3 ⊗ ℂ3.

Definition 9. Let |C〉 = (1, 0, 0) ⊗ (1, 0, 0), {M1A,M1B,M1}, and {M2A,M2B,M2} be a zero-type representation of data in3 ⊗ ℂ3 of {(μi(A),μi(B),μi(AB))}i=12, and set

cA=C|[M1A,M2A]|C,cB=C|[M1B,M2B]|C,cAB=C|[M1,M2]|B).    (73)

We say p1 and p2 are compatible with respect to concepts A, B, and AB if and only if cA=0, cB=0, and cAB=0, respectively.

We have verified the compatibility of exemplars for each conceptual combination that can be modeled in ℂ3 and in ℂ3 ⊗ ℂ3 using the data in Hampton (1988a,b). The results support our predictions. We have found that the tensor product model always leads to compatible measurements, and that the Hilbert space model leads to incompatible measurements in most cases.

For example, consider the concepts A = “Machine” and B = “Vehicle,” and the exemplars p5 = “sailboat” and p12 = “skateboard.” For the case of conceptual conjunction, we have

μ5(A)=0.56,μ5(B)=0.8,μ5(AB)=0.42, andμ12(A)=0.28,μ12(B)=0.84,μ12(AB)=0.34.    (74)

Note that exemplar p5 satisfies the conditions of Theorems 1 and 2. Thus, it can be represented in both ℂ3 and in ℂ3 ⊗ ℂ3. However, the exemplar p12 is singly overextended. Therefore, we can only represent the two exemplars simultaneously in ℂ3.

When we apply Theorems 1 and 3, and Definition 8, on these data sets, we obtain

yes

Thus, exemplars p5 and p12 are incompatible. Moreover, note that the incompatibility is larger for the conjunction of the concepts than for each of the former concepts.

As a second example, consider the concepts A = “Building,” and B = “Dwelling,” and the exemplars p2 = “cave,” and p10 = “synagogue,” whose memberships are given by

μ2(A)=0.28, μ2(B)=0.85, μ2(AB)=0.28, andμ10(A)=0.93,μ10(B)=0.49,μ10(AB)=0.45.    (76)

Both exemplars satisfy the conditions of Theorem 2. Applying Theorems 2 and 4, and Definition 9, we obtain

cA=cB=cAB=0.

This is consistent with our expectations because the representation in the second sector ℂ3 ⊗ ℂ3 correspond to classical (and thus compatible) measurements.

Since our data was collected presenting the exemplars in only one specific order (Hampton, 1988b), these computations demonstrate that we can predict order effects by determining the exemplars that are incompatible. The results presented here are, however, speculative since there is no experimental data where order effects have been recorded that could be used to contrast our computations. While our data set does not allow us to make a strong claim, we conjecture that order effects are predictable, and suggest that the concrete representations proposed in this paper could be used to develop Heisenberg-like uncertainty relations in the context of conceptual combinations.

5. Conclusion and Future Work

In this paper, we have made some advances on the representational aspects of the quantum model for concept combinations. First, we proved that the first and second sectors of the two-sector Fock space model of concept conjunctions can be concretely represented in ℂ3 and ℂ3 ⊗ ℂ3, respectively. Next, we introduced unitary transformations to provide concrete representations that are consistent with the cognitive principles of the quantum model of concepts, and used these concrete representations to study the question of measurement compatibility.

The representations introduced here could be an important tool for future applications. First, since they are consistent with the cognitive principles of the quantum model of concepts, the model could easily be introduced to a wider audience, and extended to produce concrete representations in the two-sector Fock space model. Second, they can be adopted as a representational standard for different groups who seek to develop their own computational implementations of the model. Third, the fact that all the measurements are represented in a single basis constitutes a tremendous mathematical advantage for studying the probabilistic structure of concepts.

The evidence obtained in the application of our representations to the issue of exemplar compatibility is consistent with the assumptions of the model. Since the second sector entails logical reasoning, measurements in the tensor product model should be compatible. However, incompatible measurements are likely to be found in the Hilbert space model, since the first sector is associated with non-logical or intuitive reasoning. Moreover, this line of enquiry invites us to explore possible relations between the projector operator structure and the meaning of the exemplar.

In summary, the introduction of unitary transformations and the subsequent application to develop concrete representations of concepts and their combinations seems to be a promising line of research that has the potential to expand both theoretical and applied research in quantum cognition.

Funding

This research has been funded by an internal grant from the I.K Barber school of Arts and Sciences at UBC Okanagan.

Conflict of Interest Statement

The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Acknowledgments

We would like to acknowledge Diederik Aerts and Sandro Sozzo for discussions and insights that contributed to the development of this work.

