Skip to main content

ORIGINAL RESEARCH article

Front. Psychol., 25 March 2022
Sec. Quantitative Psychology and Measurement

A Statistical Explanation of the Dunning–Kruger Effect

\nJan R. MagnusJan R. Magnus1Anatoly A. Peresetsky
Anatoly A. Peresetsky2*
  • 1Department of Econometrics and Data Science, Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam, Tinbergen Institute, Amsterdam, Netherlands
  • 2Department of Applied Economics, Faculty of Economic Sciences, Higher School of Economics (HSE University), Moscow, Russia

An explanation of the Dunning–Kruger effect is provided which does not require any psychological explanation, because it is derived as a statistical artifact. This is achieved by specifying a simple statistical model which explicitly takes the (random) boundary constraints into account. The model fits the data almost perfectly.

JEL Classification: A22; C24; C91; D84; D91; I21

Introduction

The Dunning–Kruger (DK) effect states that people with low ability tend to overestimate their ability. This hypothetical cognitive bias was first described in Kruger and Dunning (1999) and, if true, it is potentially important and dangerous, because it means that people of low ability not only perform tasks poorly but (even worse) that they think that they perform these tasks well. Dunning and Kruger claim that the reason for this bias is that people of low ability are not good in seeing and judging themselves (a deficit in metacognitive skills). A closely related effect, also important but arguably less dangerous, is that people of high ability tend to underestimate their ability. This second effect, although not discussed in Kruger and Dunning (1999), is often also associated with their names. The DK effect and Dunning and Kruger's explanation of it has been discussed and challenged extensively.

In their original article, Kruger and Dunning (1999) tested undergraduate students enrolled in various psychology courses at Cornell University for their ability in humor, logical reasoning, and English grammar. After the test they asked the students to assess their performance in the test. The students were then split in four groups according to their actual test scores. Calculating the average perceived ability in each group, Dunning and Kruger obtained Figure 1. The accuracy of the prediction was high in the top group and low in the bottom group, and the prediction in the bottom group was highly overestimated.

FIGURE 1
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 1. Perceived ability to recognize humor as a function of actual test performance (from Kruger and Dunning, 1999).

The Kruger–Dunning article raises two questions. First, is there a DK effect? And second, is the explanation provided by Dunning and Kruger correct?

There has been both criticism and support. Most studies recognize that there is a DK effect and provide a psychological explanation, sometimes agreeing, sometimes disagreeing with Kruger and Dunning's metacognitive explanations; see Ehrlinger et al. (2008), Schlosser et al. (2013), Williams et al. (2013), Sullivan et al. (2018), West and Eaton (2019), Gabbard and Romanelli (2021), and Mariana et al. (2021); and partial responses in Kruger and Dunning (2002), Dunning et al. (2003, 2004), and Dunning (2011).

Meeran et al. (2016) explained the DK effect based on the anchoring and adjustment heuristic, while Jansen et al. (2021) replicated two of Dunning and Kruger's studies using a sample of 4,000 participants. Their model for the probability of a correct answer is an extension of the one-parameter item response theory (IRT) model, known as the Rasch model (Embretson and Reise, 2013). By developing a rational model of self-assessment, they showed that the DK effect can be produced by two psychological mechanisms.

But there has also been much criticism and this criticism typically relies on a statistical rather than a psychological explanation of the DK effect. The attack on Dunning and Kruger was initiated by Krueger and Mueller (2002), who suggested a regression better-than-average approach which is parsimonious and “does not require mediation by third variables, such as metacognitive insights into one's own problem-solving abilities1.” Their approach is based on two empirical facts. First, it is well-known that people tend to overestimate their performance. Most people think they drive better than average (Svenson, 1981). In a survey of engineers, 42% thought their work ranked in the top 5% among their peers (Zenger, 1992); and in a survey of college professors, 94% thought they performed “above average” (Cross, 1977). Second, the slope in the linear regression of estimated performance on actual performance is not equal but less than one. This phenomenon is called “regression to the mean” and has been known since Galton (1886) studied the relationship between the height of sons and fathers. Combining these two facts leads to the regression better-than-average approach, and it explains the asymmetry of the DK effect: overestimation in the bottom quartile and underestimation in the upper quartile. A more precise formulation of the regression better-than-average approach was provided in the noise-plus-bias model (Burson et al., 2006).

