GENERAL COMMENTARY article

Front. Psychol., 22 April 2025

Sec. Mindfulness

Volume 16 - 2025 | https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2025.1565835

Commentary: Mindfulness and CBT: a conceptual integration bridging ancient wisdom and modern cognitive theories of psychopathology

  • Department of Psychology, Faculty of Biomedical and Health Sciences, Universidad Europea de Madrid, Villaviciosa de Odón, Spain

1 Introduction

I read Beshai's (2024) conceptual analysis on mindfulness and cognitive behavioral therapy (CBT) with interest. The author seeks to “illustrate how mindfulness, as a third-wave approach, can complement and enhance first- and second-wave approaches.”

The so-called cognitive behavioral therapies comprise a variety of therapeutic approaches typically categorized into three waves: first (e.g., behavior therapy and behavior modification), second (e.g., rational emotive behavior therapy and CBT), and third (e.g., acceptance and commitment therapy (ACT), dialectical behavioral therapy, and functional analytic psychotherapy) (Hayes, 2004). Despite broad similarities, such as shared techniques/strategies and a focus on the present, cognitive behavioral therapies are underpinned by different philosophical assumptions (O'Donohue and Chin, 2022). Herein, I discuss theoretical inconsistencies pertaining to the implementation of mindfulness within Beckian CBT. I illustrate these inconsistencies by comparing CBT and ACT— the therapeutic approaches that have arguably received the most attention within their respective waves—while relying on a secular view of mindfulness as defined by Kabat-Zinn (2003): “paying attention on purpose, in the present moment, and non-judgementally to the unfolding of experience moment by moment.”

2 Philosophical assumptions

CBT is based on Stoicism (Beck et al., 1979), a pre-Socratic philosophy emphasizing the rational control of thought and emotion. The influence of Stoicism is evident in CBT's emphasis on teaching clients to critically assess and modify the content of dysfunctional thoughts/beliefs to positively impact emotion and behavior (Dobson and Dozois, 2001). Such an emphasis, along with CBT's reliance on Kant's (1781/1929) concept of “schemas” (Dozois and Beck, 2011), reveals an ontological worldview based on elemental realism (i.e., mechanism) and mind–body dualism, as well as a focus on content rather than function (O'Donohue and Chin, 2022). These aspects highlight CBT's detachment from the behavioral and contextual roots of first- and third-wave approaches.

ACT is based on functional contextualism, a scientific philosophy rooted in Skinner's radical behaviorism and first-wave behavior analytical principles (O'Donohue and Chin, 2022). Functional contextualism assumes a monistic stance, wherein private events (i.e., thinking, feeling, paying attention) and overt behavior are ontologically alike. Therapeutic work within ACT generally focuses on the function of behavior—either private or overt—within its context. The morphology of behavior (e.g., thought content) is not usually of primary importance (Hayes et al., 2012).

3 Discussion

The worldviews underlying CBT and ACT constitute divergent perspectives on human behavior and, as a result, should orient psychotherapy in different directions (Marica, 2015). This may manifest in dissimilar views on what may count as clinically relevant behavior and mechanisms of change, ultimately leading to different case formulations. More pertinent to this discussion, such divergent worldviews should result in different conceptualizations of mindfulness and its so-called mechanisms of action, which may be reflected in the way mindfulness is integrated into clinical practice.

Mindfulness is almost synonymous with third-wave approaches. The term “mindfulness” is often presented within the ACT literature as a middle-level term (i.e., a non-technical term) (O'Donohue and Chin, 2022). Nonetheless, from a functional contextualist perspective, mindfulness can be largely conceptualized as a set of behaviors or skills to be learned (e.g., paying attention, observing rather than judging) (Kohlenberg et al., 2009). As a therapeutic resource, mindfulness is also congruent with therapeutic targets within ACT. For example, the implementation of mindfulness seeks to change the way clients relate to thoughts/emotions without necessarily modifying them. In behavioral analytic terms, it seeks to alter the eliciting and/or evoking functions of private events that may narrow an individual's behavioral repertoire and/or interfere with valued action (Hayes et al., 2012; Wilson et al., 2012). Participation in mindfulness-based interventions has been associated with a myriad of benefits (e.g., reduced psychopathology, emotion regulation, and positive reappraisal), which have been attributed to a small set of mechanisms of change (or learned skills), such as decentering (Garland et al., 2015; Grabovac et al., 2011; Shapiro et al., 2006).