Supplementary Material

The Supplementary Material for this article can be found online at: http://journal.frontiersin.org/article/10.3389/fpsyg.2015.01734

References

Aerts, D. (2007a). General quantum modeling of combining concepts: a quantum field model in fock space. arXiv preprint arXiv:0705.1740

Google Scholar

Aerts, D. (2007b). Quantum interference and superposition in cognition: a theory for the disjunction of concepts. arxiv.org/abs/0705.0975

Aerts, D. (2009). Quantum structure in cognition. J. Math. Psychol. 53, 314–348. doi: 10.1016/j.jmp.2009.04.005

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Aerts, D., and Aerts, S. (1995). Application of quantum statistics in psychological studies of decision processes. Found. Sci. 1, 85–97. doi: 10.1007/978-94-015-8816-4_11

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Aerts, D., Broekaert, J., and Gabora, L. (2011a). A case for applying an abstracted quantum formalism to cognition. New Ideas Psychol. 29, 136–146. doi: 10.1016/j.newideapsych.2010.06.002

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Aerts, D., Broekaert, J., Gabora, L., and Veloz, T. (2012a). “The guppy effect as interference,” in Quantum Interaction (Berlin; Heidelberg: Springer), 36–47. doi: 10.1007/978-3-642-35659-9_4

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Aerts, D., D'Hooghe, B., and Sozzo, S. (2011b). “A quantum cognition analysis of the Ellsberg paradox,” in Quantum Interaction (Berlin; Heidelberg: Springer), 95–104. doi: 10.1007/978-3-642-24971-6_10

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Aerts, D., and Gabora, L. (2005a). A state-context-property model of concepts and their combinations i: the structure of the sets of contexts and properties. Kybernetes 34, 151–175. doi: 10.1108/03684920510575799

CrossRef Full Text

Aerts, D., and Gabora, L. (2005b). A state-context-property model of concepts and their combinations ii: a hilbert space representation. Kybernetes 34, 176–204. doi: 10.1108/03684920510575807

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Aerts, D., Gabora, L., and Sozzo, S. (2013). Concepts and their dynamics: a quantum-theoretic modeling of human thought. Topics Cognit. Sci. 5, 737–772. doi: 10.1111/tops.12042

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Aerts, D., and Sozzo, S. (2011). “Quantum structure in cognition: why and how concepts are entangled,” in Quantum Interaction (Berlin; Heidelberg: Springer), 116–127. doi: 10.1007/978-3-642-24971-6_12

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Aerts, D., and Sozzo, S. (2014). Quantum entanglement in concept combinations. Int. J. Theor. Phys. 53, 3587–3603. doi: 10.1007/s10773-013-1946-z

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Aerts, D., Sozzo, S., and Tapia, J. (2012b). “A quantum model for the Ellsberg and Machina paradoxes,” in Quantum Interaction (Berlin; Heidelberg: Springer), 48–59. doi: 10.1007/978-3-642-35659-9_5

CrossRef Full Text

Blutner, R., Pothos, E. M., and Bruza, P. (2013). A quantum probability perspective on borderline vagueness. Topics Cognit. Sci. 5, 711–736. doi: 10.1111/tops.12041

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bruza, P., Kitto, K., Nelson, D., and McEvoy, C. (2009). Is there something quantum-like about the human mental lexicon? J. Math. Psychol. 53, 362–377. doi: 10.1016/j.jmp.2009.04.004

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bruza, P., Kitto, K., Ramm, L., Sitbon, L., Song, D., and Blomberg, S. (2012). Quantum-like non-separability of concept combinations, emergent associates and abduction. Logic J. IGPL 20, 445–457. doi: 10.1093/jigpal/jzq049

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bruza, P. D., and Cole, R. (2005). “Quantum logic of semantic space: an exploratory investigation of context effects in practical reasoning,” in We Will Show Them: Essays in Honour of Dov Gabbay, Vol. 1, eds S. Artemov, H. Barringer, A. S. d'Avila Garcez, L. C. Lamb, and J. Woods (London: College Publications), 339–361.

Busemeyer, J., and Wang, Z. (2007). “Quantum information processing explanation for interactions between inferences and decisions,” in AAAI Spring Symposium: Quantum Interaction (Stanford, CA: AAAI), 91–97.

Busemeyer, J. R., and Bruza, P. D. (2012). Quantum Models of Cognition and Decision. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Google Scholar

Busemeyer, J. R., Pothos, E. M., Franco, R., and Trueblood, J. S. (2011). A quantum theoretical explanation for probability judgment errors. Psychol. Rev. 118, 193. doi: 10.1037/a0022542

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Fodor, J. (1998). Concepts: Where Cognitive Science Went Wrong. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Fodor, J., and Lepore, E. (1996). The red herring and the pet fish: why concepts still can't be prototypes. Cognition 58, 253–270. doi: 10.1016/0010-0277(95)00694-X

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gilovich, T., Griffin, D., and Kahneman, D. (2002). Heuristics and Biases: The Psychology of Intuitive Judgment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Google Scholar

Hampton, J. (1988a). Disjunction of natural concepts. Memory Cogn. 16, 579–591. doi: 10.3758/BF03197059

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hampton, J. (1997a). Inheritance of attributes in natural concept conjunctions. Memory Cogn. 15, 55–71. doi: 10.3758/BF03197712

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hampton, J. A. (1997b). “Emergent attributes in combined concepts,” in Creative Thought: An Investigation of Conceptual Structures and Processes, eds T. B. Ward, S. M. Smith, and J. Vaid (Washington, DC: American Psychological Association), 83–110.