The DK effect also occurs in different environments, for example the problem of face recognition. This situation was recently investigated by Kramer et al. (2022), who found imperfect correlation between self-insight and competence.

Several studies attempted to provide statistical explanations. Ackerman et al. (2002) demonstrated that pictures like Figure 1 can be obtained with simulated data using two random variables with small correlation r = 0.19 (one representing objective knowledge and the other self-reported knowledge). Ackerman and Wolman (2007) studied post-test self-estimates of “Raven” performance, using a scatter plot with a regression line representing the effect of self-estimated Raven performance on Raven's actual performance. They found a correlation less than 1 and also the slope of the regression line was less than 1, demonstrating the DK effect. Nuhfer et al. (2016) used simulated random variables with correlation less then 1 and various graphical representations of the data to illustrate the DK effect. Krajc and Ortmann (2008) assumed a nonsymmetric J-distribution for the talent of the undergraduates studied by Kruger and Dunning (1999), which leads to more students in the left tail of the students' ability distribution, resulting in the DK effect. McIntosh et al. (2019) experimented with movement and memory tasks, and concluded that the DK effect exists as an empirical phenomenon. But they disagreed with the explanation that poor insight is the reason for overestimation among the unskilled. Gignac and Zajenkowski (2020), using a sample of general community participants, tested the validity of the DK effect with the Glejser test of heteroskedasticity and by nonlinear (quadratic) regression, and found much less evidence in favor of the DK effect than Kruger and Dunning (1999).

Our explanation of the DK effect is based on the fact that the data are bounded. This feature of the data has not received much attention, with the exception of Burson et al. (2006), who concluded that the boundary restriction “is an important concern that should be addressed in future research;” and Krajc and Ortmann (2008), who noted that students in the bottom quartile can only make optimistic errors placing themselves into a higher quartile, while students in the top quartile can only make pessimistic errors placing themselves in a lower quartile.

The remark by Krajc and Ortmann provides the essence of our story. Consider a brilliant student who typically scores 95 or 99 points out of 100. Because of the bound at 100, there is not much room to predict higher than her ability but there is plenty of room to predict lower, so she would typically predict 85 or 90, thus underestimating her score. The same happens at the bottom end of the scale, where there is a bound of 0 and a student would typically overestimate. This simple observation is the basis of our model.

We shall employ data on 665 undergraduates at the International College of Economics and Finance of the Higher School of Economics in Moscow, who predict their grade on a 0–100 scale for a statistics exam. We use a simple statistical model which explicitly specifies the (random) boundary constraints. This model fits the data almost perfectly. There is thus no need for a psychological explanation of the DK effect: it is a statistical artifact.

The remainder of this article is organized as follows. First, we present and discuss the data. Next, we present a simple one-parameter model that accounts for censuring, and show that this model explains the DK effect, although not yet perfectly. Then, we extend this simple model to a more realistic three-parameter model where the bounds are random rather than fixed, and present the results based on this extended model. The fit is now near-perfect. The final section concludes and provides a tentative explanation of why it is that people still believe the psychological underpinnings of the DK effect. A mathematical Appendix contains the statistical theory underlying the required conditional expectation functions.

The Data

We shall study the DK effect by comparing exam results with predictions of these results, and, in this section, we describe the data in some detail.

The International College of Economics and Finance (ICEF) in Moscow was established in 1997 jointly by the London School of Economics and Political Science (LSE) in London and the Higher School of Economics (HSE) in Moscow. The college offers a four-year bachelor's program, which is considered to be one the top programs in economics in Russia. Each year about 200 students enter the program, typically immediately after high school. In their first year the students follow, among other subjects, a course called Statistics-1, and in their second year they follow Statistics-2. Both courses are compulsory. Our data are obtained from four cohorts of students following Statistics-2 in the period 2016–2019. In total, after removing students who took the course for a second time, 665 students remained who took this course and provided a prediction.