I contend that the implementation of mindfulness within CBT conflicts with the philosophical assumptions underlying CBT. First, as noted by Beshai (2024) and others (Beck, 1970), CBT's philosophical assumptions postulate that change in thought content is essential for change in behavior and emotion. CBT clients are routinely taught to critically assess their beliefs to identify potential maladaptive cognitions; when distancing from thoughts is promoted, it is done to change thought content (Dozois and Beck, 2011). As discussed above, however, mindfulness is implemented within ACT on the assumption that private events (e.g., thoughts) do not need to be altered for change in emotion or behavior to occur (Germer et al., 2016). Rather, the practice of mindfulness is meant to promote decentering from private events, which often leads to reduced suffering and facilitate desired behavior change (Germer et al., 2016). Second, CBT embraces a content-oriented view of the self, believed to be comprised of cognitive structures (e.g., core beliefs). In contrast, the Buddhist philosophy underlying mindfulness contends that the self is an illusion (i.e., anatta) (Germer et al., 2016); this is consistent with functional contextualism's (and radical behaviorism's) view of the self, conceptualized as a behavioral repertoire rather than an individual entity (Wilson et al., 2012).

In summary, the ultimate question posed here is whether mindfulness can be assimilated within CBT in a way that is consistent with CBT's underlying philosophical assumptions, that is, whether “theoretically consistent eclecticism” is possible (Dryden, 1987). I don't think it is, given that what mindfulness is (Germer et al., 2016) seems to challenge CBT's fundamental propositions. Therefore, although cognitive behavior therapies share a variety of techniques and strategies, I do not think “technical eclecticism” is possible in this case (Lazarus, 1995).

Author contributions

AA-C: Conceptualization, Writing – original draft, Writing – review & editing.

Funding

The author(s) declare that no financial support was received for the research and/or publication of this article.

Conflict of interest

The author declares that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Generative AI statement

The author(s) declare that no Gen AI was used in the creation of this manuscript.

Publisher's note

All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article, or claim that may be made by its manufacturer, is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.

References

Beck, A. T. (1970). Cognitive therapy: nature and relation to behavior therapy. Behav. Ther. 1, 184–200. doi: 10.1016/S0005-7894(70)80030-2

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Beck, A. T., Rush, A. J., Shaw, B. F., and Emery, G. (1979). Cognitive Therapy of Depression. New York: Guilford Press.

Google Scholar

Beshai, S. (2024). Mindfulness and CBT: a conceptual integration bridging ancient wisdom and modern cognitive theories of psychopathology. Front. Psychol. 15:1489798. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2024.1489798

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Dobson, K. S., and Dozois, D. J. (2001). “Historical and philosophical bases of the cognitive–behavioral tradition,” in Handbook of Cognitive-Behavioral Therapies (2nd edn), ed. K. S. Dobson (New York: Guilford Press), 3–39.

Google Scholar

Dozois, D. J. A., and Beck, A. T. (2011). “Cognitive therapy,” in Acceptance and mindfulness in cognitive behavior therapy: Understanding and applying the new therapies, eds. J. D. Herbert, and E. M. Forman (New York: John Wiley and Sons, Inc.), 26–56. doi: 10.1002/9781118001851.ch2

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Dryden, W. (1987). RET as a Theoretically Consistent form of Eclectic Therapy. Current Issues in Rational-Emotive Therapy (Psychology Revivals). London: Routledge.