Hampton, J. A. (1988b). Overextension of conjunctive concepts: evidence for a unitary model of concept typicality and class inclusion. J. Exp. Psychol. Learn. Mem. Cogn. 14, 12. doi: 10.1037/0278-7393.14.1.12

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hampton, J. A. (1996). Conjunctions of visually based categories: overextension and compensation. J. Exp. Psychol. Learn. Mem. Cogn. 22, 378. doi: 10.1037/0278-7393.22.2.378

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Haven, E., and Khrennikov, A. (2013). Quantum Social Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Google Scholar

Heisenberg, W. (1927). Über den anschaulichen inhalt der quantentheoretischen kinematik und mechanik. Zeitschrift Phys. 43, 172–198. doi: 10.1007/BF01397280

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Isham, C. J. (2001). Lectures on Quantum Theory. New Delhi: Allied Publishers.

Google Scholar

Kamp, H., and Partee, B. (1995). Prototype theory and compositionality. Cognition 57, 121–191. doi: 10.1016/0010-0277(94)00659-9

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Khrennikov, A. (2009). Quantum-like model of cognitive decision making and information processing. Biosystems 95, 179–187. doi: 10.1016/j.biosystems.2008.10.004

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Medin, D. (1989). Concepts and conceptual structure. Am. Psychol. 44, 1469–1481. doi: 10.1037/0003-066X.44.12.1469

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Medin, D. L., and Shoben, E. J. (1988). Context and structure in conceptual combination. Cogn. Psychol. 20, 158–190. doi: 10.1016/0010-0285(88)90018-7

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Meyer, P. A. (1995). Quantum Probability for Probabilists, Vol. 1538. Heidelberg: Springer Science & Business Media.

Google Scholar

Moro, R. (2009). On the nature of the conjunction fallacy. Synthese 171, 1–24. doi: 10.1007/s11229-008-9377-8

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pitowsky, I. (1989). Quantum Probability – Quantum Logic, Vol. 321. Berlin: Springer.

Google Scholar

Pothos, E. M., and Busemeyer, J. R. (2013). Can quantum probability provide a new direction for cognitive modeling? Behav. Brain Sci. 36, 255–274. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X12001525

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Rips, L. J. (1995). The current status of research on concept combination. Mind Lang. 10, 72–104. doi: 10.1111/j.1468-0017.1995.tb00006.x

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Smith, E., and Osherson, D. (1981). On the adequacy of prototype theory as a theory of concepts. Cognition 9, 35–38. doi: 10.1016/0010-0277(81)90013-5

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Sozzo, S. (2014). A quantum probability explanation in fock space for borderline contradictions. J. Math. Psychol. 58, 1–12. doi: 10.1016/j.jmp.2013.11.001

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Storms, G., De Boeck, P., Van Mechelen, I., and Ruts, W. (1998). Not guppies, nor goldfish, but tumble dryers, noriega, jesse jackson, panties, car crashes, bird books, and stevie wonder. Memory Cognit. 26, 143–145. doi: 10.3758/BF03211377

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Tenenbaum, J., Kemp, C., Griffiths, T., and Goodman, N. (2011). How to grow a mind: statistics, structure, and abstraction. Science 331, 1279–1286. doi: 10.1126/science.1192788

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Tversky, A., and Kahneman, D. (1983). Extensional versus intuitive reasoning: the conjunction fallacy in probability judgment. Psychol. Rev. 90, 293. doi: 10.1037/0033-295X.90.4.293

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Veloz, T. (2015). Towards a Quantum Theory of Cognition: History, Development, and Perspectives. Ph.D. thesis, University of British Columbia - Okanagan.

Wang, Z., and Busemeyer, J. R. (2013). A quantum question order model supported by empirical tests of an A Priori and precise prediction. Topics Cogn. Sci. 5, 689–710. doi: 10.1111/tops.12040

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Keywords: concept combination, quantum cognition, data representation, unitary transformation, conjunction

Citation: Veloz T and Desjardins S (2015) Unitary Transformations in the Quantum Model for Conceptual Conjunctions and Its Application to Data Representation. Front. Psychol. 6:1734. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2015.01734

Received: 03 August 2015; Accepted: 28 October 2015;
Published: 12 November 2015.

Edited by:

Sandro Sozzo, University of Leicester, UK

Reviewed by:

Zheng Wang, Ohio State University, USA
Jose Acacio De Barros, San Francisco State University, USA

Copyright © 2015 Veloz and Desjardins. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) or licensor are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Tomas Veloz, dHZlbG96QGdtYWlsLmNvbQ==

These authors have contributed equally to this work.

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.