In Statistics-2 students take three exams every year, at the end of October (exam 1), the end of December (exam 2), and the end of March (exam 3). The exams are written exams, not multiple choice, and each exam consists of two parts (80 min each) with a ten min break between the two parts. The level of the exam questions is the same in the two parts. To avoid cheating, students are not allowed to leave and come back during each part of the exam. At the end of part 1 and at the end of part 2 the examiner collects each student's work. Each part is graded out of 50 points.

At the end of the first part of each of the three exams each student is invited to predict (out of 100) their grade for this exam (the two parts together). When writing down the prediction, students know the questions and their answers in part 1, but not yet the questions of part 2. To encourage students to provide a prediction and try their best, a bonus is promised as follows. If the difference between the prediction and the grade is less than or equal to 3 in absolute value, then one bonus point is added to the grade. For example, if the prediction is 49 and the grade is 52, then the grade for this exam is marked up to 53. This procedure had to be and has been approved by the ICEF administration. As a result of the procedure and the possibility of a bonus, the response rate was extremely high (97%). The idea of giving each student an incentive to express their opinion was successfully used earlier in experiments by Blackwell (2010) and Magnus and Peresetsky (2018). Each of the two parts typically consists of four problems (not multiple choice). Each problem was graded by the same class teacher, thus improving the objectivity of the grades (see Meeran et al., 2016).

In the current study, we take data only from the second exam in each year. This is the most representative of the three exams, because in the first exam students may not yet be familiar with the benefits of a careful prediction, and in the third exam there is the problem that smart (or risk averse) students utilize the bonus to maximize the probability that their grade is ≥25, which is a requirement for passing the course. The student's optimal strategy is then to choose their prediction between 21 and 27 in which case a grade of 24 would be marked up to 25. Many students actually use this strategy which leads to an overrepresentation of 24 and 25 in the sample of the third exam.

In each year t we thus have one grade and one prediction per student. Let us define

                          xit:actual grade of studentiin yeart,                      yitraw:raw (unadjusted) prediction of student                                 i in yeart,dit=yitraw-xit:difference between raw prediction and                                 actual grade.

In each year we can average over students and this gives

x̄t=1nti=1ntxit,  ȳtraw=1nti=1ntyitraw,  d̄t=1nti=1ntdit,

where nt denotes the number of students in year t.

We don't want to use the raw predictions directly, because of the variation in the student cohort's strengths and in the difficulty of the exam over the years. To filter out these variations we define an adjusted prediction

yit=yitraw-d̄t    (1)

with the property that ȳt=x̄t, so that in each year the average prediction equals the average grade.

In Table 1, we present a summary of the data. Per year we provide the number of students nt, the average exam grade x̄t, the average raw prediction ȳtraw, and the difference d̄t between these two averages. The difference dit varies a lot within each year, as shown by the standard deviation τt in the last column. The second exam in 2017 turned out particularly difficult (or the cohort was less motivated) leading to relatively low grades.

TABLE 1
www.frontiersin.org

Table 1. Descriptive statistics (means) of the data.

Fixed Bounds

As a first attempt to model the predictions we propose the following equation:

yitraw=αt+xit+ζit,    (2)

where the constant αt may vary per year to adjust for (over)confidence and the difficulty of the exam, and the errors ζit are assumed to be independent and identically distributed as N(0,σζ2). Writing Equation (2) in deviation form gives

yitraw-ȳtraw=(xit-x̄t)+(ζit-ζ̄t).

The adjusted prediction is given by

yit=yitraw-d̄t=yitraw-ȳtraw+x̄t,

which leads to the simple equation

yit=xit+ϵit,  ϵit=ζit-ζ̄t.

After adjustment, the year plays no longer any role, so we may simplify the notation and write

yi=xi+ϵi.    (3)

The difference between the (adjusted) prediction yi and the grade xi is thus random noise, and the only thing to estimate is the variance of that noise.