Google Scholar

Garland, E. L., Farb, N. A. R., Goldin, P., and Fredrickson, B. L. (2015). Mindfulness broadens awareness and builds eudaimonic meaning: a process model of mindful positive emotion regulation. Psychol. Inq. 26, 293–314. doi: 10.1080/1047840X.2015.1064294

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Germer, C., Siegel, R. D., and Fulton, P. R. (2016). Mindfulness and Psychotherapy, Second Edition (Second ed.). London: Guilford Publications.

Google Scholar

Grabovac, A. D., Lau, M. A., and Willett, B. R. (2011). Mechanisms of mindfulness: a buddhist psychological model. Mindfulness 2, 154–166. doi: 10.1007/s12671-011-0054-5

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Hayes, S. C. (2004). Acceptance and commitment therapy, relational frame theory, and the third wave of behavioral and cognitive therapies. Behav. Ther. 35, 639–665. doi: 10.1016/S0005-7894(04)80013-3

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Hayes, S. C., Barnes-Holmes, D., and Wilson, K. G. (2012). Contextual Behavioral Science: Creating a science more adequate to the challenge of the human condition. J. Contextual Behav. Sci. 1, 1–16. doi: 10.1016/j.jcbs.2012.09.004

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Kabat-Zinn, J. (2003). Mindfulness-based interventions in context: past, present, and future. Clin. Psychol.: Sci. Pract. 10, 144–156. doi: 10.1093/clipsy.bpg016

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Kant, I. (1781/1929). Critique of Pure Reason. (N. K. Smith, Trans.). London, England: Macmillan. (Original work published 1781).

Google Scholar

Kohlenberg, R. J., Tsai, M., Kanter, J. W., and Parker, C. R. (2009). “Self and mindfulness,” in A guide to Functional Analytic Psychotherapy. Awareness, courage, love, and behaviorism (Springer Science and Business Media), 103–130. doi: 10.1007/978-0-387-09787-9_1

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Lazarus, A. A. (1995). Different types of eclecticism and integration: let's be aware of the dangers. J. Psychother. Integr. 5, 27–39. doi: 10.1037/h0101169

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Marica, M. A. (2015). Philosophical assumptions of psychotherapeutic paradigms. Procedia-Soc. Behav. Sci. 180, 383–388. doi: 10.1016/j.sbspro.2015.02.133

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

O'Donohue, W., and Chin, F. T. (2022). “Meta-science and the three waves of cognitive behavior therapy: three distinct sets of commitments,” in Behavior Therapy: First, Second, and Third Waves, eds. W. O'Donohue, and A. Masuda (Cham: Springer International Publishing), 53–81. doi: 10.1007/978-3-031-11677-3_3

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Shapiro, S. L., Carlson, L. E., Astin, J. A., and Freedman, B. (2006). Mechanisms of mindfulness. J. Clin. Psychol. 62, 373–386. doi: 10.1002/jclp.20237

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Wilson, K. G., Bordieri, M., Whiteman, K., and Slater, R. M. (2012). “The self and mindfulness,” in The Self and Perspective Taking: Contributions and Applications from Modern Behavioral Science, eds. L. McHUgh, and I. Stewart (Oakland: New Harbinger Publications), 181–198.

Google Scholar

Keywords: mindfulness, CBT, ACT, functional contextualism, philosophical assumptions, psychotherapy

Citation: Aguirre-Camacho A (2025) Commentary: Mindfulness and CBT: a conceptual integration bridging ancient wisdom and modern cognitive theories of psychopathology. Front. Psychol. 16:1565835. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2025.1565835

Received: 23 January 2025; Accepted: 04 April 2025;
Published: 22 April 2025.

Edited by:

Vanessa Caridad Somohano, United States Department of Veterans Affairs, United States

Reviewed by:

María Xesús Froxán Parga, Autonomous University of Madrid, Spain

Copyright © 2025 Aguirre-Camacho. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Aldo Aguirre-Camacho, YWxkby5hZ3VpcnJlQHVuaXZlcnNpZGFkZXVyb3BlYS5lcw==; YWxkby5hZ3VpcnJlLmNAZ21haWwuY29t

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.