This first attempt does not, however, take into account that the left-hand side of Equation (3) is bounded by 0 ≤ yi ≤ 100, so that the right-hand side is similarly bounded. The right-hand side xi + ϵi does not automatically fulfill this constraint; it has to be censored to do so. The basic censuring model in statistics and econometrics is the tobit model introduced by Tobin (1958). In the tobit model, we introduce a latent (unobserved) random variable yi* defined as

yi*=xi+ϵi,    (4)

where the ϵi are independent and identically distributed as N(0,σϵ2). Then, we model yi as

yi={0, if yi*0,yi*, if 0<yi*100,100, if yi*>100.    (5)

This is the standard tobit model, double-censured due to the fact that we have both a lower and an upper bound.

Model Equation (5) is more realistic than model Equation (3), and once we have estimated σϵ2 we can compute the expectation h(xi) = E(yi) as given in Equation (9) in the Appendix.

Estimating σϵ by maximum likelihood (ML) gives σ^ϵ=12.5 with standard error 0.35. In Figure 2, we plot the expectation h(xi) = E(yi) for four values of σϵ: 10, 20, 30, and 40 (and 0, which is the 45° line). Figure 2 already demonstrates how the two bounds force the expectation function in the direction of the DK effect in Figure 1.

FIGURE 2
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 2. Expectation functions for the one-parameter censored tobit model for σϵ = 0, 10, 20, 30, 40.

But the fixed-bound model is not yet completely satisfactory due to the fact that it is not realistic to assume that yi = 0 if yi*0 or that yi = 100 if yi*>100: no student predicts 0 (however, poor) or 100 (however, brilliant). This leads to the random-bounds model presented in the next section.

Random Bounds

A more realistic model is given by

yi={|ui|, if y*0,yi*, if 0<y*100,100|vi|, if y*>100,    (6)

where we assume that ϵi, ui, and vi are independent and identically distributed, that they are independent of each other, and that all three are normally distributed as N(0,σϵ2), N(0,σu2), and N(0,σv2), respectively.

When applying Equation (6) there is one further complication, namely that the lower bound must not only satisfy |ui| > 0, but also |ui| < 100, while the upper bound must not only satisfy 100 − |vi| < 100, but also 100−|vi| > 0. Hence, we must require that |ui| <100 and |vi| < 100. This will be “almost” true in most applications. For example, we have Pr(|ui| < 100) = 99.9 and 95.5 for σu = 30 and 50, respectively. We deal formally with this situation by considering the conditional expectation function

h(xi)=E(yi|0<yi<100).    (7)

We derive the mathematical expression for this conditional expectation function in the Appendix, resulting in Equation (8).

The ML estimates are presented in Table 2, first without restriction and then under the restriction that σu = σv. The estimates take on reasonable values and they are estimated rather precisely. The restriction σu = σv is not rejected by a Wald (p-value 0.061) or likelihood ratio (p-value 0.412) test.

TABLE 2
www.frontiersin.org

Table 2. Maximum likelihood estimates for the three-parameter model (standard errors in parentheses).

In Figure 3, we present the conditional expectation functions based on the ML estimates in Table 2. As expected, there is not much difference between the restricted (σu = σv) and the unrestricted plot, and both plots clearly show the DK effect based purely on the fact that the observations are bounded. The observed S-shape is very similar to the empirical plots reported in the literature: overestimation for the weak students (“unskilled and unaware of it” in the words of Dunning and Kruger) and underestimation for the strong students.

FIGURE 3
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 3. Conditional expectation functions for the three-parameter censored tobit model based on ML and nonparametric estimates.

As a benchmark comparison we also provide a nonparametric plot based on locally-weighted scatter plot smoothing (lowess) with bandwidth 0.2. The ML plots are close to the nonparametric plot when x is small but not so close when x is large. This is caused by the fact that only 14% of the observations fall in the interval x>60.

We can try and fit our three parameters such that the conditional expectation function is “as close as possible” to the nonparametric plot. If we employ nonlinear least squares (NLS), then we find σ^ϵ=29.6(0.70), σ^u=0, and σ^v=33.1(2.13). The NLS plot in Figure 4 is now very close to the nonparametric plot. In fact, the shape of the conditional expectation function is quite robust against changes in the three parameters. If we fix the parameters at σϵ = 30, σu = 10, and σv = 35; or at σϵ = 25, σu = 15, and σv = 40, then we obtain conditional expectations that are almost indistinguishable from Figure 4.

FIGURE 4
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 4. Conditional expectation functions for the three-parameter censored tobit model based on NLS and nonparametric estimates.

Discussion and Conclusions

In this article, we have attempted to provide an explanation of the DK effect which does not require any psychological explanation. By specifying a simple statistical model which explicitly takes the (random) boundary constraints into account, we achieve a near-perfect fit, thus demonstrating that the DK effect is a statistical artifact. In other words: there is an effect, but it does not reflect human nature.

Many authors writing on the DK effect refer to regression to the mean (RM) as if this were a well-known statistical fact, not requiring further justification, while in fact the mechanism underlying the RM effect needs to be explained in each application. A “psychological” explanation of the RM effect was suggested by Wellman (1940), though instantly criticized by Goodenough and Maurer (1940).

Before we discuss the RM effect further, let's point out a common confusion in its interpretation. Suppose we have data on two variables x and y, say (x1, y1), …, (xn, yn). Then we can compute the sample correlation rxy. We can also regress y on x, estimating α and β from the regression yi = α+βxi + ϵi. The least-squares estimator of β can be written as β^=rxysy/sx, where sx2 and sy2 are the sample variances of x and y, respectively. The term “imperfect correlation” is used to indicate that 0 < rxy < 1. Regression to the mean on the other hand is equivalent to 0<β^<1. Confusion arises because the two conditions are not the same. When rxy = 1 and sy < sx, then β^<1 so that there is regression to the mean in spite of the fact that rxy = 1. Vice versa, when β^=1 and sy > sx, then r < 1 so that there is no regression to the mean in spite of the fact that rxy < 1.

The RM effect was first described by sir Francis Galton in 1886. Galton compared the heights of parents and children and found that if the parents are tall, then the children are, on average, shorter than their parents, and that if the parents are short, the children are, on average, taller. He explained the RM effect by assuming that there are two genes responsible for height: one is inherited from the parents, and the other reflects the average height in the population. The height of the children can then be represented as a weighted average of the two.

Galton's explanation was appealing and brilliant, given the knowledge on genetics at that time. Today we know that height is determined by about 700 genes in approximately 180 locations in the chromosomes (Allen et al., 2010), and the RM effect can be explained in a probabilistic framework from the fact that of each pair of chromosomes one is inherited from the mother and one from the father.

But there could be bounds here too, not “hard” bounds (like 0 and 100 in exams) but “soft” bounds (say, 130 and 230 cm). Suppose the inherited height equals the average height of the parents with some random shock. If the inherited height is too high or too low then the probability of prenatal death is high, which explains (at least in part) the RM effect as a statistical artifact caused by these bounds. In fact, our presented theory based on boundaries can explain the RM effect in many areas, not just students' grades or children's heights.

Finally, why do people still believe in psychological explanations of the DK effect? The literature abounds with characters who overestimate themselves and with wisdoms about how stupid it is to think you are clever. Shakespeare writes: “The fool doth think he is wise, but the wise man knows himself to be a fool” (As You Like It), and Alexander Pope warns: “A little learning is a dangerous thing” (An Essay on Criticism), in the same spirit as Confucius' maxim: “Real knowledge is to know the extent of one's ignorance.”

Perhaps the explanation for the persistence of this belief is: We have two facts, both true. First, we actually observe the DK effect. Second, if we compare people's ideas about their own ability with objective measurements of this ability, we find that people tend to overestimate themselves. Then, what is more natural than to think that these two statements are related to each other, in fact, that one causes the other? The problem is, they aren't.

Data Availability Statement

The original contributions presented in the study are included in the article/supplementary material, further inquiries can be directed to the corresponding author/s.

Ethics Statement

Ethical review and approval was not required for the study on human participants in accordance with the local legislation and institutional requirements. Written informed consent from the patients/ participants or patients/participants legal guardian/next of kin was not required to participate in this study in accordance with the national legislation and the institutional requirements.

Author Contributions

All authors listed have made a substantial, direct, and intellectual contribution to the work and approved it for publication.

Conflict of Interest

The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Publisher's Note

All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article, or claim that may be made by its manufacturer, is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.

Acknowledgments

We are grateful to two referees and to the editor for their positive and constructive comments.

Footnotes

1. ^To avoid confusion: Joachim Krueger of Brown University and Justin Kruger of Cornell University are two different people.

References

Ackerman, P. L., Beier, M. E., and Bowen, K. R. (2002). What we really know about our abilities and our knowledge. Pers. Individual Diff. 33, 587–605. doi: 10.1016/S0191-8869(01)00174-X

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ackerman, P. L., and Wolman, S. D. (2007). Determinants and validity of self-estimates of abilities and self-concept measures. J. Exp. Psychol. Appl. 13, 57–78. doi: 10.1037/1076-898X.13.2.57

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Allen, H. L., Estrada, K., Lettre, G., Berndt, S. I., Weedon, M. N., and Rivadeneira, F. (2010). Hundreds of variants clustered in genomic loci and biological pathways affect human height. Nature 467, 832–838. doi: 10.1038/nature09410

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Blackwell, C. (2010). Rational expectations in the classroom: a learning activity. J. Econ. Educ. 10, 1–6.

Google Scholar

Burson, K. A., Larrick, R. P., and Klayman, J. (2006). Skilled or unskilled, but still unaware of it: how perceptions of difficulty drive miscalibration in relative comparisons. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 90, 60–77. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.90.1.60

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Cross, P. (1977). Not can but will college teaching be improved? New Direct. High. Educ. 17, 1–15. doi: 10.1002/he.36919771703

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Dunning, D. (2011). The Dunning–Kruger effect: on being ignorant of one's own ignorance. Adv. Exp. Soc. Psychol. 44, 247–296. doi: 10.1016/B978-0-12-385522-0.00005-6

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Dunning, D., Heath, C., and Suls, J. (2004). Flawed self-assessment: Implications for health, education, and the workplace. Psychol. Sci. Publ. Interest 5, 69–106. doi: 10.1111/j.1529-1006.2004.00018.x

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Dunning, D., Johnson, K., Ehrlinger, J.M., and Kruger, J. (2003). Why people fail to recognize their own incompetence. Curr. Direct. Psychol. Sci. 12, 83–87. doi: 10.1111/1467-8721.01235

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ehrlinger, J., Johnson, K., Banner, M., Dunning, D., and Kruger, J. (2008). Why the unskilled are unaware: further explorations of (absent) self-insight among the incompetent. Org. Behav. Hum. Decis. Process. 105, 98–121. doi: 10.1016/j.obhdp.2007.05.002

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Embretson, S. E., and Reise, S. P. (2013). Item Response Theory. New York, NY: Psychology Press. doi: 10.4324/9781410605269

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gabbard, T., and Romanelli, F. (2021). The accuracy of health professions students' self-assessments compared to objective measures of competence. Am. J. Pharmaceutical Educ. 85, 8405. doi: 10.5688/ajpe8405

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Galton, F. (1886). Regression towards mediocrity in hereditary stature. J. Anthropol. Inst. Great Brit. Ireland 15, 264–263. doi: 10.2307/2841583

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gignac, G. E., and Zajenkowski, M. (2020). The Dunning–Kruger effect is (mostly) a statistical artefact: valid approaches to testing the hypothesis with individual differences data. Intelligence 80, 101449. doi: 10.1016/j.intell.2020.101449

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Goodenough, F. L., and Maurer, K. M. (1940). The relative potency of the nursery school and the statistical laboratory in boosting the IQ. J. Educ. Psychol. 31, 541–549. doi: 10.1037/h0055395

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Jansen, R. A., Rafferty, A. N., and Griffiths, T. L. (2021). A rational model of the Dunning–Kruger effect supports insensitivity to evidence in low performers. Nat. Hum. Behav. 5, 756–763. doi: 10.1038/s41562-021-01057-0

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Krajc, M., and Ortmann, A. (2008). Are the unskilled really that unaware? an alternative explanation. J. Econ. Psychol. 29, 724–738. doi: 10.1016/j.joep.2007.12.006

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kramer, R. S. S., Gous, G., Mireku, M. O., and Ward, R. (2022). Metacognition during unfamiliar face matching. Brit. J. Psychol. doi: 10.1111/bjop.12553

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Krueger, J., and Mueller, R. A. (2002). Unskilled, unaware, or both? The better-than-average heuristic and statistical regression predict errors in estimates of own performance. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 82, 180–188. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.82.2.180

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kruger, J., and Dunning, D. (1999). Unskilled and unaware of it: how difficulties in recognizing one's own incompetence lead to inflated self-assessments. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 77, 1121–1134. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.77.6.1121

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kruger, J., and Dunning, D. (2002). Unskilled and unaware — but why? a reply to Krueger and Mueller (2002). J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 82, 189–192. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.82.2.189

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Magnus, J. R., and Peresetsky, A. A. (2018). Grade expectations: rationality and overconfidence. Front. Psychol. Quant. Psychol. Meas. 8, 2346. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2017.02346

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Mariana, V. C., Coutinho, J. T., Alsuwaidi, A. S. M., and Couchman, J. J. (2021). Dunning–Kruger effect: intuitive errors predict overconfidence on the cognitive reflection test. Front. Psychol. 12, 603225. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2021.603225

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

McIntosh, R. D., Fowler, E. A., Lyu, T., and Sala, S. D. (2019). Wise up: clarifying the role of metacognition in the Dunning–Kruger Effect. J. Exp. Psychol. Gen. 148, 1882–1897. doi: 10.1037/xge0000579

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Meeran, S., Goodwin, P., and Yalabik, B. (2016). A parsimonious explanation of observed biases when forecasting one's own performance. Int. J. Forecast. 32, 112–120. doi: 10.1016/j.ijforecast.2015.05.001

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Nuhfer, E., Cogan, C., Fleisher, S., Gaze, E., and Wirth, K. (2016). Random number simulations reveal how random noise affects the measurements and graphical portrayals of self-assessed competency. Numeracy 9, 4. doi: 10.5038/1936-4660.9.1.4

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Schlosser, T., Dunning, D., Johnson, K. L, and Kruger, J. (2013). How unaware are the unskilled? Empirical tests of the ‘signal extraction' counterexplanation for the Dunning–Kruger effect in self-evaluation of performance. J. Econ. Psychol. 39, 85–100. doi: 10.1016/j.joep.2013.07.004

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Sullivan, P. J., Ragogna, M., and Dithurbide, L. (2018). An investigation into the Dunning–Kruger effect in sport coaching. Int. J. Sport Exer. Psychol. 17, 1–9. doi: 10.1080/1612197X.2018.1444079

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Svenson, O. (1981). Are we all less risky and more skillful than our fellow drivers? Acta Psychol. 47, 143–148. doi: 10.1016/0001-6918(81)90005-6

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Tobin, J. (1958). Estimation of relationships for limited dependent variables. Econometrica 26, 24–36. doi: 10.2307/1907382

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Wellman, B. L. (1940). “Iowa studies on the effects of schooling,” in The Thirty-Ninth Yearbook of the National Society for the Study of Education: Intelligence: Its Nature and Nurture. Part 2, Original Studies and Experiments., ed G. M. Whipple (Bloomington, IL: Public School Publishing Co.), 377–399.

Google Scholar

West, K., and Eaton, A. A. (2019). Prejudiced and unaware of it: evidence for the Dunning–Kruger model in the domains of racism and sexism. Pers. Ind. Diff., 146, 111–119. doi: 10.1016/j.paid.2019.03.047

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Williams, E. F., Dunning, D., and Kruger, J. (2013). The hobgoblin of consistency: Algorithmic judgment strategies underlie inflated self-assessments of performance. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 104, 976–994. doi: 10.1037/a0032416

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Zenger, T. R. (1992). Why do employers only reward extreme performance? examining the relationships among performance, pay, and turnover. Admin. Sci. Quart. 37, 198–219. doi: 10.2307/2393221

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Mathematical Appendix

Consider the censored model Equation (6), where we write y*, y, and x instead of yi*, yi, and xi for simplicity. We have

p1=Pr(y*0)=Φ(-xσϵ),p2=Pr(0<y*100)=1-p1-p3,p3=Pr(y*>100)=1-Φ(100-xσϵ),

where Φ denotes the cumulative distribution function of the standard-normal distribution, and

q1=Pr(y0)=Pr(y0|y*>100)·Pr(y*>100)     =Pr(100-σv|v|0)·p3=2p3Φ(-100σv),q2=Pr(0<y100)=1-q1-q3,q3=Pr(y>100)=Pr(y>100|y*0)·Pr(y*0)     =Pr(σu|u|>100)·p1=2p1Φ(-100σu).

Let 0 < t < 100. Then,

G1(t)=Pr(0<y<t|y*0)=Pr(0<σu|u|<t)           =1-2Φ(-tσu),G2(t)=Pr(0<y<t|0<y*100)           =Pr(0<y*<t|0<y*100)           =Pr(0<y*<t)Pr(0<y*<100)=Pr(0<x+σϵϵ<t)p2           =1p2[Φ(t-xσϵ)-Φ(-xσϵ)],G3(t)=Pr(0<y<t|y*>100)=Pr(0<100-σv|v|<t)           =2[Φ(100σv)-Φ(100-tσv)]

with derivatives

g1(t)=2σuϕ(-tσu),g2(t)=1p2σϵϕ(t-xσϵ),g3(t)=2σvϕ(100-tσv),

where ϕ = Φ′ denotes the density of the standard-normal distribution. This gives

m1=0100tg1(t)dt=2σu0100/σusϕ(s)ds      =-2σu0100/σuϕ(s)ds=2σu(ϕ(0)-ϕ(100σu)),m2=0100tg2(t)dt=xp2-x/σϵ(100-x)/σϵϕ(s)ds      +σϵp2-x/σϵ(100-x)/σϵsϕ(s)ds      =xp2(Φ(100-xσϵ)-Φ(-xσϵ))      -σϵp2(ϕ(100-xσϵ)-ϕ(-xσϵ)),m3=0100tg3(t)dt=200-100/σv0ϕ(s)ds      +2σv-100/σv0sϕ(s)ds      =200(Φ(0)-Φ(-100σv))-2σv(ϕ(0)-ϕ(-100σv)).

Letting

F(t)=Pr(0<y<t|0<y<100)         =p1G1(t)+p2G2(t)+p3G3(t)q2

with derivative

f(t)=p1g1(t)+p2g2(t)+p3g3(t)q2,

we thus obtain

0100tf(t)dt=p1m1+p2m2+p3m3q2,    (8)

which provides the expectation in the general case.

In the special case of model Equation (5) we have σu = σv = 0, and hence m1 = 0, m3 = 100, and q2 = 1. This gives the expectation

0100tf(t)dt=p2m2+100p3.    (9)

Keywords: boundary conditions, tobit model, Dunning–Kruger effect, conditional expectation, underestimation and overestimation

Citation: Magnus JR and Peresetsky AA (2022) A Statistical Explanation of the Dunning–Kruger Effect. Front. Psychol. 13:840180. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2022.840180

Received: 20 December 2021; Accepted: 18 February 2022;
Published: 25 March 2022.

Edited by:

Rick Thomas, Georgia Institute of Technology, United States

Reviewed by:

Robin Kramer, University of Lincoln, United Kingdom
Phillip Ackerman, Georgia Institute of Technology, United States

Copyright © 2022 Magnus and Peresetsky. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Anatoly A. Peresetsky, aperesetsky@hse.ru

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.